-
Respectful Paternalism Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2021-04-10 Viki Møller Lyngby Pedersen
A common objection to paternalism concerns its expressive content. Many reject paternalistic policies and actions on the ground that they arguably involve insulting expressions of disrespect toward those subjected to them. The paper challenges this view. It argues that refraining from acting paternalistically can be disrespectful. Specifically, the paper argues that there is a relevant way in which
-
Deflating Parental Rights Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2021-04-01 James G. Dwyer
Perhaps the greatest determinant of individual and societal welfare is who raises children and with what degree of discretion. Philosophers have endeavored in myriad ways to provide normative justification for ascribing a right to be a legal parent and to possess particular legal powers as a parent. This Article shows why they fail and offers an alternative theoretical framework for delimiting parental
-
Conditional Consent Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2021-02-19 Karamvir Chadha
There are two distinct ways for someone to place conditions on their morally valid consent. The first is to place conditions on the moral scope of their consent—whereby they waive some moral claim rights but not others. The second is to conditionally token consent—whereby the condition affects whether they waive any moral claim rights at all. Understanding this distinction helps make progress with
-
The One-System View and Dworkin’s Anti-Archimedean Eliminativism Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2021-02-18 Hillary Nye
Many of Dworkin’s interlocutors saw his ‘one-system view’, according to which law is a branch of morality, as a radical shift. I argue that it is better seen as a different way of expressing his longstanding view that legal theory is an inherently normative endeavor. Dworkin emphasizes that fact and value are separate domains, and one cannot ground claims of one sort in the other domain. On this view
-
What’s the Party Like? The Status of the Political Party in Anti-Defection Jurisdictions Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2021-01-02 Udit Bhatia
This paper explores how political parties should be regulated in jurisdictions with anti-defection laws, which constitutionalise parties’ control over the legislative process. It begins by arguing that parties in such jurisdictions should be understood as neither private organisations nor quasi-public bodies but as legislative entities. Next, it argues that recognising the legislative status of the
-
From Angels to Humans: Law, Coercion, and the Society of Angels Thought Experiment Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2020-12-01 Lucas Miotto
Whether legal systems are necessarily coercive raises normative concerns. Coercion carries a presumption of illegitimacy and a special justificatory burden. If legal systems are necessarily coercive, coerciveness necessarily taints our legal institutions. Traditionally, legal systems have been regarded as contingently coercive. This view is mainly supported by the society of angels thought experiment
-
The Priority of Liberty: An Argument from Social Equality Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2020-10-19 Devon Cass
John Rawls’s thesis that a certain package of basic liberties should be given lexical priority is of great interest for legal and political philosophy, but it has received relatively little defense from Rawls or his supporters. In this paper, I examine three arguments for the thesis: the first is based on the two ‘moral powers’; the second, on the social bases of self-respect; and the third, on a Kantian
-
Rethinking the Use of Statistical Evidence to Prove Causation in Criminal Cases: A Tale of (Im)Probability and Free Will Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2020-07-17 Amit Pundik
Whenever a litigant needs to prove that a certain result was caused in a specific way, what could be more compelling than citing the infinitesimal probability of that result emanating from an alternative natural cause? Contrary to this intuitive position, in the present article, I argue that the contention that a result was due to a certain cause should remain unaffected by statistical evidence of
-
Must Penal Law Be Insulated from Public Influence? Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2020-07-17 Christopher D. Berk
Punishment and democracy appear to exacerbate each other’s worst features. The institutions and moral intuitions used to punish those that break the law can hollow out civic participation, distort the electorate, and undermine core democratic values. Likewise, many have argued the decentralized character of democracy is a key, albeit indirect, cause of increasingly punitive public policies that are
-
The Morality of Treason Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2020-06-26 Cécile Fabre
Treason is one of the most serious legal offences that there are, in most if not all jurisdictions. Laws against treason are rooted in deep-seated moral revulsion about acts which, in the political realm, are paradigmatic examples of breaches of loyalty. Yet, it is not altogether clear what treason consists in: someone’s traitor is often another’s loyalist. In this paper, my aim is twofold: to offer
-
Opportunity Costs Pacifism. Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2020-05-26 James Pattison
If the resources used to wage wars could be spent elsewhere and save more lives, does this mean that wars are unjustified? This article considers this question, which has been largely overlooked by Just War Theorists and pacifists. It focuses on whether the opportunity costs of war lead to a form of pacifism, which it calls ‘Opportunity Costs Pacifism’. The article argues that Opportunity Costs Pacifism
-
Response Retributivism: Defending the Duty to Punish Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2020-05-21 Leora Dahan Katz
This paper offers a response retributive theory of punishment, taking the role of the punisher as well as the relations between the parties to punishment to be central to retributive justification. It proposes that punishment is justified in terms of the ethics of appropriate response, and more precisely, in terms of the duty agents have to dissociate from the devaluation inherent in the culpable wrongdoing
-
Hart, Radbruch and the Necessary Connection Between Law and Morals Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2020-05-17 J. G. Moore
Legal positivism maintains a distinction between law as it is and law as it ought to be. In other words, for positivists, a law can be legally valid even if it is immoral. H. L. A. Hart hoped to defend legal positivism against natural law. This paper analyses Hart’s criticism of Gustav Radbruch, a natural lawyer, before suggesting that Hart’s account of legal positivism gives rise to a logical problem
-
Methodologies of Rule of Law Research: Why Legal Philosophy Needs Empirical and Doctrinal Scholarship Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2020-05-14 Sanne Taekema
Rule of law is a concept that is regularly debated by legal philosophers, often in connection to discussion of the concept of law. In this article, the focus is not on the substance of the conceptual claims, but on the methodologies employed by legal philosophers, investigating seminal articles on the rule of law by Joseph Raz and Jeremy Waldron. I argue that their philosophical argumentations often
-
Correction to: Book Review Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2020-04-30
In the original publication of the article, the corresponding author name was inadvertently left out. The corresponding author name is ‘‘Fergus Green’’. The original article has been corrected.
-
Setting Precedents Without Making Norms? Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2020-04-09 Katharina Stevens
Some authors argue that the rule-of-law ideal gives judges a prima facie duty to provide a determinate formulation of the precedent’s general norm in all their precedent-opinions. I question that claim. I agree that judges have a duty to decide their cases based on reasons and that they should formulate these reasons in their opinions. I also agree that formulations of general norms should be the goal
-
A critique of some recent victim-centered theories of nonconsequentialism Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2020-03-26 S. Matthew Liao, Christian Barry
Recently, Gerhard Øverland and Alec Walen have developed novel and interesting theories of nonconsequentialism. Unlike other nonconsequentialist theories such as the Doctrine of Double Effect (DDE), each of their theories denies that an agent’s mental states are (fundamentally) relevant for determining how stringent their moral reasons are against harming others. Instead, Øverland and Walen seek to
-
State Estoppel Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2020-03-18 Dennis Klimchuk
It is a recurring idea in the history of political philosophy that concepts and doctrines of private law are illuminative of public law and political philosophy. Central among these are contract (especially) and the trust. In this paper, I consider the prospects of a third: estoppel. The public law context in which estoppel is most commonly invoked is criminal law, and there especially in the service
-
The Dilemmas of Constitutional Courts and the Case for a New Design of Kelsenian Institutions Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2020-03-13 Pablo Castillo-Ortiz
Legal and political controversies persist about the performance of Kelsenian-type constitutional courts in democratic systems. One of the reasons is that the design of these institutions cannot easily accommodate simultaneous but conflicting demands for the strong protection of democracy and human rights, judicial independence and constitutional restraint. Challenging the dominant approach to the design
-
Correction to: Against Philosophical Anarchism Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2020-03-09 Fabian Wendt
In the original publication of the article, the corresponding author name was published incorrectly as “And Fabian Wendt”. The correct author name is “Fabian Wendt”. The original article has been corrected.
-
Promises, Rights, and Deontic Control Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2020-03-05 Crescente Molina
This article argues that the notion of a promissory right captures a central feature of the morality of promising which cannot be explained by the notion of promissory obligation alone: the fact that the promisee acquires a full range of control over the promisor’s obligation. It defends two main claims. First, it argues that promissory rights are distinctively grounded in our interest in controlling
-
Against the Managerial State: Preventive Policing as Non-Legal Governance Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2020-03-02 John Lawless
Since at least the 1980s, police departments in the United States have embraced a set of practices that aim, not to enable the prosecution of past criminal activity, but to discourage (or even prevent) people from breaking the law in the first place. It is not clear that these practices effectively lower the crime rate. However, whatever its effect on the crime rate, I argue that preventive policing
-
Against Philosophical Anarchism Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2020-02-26 Fabian Wendt
Philosophical anarchists claim that all states lack political authority and are illegitimate, but that some states are nevertheless morally justified and should not be abolished. I argue that philosophical anarchism is either incoherent or collapses into either statism or political anarchism.
-
Welfare and Freedom: Towards a Semi-Kantian Theory of Private Law Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2020-02-12 Yitzhak Benbaji
The Kantian theory of private law, as Ernest Weinrib and Arthur Ripstein have developed it over the last two decades, is based on a fundamental normative truth, viz., no person is subordinate or superior to another person. Kantians construe any attempt to understand and justify the distribution of the rights-claims and rights-liberties that constitute private law in terms of aggregate welfare and/or
-
Holding Responsible and Taking Responsibility Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2020-02-04 Stephen Bero
In matters of responsibility, there are often two sides to the transaction: one party who holds another responsible, and the other who (ideally) takes responsibility for her conduct. The first side has been closely scrutinized in discussions of the nature of responsibility, due to the influential Strawsonian conjecture that an agent is responsible if and only if it is (in some sense) appropriate to
-
Distributive Justice for Aggressors Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2020-01-31 Patrick Tomlin
The individualist nature of much contemporary just war theory means that we often discuss cases with single attackers. But even if war is best understood in this individualist way, in war combatants often have to make decisions about how to distribute harms among a plurality of aggressors: they must decide whom and how many to harm, and how much to harm them. In this paper, I look at simultaneous multiple
-
Legality ’s Law’s Empire Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2020-01-23 Nevin Johnson
Scott Shapiro’s Legality argues the positivist Planning Theory of law meets the anti-positivist challenge posed by the argument from theoretical disagreements about law (ATD) in Ronald Dworkin’s Law’s Empire. Legality equates theoretical disagreements with what Shapiro calls meta-interpretive disagreements, and then offers a legal theory of meta-interpretation that purportedly accounts for the existence
-
Against the Alienage Condition for Refugeehood Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2020-01-03 Eilidh Beaton
Under the 1951 Refugee Convention, there are two necessary conditions for refugeehood: (1) a well-founded fear of persecution for reasons of race, religion, nationality, membership of a particular social group or political opinion and (2) alienage – that is, being outside of one’s country of nationality or habitual residence. In 1985 Andrew Shacknove famously argued that both of these conditions should
-
Morally Permissible Risk Imposition and Liability to Defensive Harm Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2020-01-02 Susanne Burri
This paper examines whether an agent becomes liable to defensive harm by engaging in a morally permissible but foreseeably risk-imposing activity that subsequently threatens objectively unjustified harm. It first clarifies the notion of a foreseeably risk-imposing activity by proposing that an activity should count as foreseeably risk-imposing if an agent may morally permissibly perform it only if
-
Liberal Religious Neutrality and the Demarcation of Science: The Problem with Methodological Naturalism Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2020-01-02 Cristóbal Bellolio
There have been persistent philosophical efforts to demarcate the province of science. Fewer attempts have been made to explore whether these demarcation strategies are consistent with the liberal promise of religious neutrality (LPRN). Within this framework, most liberal political theorists seem to agree that hypotheses suggesting supernatural agency should remain outside the purview of science by
-
Legitimate Power without Authority: The Transmission Model Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2019-12-14 Matthias Brinkmann
Some authors have argued that legitimacy without authority is possible, though their work has not found much uptake in mainstream political philosophy. I provide an improved model how legitimate political institutions without authority are possible, the Transmission Model, which I couple with a thin substantive position, the Moral Value View. I defend the model against three common objections.
-
Why Snowden and not Greenwald? On the Accountability of the Press for Unauthorized Disclosures of Classified Information Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2019-12-04 Dorota Mokrosinska
In 2013, following the leaks by Edward Snowden, The Guardian published a number of classified NSA documents. Both leaking and publishing leaks violate the law prohibiting unauthorized disclosures. Accordingly, there are two potential targets for prosecution: the leakers and the press. In practice, however, only the leakers are prosecuted: Snowden is facing a threat of 30 years’ imprisonment; no charges
-
Compromise and religious freedom Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2019-11-27 Brian Hutler
Compromise is surprisingly common in the context of religious freedom. In Holt v. Hobbs, for example, a Muslim prison inmate challenged his prison’s no-beards policy on religious freedom grounds. He proposed, and was eventually granted, a compromise that allowed him to grow a half-inch beard rather than the full beard normally required by his beliefs. Some have argued that such a compromise is inconsistent
-
A Quasi-Contract Theory of Political Obligation Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2019-11-19 Cameron Oren Hunter
Whether there is a general moral obligation to obey the law, often referred to as ‘political obligation’, is an enduring question in contemporary legal and political philosophy. Theories are continually being formulated, criticized, and reformulated as theorists attempt to settle this issue. However, there yet remains no general consensus as to whether any theory successfully answers this question
-
Lying, Reciprocity, and Free Speech – A Reply to Eight Critics Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2019-10-29 Seana Valentine Shiffrin
In this article, I reply to eight critics of my book Speech Matters: On Lying, Morality, and the Law. The topics include lying, promising, reciprocity, free speech, and the testimonial duties of institutions.
-
Rescuing Public Reason Liberalism’s Accessibility Requirement Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2019-08-31 Gabriele Badano, Matteo Bonotti
Public reason liberalism is defined by the idea that laws and policies should be justifiable to each person who is subject to them. But what does it mean for reasons to be public or, in other words, suitable for this process of justification? In response to this question, Kevin Vallier has recently developed the traditional distinction between consensus and convergence public reason into a classification
-
Entrapment, Culpability, and Legitimacy Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2019-08-31 Hochan Kim
In this paper, I offer a novel account of entrapment. This account suggests that the wrongness of pursuing punishment in cases of entrapment consists of two distinct components, one concerning the culpability of the entrapped defendant and the other concerning the legitimacy of the entrapping state to prosecute crimes that it has effectively created. Distinguishing these two components of entrapment
-
The Feasibility of a Public Interest Defense for Whistleblowing Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2019-06-28 Eric R. Boot
It is commonly stated, by both whistleblower protection laws and political philosophers, that a breach of state secrecy by disclosing classified documents is justified if it serves the public interest. The problem with this defense of justified whistleblowing, however, is that the operative term – the public interest – is all too often left unclarified. This is problematic, because it leaves potential
-
Is Sincerity the First Virtue of Social Institutions? Police, Universities, and Free Speech Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2019-06-03 Amanda R. Greene
In the final chapter of Speech Matters, Seana Shiffrin argues that institutions have especially stringent duties to protect speech freedoms. In this article, I develop a few lines of criticism. First, I question whether Shiffrin’s framework of justified suspended contexts is appropriate for institutional settings. Second, I challenge the presumption that the knowledge-gathering function performed by
-
The Morality of Lying and the Murderer at the Door Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2019-05-28 Kate Greasley
The article engages with some of the main claims in chapter 1 of Seana Shiffrin’s book Speech Matters. There, Shiffrin sets out a case for a general moral prohibition on lying, based on the conditions required for reliable speech, and circumscribes the permissible falsehoods that could be uttered to would-be moral criminals, such as Kant’s familiar murderer at the door. I raise a few questions about
-
Promising Under Duress Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2019-05-08 Prince Saprai
In her chapter “Duress and Moral Progress”, Seana Shiffrin offers a novel perspective on coerced promises. According to the dominant view, these promises confer no right to performance on the coercer and do not create new reasons for the victim. Shiffrin accepts that these promises fail to confer rights, but disagrees that they never alter the victim’s moral profile. She argues that they do at least
-
Why Inconclusiveness is a Problem for Public Reason Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2019-05-07 Ben Cross, Thomas M. Besch
Most theorists of public reason, including both its proponents and critics, now accept that it is inconclusive, meaning that its correct application can result in a plurality of reasonable solutions to the issues it addresses. While some early critics argued that the inconclusiveness of public reason presented a serious problem for political legitimacy – a charge often associated with ‘the completeness
-
Consent, Communication, and Abandonment Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2019-04-10 Tom Dougherty
According to the Behavioral View of consent, consent must be expressed in behavior in order to release someone from a duty. By contrast, the Mental View of consent is that normatively efficacious consent is entirely mental. In previous work, I defended a version of the Behavioral View, according to which normatively efficacious ‘consent always requires public behavior, and this behavior must take the
-
Punishment, Fair Play and the Burdens of Citizenship Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2019-04-08 Piero Moraro
The fair-play theory of punishment claims that the state is justified in imposing additional burdens on law-breakers, to remove the unfair advantage the latter have enjoyed by disobeying the law. From this perspective, punishment reestablishes a fair distribution of benefits and burdens among all citizens. In this paper, I object to this view by focusing on the case of civil disobedience. I argue that
-
Mutually Beneficial Coercion: A Critique of the Coercive Approach to Distributive Justice Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2019-03-26 Elizabeth C. Hupfer
According to the coercive approach to distributive justice, the coercive nature of the political state requires justification in the form of distributive benefits owed only to members of the state (e.g., citizens). In this paper I analyze and dismiss traditional objections to the coercive approach, and I proceed to raise two novel objections. First, according to my equivocation objection, I contend
-
Punishing Wrongs from the Distant Past. Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2019-03-21 Thomas Douglas
On a Parfit-inspired account of culpability, as the psychological connections between a person’s younger self and older self weaken, the older self’s culpability for a wrong committed by the younger self diminishes. Suppose we accept this account and also accept a culpability-based upper limit on punishment severity. On this combination of views, we seem forced to conclude that perpetrators of distant
-
What’s Special about the Insult of Paternalism? Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2019-03-19 Carl Fox
A common assumption is that paternalism generates a special, and especially grievous, insult. Identifying this distinctive insult is then presented as the key to unlocking the concept and determining its moral significance. I submit that there is no special insult. It is, rather, a particular form that a lack of recognition respect can take. Attempting to capture the special insult has led us into
-
Arguing Against the Expressive Function of Punishment: Is the Standard Account that Insufficient? Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2019-03-16 Ambrose Y. K. Lee
This paper critically appraises the arguments that have been offered for what can be called ‘the expressive function of punishment’. According to this view, what distinguishes punishment from other kinds of non-punitive hard treatment is that punishment conveys a censorial/reprobative message about what the punished has done, and that this expressive function should therefore be accepted as part of
-
Conscientious objection and equality laws: Why the content of the conscience matters Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2019-03-12 Yossi Nehushtan
By enacting equality laws the liberal state decides the limits of liberal tolerance by relying on content-based rather than content-neutral considerations. Equality laws are not and cannot be neutral. They reflect a content-based moral decision about the importance and weight of the principle of equality vis-à-vis other rights or interests. This leads to the following conclusions: First, since equality
-
Law as a Social Construction and Conceptual Legal Theory Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2019-03-07 Dan Priel
A currently popular view among legal positivists is that law is a social construction. Many of the same legal philosophers also argue that before one can study law empirically, one needs to know what it is. At the heart of this paper is the claim that these two propositions are inconsistent. It presents the following dilemma: if law is a social construction like all other social constructions, then
-
Lying as a Political Wrong Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2019-03-04 Micah Schwartzman
In Speech Matters, Seana Shiffrin claims that certain lies should be tolerated on grounds of political inclusiveness. If political equality requires perfect compliance with fair terms of social cooperation, and if lying violates those terms, then liars might be at risk of losing their standing as political equals. To avoid that draconian result requires accommodation of moral imperfections, including
-
Thoughts on a Thinker-Based Approach to Freedom Of Speech Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2019-02-21 Eric Barendt
While agreeing with Seana Shiffrin that any free speech theory must depend on assumptions about our need for free thinking, I am sceptical about her claim that her thinker-based approach provides the best explanation for freedom of speech. Her argument has some similarities with Mill’s argument from truth and with self-development theories, though it improves on the latter. But the thinker-based approach
-
Breaking the Law Under Competitive Pressure Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2019-02-20 Robert C. Hughes
When a business has competitors that break a burdensome law, is it morally required to obey this law, or may it break the law to avoid an unfair competitive disadvantage? Though this ethical question is pervasive in the business world, many non-skeptical theories of the obligation to obey the law cannot give it a clear answer. A broadly Kantian account, by contrast, can explain why businesspeople ought
-
Punishment as Moral Fortification and Non-Consensual Neurointerventions Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2019-02-08 Areti Theofilopoulou
The purpose of this paper is twofold. First, I defend and expand the Fortificationist Theory of Punishment (FTP). Second, I argue that this theory implies that non-consensual neurointerventions – interventions that act directly on one’s brain – are permissible. According to the FTP, punishment is justified as a way of ensuring that citizens who infringe their duty to demonstrate the reliability of
-
Lying, Speech and Impersonal Harm Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2019-01-11 Nicholas Hatzis
Should the law punish the mere utterance of lies even if the listener has not been deceived? Seana Shiffrin has recently answered this question in the affirmative. She argues that pure lying as such harms the moral fabric of sincerity and distorts the testimonial warrants which underpin communication. The article begins with a discussion of Shiffrin’s account of lying as a moral wrong and the idea
-
Legal Obligation & Its Limits Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2019-01-02 Emad H. Atiq
Judges decide cases by appeal to rules of general application they deem to be law. If a candidate rule resolves the case and is, ex ante and independently of the judge’s judgment, the law, then the judge has a legal obligation to declare it as such and follow it. That, at any rate, is conventional wisdom. Yet the principle is false – a rule’s being law or the judge’s believing it to be law is neither
-
‘Won’t Somebody Please Think of the Children?’ Hate Speech, Harm, and Childhood Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2018-12-07 Robert Mark Simpson
Some authors claim that hate speech plays a key role in perpetuating unjust social hierarchy. One prima facie plausible hypothesis about how this occurs is that hate speech has a pernicious influence on the attitudes of children. Here I argue that this hypothesis has an important part to play in the formulation of an especially robust case for general legal prohibitions on hate speech. If our account
-
The Nature of Retributive Justice and Its Demands on the State Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2018-11-13 Richard L. Lippke
The enterprise of state punishment requires the use of limited resources for which there are other competitors, such as national defense, market regulation, and social welfare. How resource-demanding retributive justice will turn out to be depends on how retributivists answer a series of questions concerning the theory’s structure. After elaborating these questions and the varieties of retributive
-
Vesting Agent-Relative Permissions in a Proxy* Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2018-10-25 Saba Bazargan-Forward
We all have agent-relative permissions to give extra weight to our own well-being. If you and two strangers are drowning, and you can save either yourself or two strangers, you have an agent-relative permission to save yourself. But is it possible for you to ‘vest’ your agent-relative permissions in a third party – a ‘proxy’ – who can enact your agent-centered permissions on your behalf, thereby permitting
-
Law’s Normative Point Law Philos. (IF 0.816) Pub Date : 2018-06-29 George Duke
This paper defends the explanatory priority for the general descriptive theory of law of an investigation into law’s normative point over an investigation of law’s other central features. The paper begins by clarifying the normative priority thesis and implications of the assertion that law has a normative point. It then develops, in Section II, two arguments in favour of the priority thesis. Section III
Contents have been reproduced by permission of the publishers.