Skip to main content
Log in

Decision-making under risk: when is utility-maximization equivalent to risk-minimization?

  • Published:
Theory and Decision Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Motivated by the analysis of a general optimal portfolio selection problem, which encompasses as special cases an optimal consumption and an optimal debt-arrangement problem, we are concerned with the questions of how a personality trait like risk-perception can be formalized and whether the two objectives of utility-maximization and risk-minimization can be both achieved simultaneously. We address these questions by developing an axiomatic foundation of preferences for which utility-maximization is equivalent to minimizing a utility-based shortfall risk measure. Our axiomatization hinges on a novel axiom in decision theory, namely the risk-perception axiom.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Data availability

We do not analyze or generate any data sets because our work proceeds within a theoretical and mathematical approach.

Notes

  1. E.g., the utility-based shortfall risk measure. See, for example, Gundel and Weber (2007) or Guo and Xu (2019).

  2. E.g., the Value at Risk (VaR) or conditional value at risk (CVaR).

  3. It is well known that the acceptance set of a coherent risk measure is a convex cone containing the positive cone of the payoff space (see section 3).

  4. The idea, here, is that the true probability measure is unknown. Therefore, the decision-maker hedges against the risk arising from ambiguity regarding the true probability measure on the states of nature.

  5. See, e.g., Guo and Xu (2019) and Gundel and Weber (2007) for the definition and a fairly detailed account of utility-based shortfall risk measures. We note, in passing, that VaR is a special case of SR.

  6. See, e.g., LeRoy and Werner (2014) for the definition of arbitrage-free asset prices in simple two-period models of financial markets.

  7. See, e.g., Ross (1978) or Clark (1993) for the valuation problem and the fundamental theorem of asset pricing in ordered vector spaces.

  8. In the sequel, we will refer to the function (4) as the (coherent) risk measure defined on X with respect to the cone P and the order unit \(x_{0}\).

  9. Where h is any real number.

  10. See, e.g., Theorem 14.9, the proof of Theorem 14.10, and Corollary 14.11 in Aliprantis and Border (2006).

  11. See page 475 therein.

  12. Refer to the above axiom A.6.

  13. See page 476 in Guo and Xu (2019) for the definition of distributionally robust SR.

  14. Therefore, it is not accurate to directly relate our results to Kimball’s.

  15. See the comments below (2).

  16. With respect to both \(\ell _{\infty }^{+}\) and P.

  17. See, e.g., Lemma 5.51 in Aliprantis and Border (2006).

  18. This fact will be used again in the rest of the proof without further notice.

  19. As such, \(-U\) is a coherent risk measure (satisfying \(U\left( {\textbf{1}} \right) =1\)) defined on \(\ell _{\infty }\) ordered by \(\ell _{\infty }^{+}\) and with \({\textbf{1}}\) as an order unit.

  20. For the concept of non-degeneracy and its implications for uniqueness of the ambiguity set C, see pages 144-145 in Gilboa and Schmeidler (1989).

References

  • Aliprantis, C. D., & Border, K. C. (2006). Infinite Dimensional Analysis A Hitchhiker’s Guide. New York, Third edition: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, S. A. (1993). The valuation problem in arbitrage price theory. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 22, 463–478.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilboa, I., & Schmeidler, D. (1989). Maximin expected utility with non-unique prior. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 18, 141–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gundel, A., & Weber, S. (2007). Robust utility maximization with limited downside risk in incomplete markets. Stochastic Processes and their Applications, 117, 1663–1688.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guo, S., & Xu, H. (2019). Distributionally robust shortfall risk optimization model and its approximation. Mathematical Programming, 174, 473–498.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kimball, M. S. (1990). Precautionary Saving in the Small and in the Large. Econometrica, 58, 53–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kountzakis, C., & Polyrakis, I. A. (2013). Coherent risk measures in general economic models and price bubbles. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 49(3), 201–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • LeRoy, S. F., & Werner, J. (2014). Principles of Financial Economics (2nd ed.). Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ross, S. (1978). A Simple Approach to the Valuation of Risky Streams. The Journal of Business, 51, 453–475.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmeidler, D. (1989). Subjective Probability and Expected Utility without Additivity. Econometrica, 57(3), 571–587.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weber, E. U. (2004). Perception Matters: Psychophysics for Economists. In J. Carrillo & I. Brocas (Eds.), Psychology and Economics (pp. 165–176). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Funding

The authors have no relevant financial or non-financial interests to disclose.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Francesco Ruscitti.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The authors declare that they have no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Appendix

Appendix

Proof of Theorem 1

\((2)\Rightarrow (1)\):


Let \(U\left( {\textbf{x}}\right) =\min \left\{ {\mathbb {E}}_{\pi } \left[ {\textbf{x}}\right] :\pi \in D\right\}\) for all \({\textbf{x}}\in \ell _{\infty }\), and define the binary (preference) relation \(\succsim\) on \(\ell _{\infty }\) by \({\textbf{x}}\succsim {\textbf{y}}\) if and only if \(U({\textbf{x}})\ge U({\textbf{y}})\) for all \({\textbf{x}},{\textbf{y}}\in \ell _{\infty }\). Since U is real-valued and D is closed, we have that

$$\begin{aligned} \min \left\{ {\mathbb {E}}_{\pi }\left[ {\textbf{x}}\right] :\pi \in D\right\} =\inf \left\{ {\mathbb {E}}_{\pi }\left[ {\textbf{x}}\right] :\pi \in D\right\} , \text { for all }{\textbf{x}}\in \ell _{\infty \text {.}}\text {.} \end{aligned}$$
(5)

Using (5), some straightforward algebra shows the following:

$$\begin{aligned} -U\left( {\textbf{x}}\right) =-\inf \left\{ {\mathbb {E}}_{\pi }\left[ {\textbf{x}} \right] :\pi \in D\right\} =\inf \left\{ t\in {\mathbb {R}}:{\textbf{x}}+t\textbf{ 1}\in P\right\} \text {,} \end{aligned}$$

where \(P=\left\{ {\textbf{x}}\in \ell _{\infty }:{\mathbb {E}}_{\pi } \left[ {\textbf{x}}\right] \ge 0\text { for all }\pi \in D\right\} .\) Since P is a closed cone containing \(\ell _{\infty }^{+}\), and \(\mathbf {1\in }P\) is an order unit,Footnote 16 by Lemma 1 and the above equality we have that \(-U:\ell _{\infty }\rightarrow {\mathbb {R}}\) is a coherent risk measure, with respect to \(\ell _{\infty }^{+}\) and the vector \({\textbf{1}}\), and \({\mathcal {A}}_{-U}=P\). Therefore, it follows from the four defining properties of coherent risk measures (in section 3) and the definition of acceptance set that:

$$\begin{aligned}{} & {} {\textbf{x}}-\mathbf {y\in }\ell _{\infty }^{+}\hbox { implies }U\left( {\textbf{x}} \right) \ge U\left( {\textbf{y}}\right) . \ (i)\\{} & {} U\left( \mathbf {x+}t{\textbf{1}}\right) =U\left( {\textbf{x}}\right) +t\hbox {, for all }{\textbf{x}}\in \ell _{\infty }\hbox { and }t\in {\mathbb {R}}. \ (ii)\\{} & {} U\left( \mathbf {x+y}\right) \ge U\left( {\textbf{x}}\right) +U\left( \textbf{ y}\right) \hbox {, for all }{\textbf{x}},{\textbf{y}}\in \ell _{\infty }. \ (iii) \\{} & {} U\left( \lambda {\textbf{x}}\right) =\lambda U\left( {\textbf{x}}\right) \hbox {, for all }{\textbf{x}}\in \ell _{\infty }\hbox { and }\lambda \ge 0. \ (iv) \\{} & {} \left\{ {\textbf{x}}\in \ell _{\infty }:U\left( {\textbf{x}}\right) \ge 0\right\} =A_{-U}=P \ (v). \end{aligned}$$

Of course, \(\succsim\) satisfies axiom A.1. Using the above properties (ii) and (iv) it is very easy to see that \(\succsim\) satisfies axiom A.2. By the above properties (iii) and (iv), \(-U\) is a sublinear function and one can readily see that it is bounded on every neighborhood of zero. Hence, U is continuous in the supremum norm-topology.Footnote 17 In turn, continuity of U easily implies that \(\succsim\) satisfies axiom A.3. That \(\succsim\) satisfies axiom A.4. part (a) is an immediate consequence of property (i). As to part (b) of axiom A.4., suppose that there is some \(\epsilon >0\), such that \(x_{n}-y_{n}\ge \epsilon\) for every \(n\in {\mathbb {N}}\). Then, \({\textbf{x}}-{\textbf{y}}\) lies in the norm-interior of \(\ell _{\infty }^{+}\). Since \(P\supseteq \ell _{\infty }^{+}\), it also belongs to the norm-interior of P. Therefore, since \(-U\left( {\textbf{x}}\right) =\inf \left\{ t\in {\mathbb {R}}:{\textbf{x}}+t{\textbf{1}}\in P\right\}\) (see above), it follows from Lemma 2 that \(U\left( {\textbf{x}}-{\textbf{y}}\right) >0\). On the other hand, as an easy consequence of property (iii), we get \(U\left( {\textbf{x}}\right) -U\left( {\textbf{y}}\right) \ge U\left( {\textbf{x}}-{\textbf{y}}\right)\), which implies \(U\left( {\textbf{x}}\right) >U\left( {\textbf{y}}\right)\), and hence, \({\textbf{x}}\succ {\textbf{y}}\). This establishes that \(\succsim\) satisfies part (b) of axiom A.4. Next, a very straightforward application of properties (iii) and (iv) shows that \(\succsim\) satisfies axiom A.5. Finally, property (iv) clearly yields \(U\left( {\textbf{0}}\right) =0\). Thus, \(\succsim\) satisfies axiom A.6 as an obvious implication of property (v).

\((1)\Rightarrow (2)\): To improve readability, the proof will be divided into three steps.

Step 1 (Existence of a utility function representing preferences):

Let \(\succsim\) be a preference relation on \(\ell _{\infty }\) satisfying axioms A.1-A.6. Pick any arbitrary \(\mathbf {x\in }\ell _{\infty }\), and define the following sets:

$$\begin{aligned} A= & {} \left\{ t\in {\mathbb {R}}:t{\textbf{1}}\succsim {\textbf{x}}\right\} \text { } \\ B= & {} \left\{ t\in {\mathbb {R}}:{\textbf{x}}\succsim t{\textbf{1}}\right\} \text {.} \end{aligned}$$

We claim that A and B are both non-empty. To see this, note that, by definition of \(\ell _{\infty }\), there exists some \(M>0\) such that \(-M\le x_{n}\le M\) for every \(n\in {\mathbb {N}}\). Thus, by A.4 part (a) we get \(M\mathbf {1\succsim x}\succsim -M{\textbf{1}}\). Therefore, \(M\in A\) and \(-M\in B\). Moreover, using axiom A.3 it is easy to check that A and B are both closed. Furthermore, completeness of preferences (see axiom A.1) implies \(\mathbb {R=}A\cup B\). Thus, since \({\mathbb {R}}\) is connected, we must have that \(A\cap B\ne \varnothing\). This readily implies (see the above definitions of sets A and B) that there exists a real number \(t_{\textbf{ x}}\) such that \(t_{{\textbf{x}}}\mathbf {1\sim x}\). Such a number is unique. For, suppose, by way of obtaining a contradiction, that there is some \(s_{ {\textbf{x}}}\ne t_{{\textbf{x}}}\) such that \(s_{{\textbf{x}}}\mathbf {1\sim x}\), and assume, without any loss of generality, that \(s_{{\textbf{x}}}>t_{\textbf{x }}\). Then, on the one hand A.1 implies \(s_{{\textbf{x}}}\mathbf {1\sim }t_{ {\textbf{x}}}{\textbf{1}}\), and on the other hand it follows from A.4 part (b) that \(s_{{\textbf{x}}}{\textbf{1}}\succ t_{{\textbf{x}}}{\textbf{1}}\), which yields the desired contradiction. Therefore, we have established the existence of a function \(U:\ell _{\infty }\rightarrow {\mathbb {R}}\) defined by

$$\begin{aligned} \ell _{\infty }\ni \mathbf {x\mapsto }U\left( {\textbf{x}}\right) :=t_{\textbf{x }}\text { with }t_{{\textbf{x}}}\mathbf {1\sim x}\text {.} \end{aligned}$$

Moreover, using axioms A.1 and A.4 it is a simple exercise to verify that \({\textbf{x}}\succsim {\textbf{y}}\) if and only if \(U\left( \textbf{x }\right) \ge U\left( {\textbf{y}}\right)\). This proves that the above \(U:\ell _{\infty }\rightarrow {\mathbb {R}}\) is a utility function representing the given preferences. Incidentally, observe that, by construction of the utility function, \(U\left( c{\textbf{1}}\right) =c\) for every real number c.Footnote 18

Step 2 (Showing that the utility function is a functional a la Gilboa and Schmeidler):

We claim that axioms (A.1)-(A.5) imply the existence of a non-empty, closed, and convex set C of finitely additive probability measures on \(2^{{\mathbb {N}}}\) such that

$$\begin{aligned} U\left( {\textbf{x}}\right) =\min \left\{ {\mathbb {E}}_{\pi }\left[ {\textbf{x}} \right] :\pi \in C\right\} ,\text { for all }{\textbf{x}}\in \ell _{\infty }. \end{aligned}$$

To prove the claim, we begin by noting that A.4 part (a) immediately implies that the utility function is monotonic, i.e., satisfies property (i) listed above. Next, we will prove that the utility function U satisfies property (iv) listed above. That (iv) holds true for \(\lambda =0\) and \(\lambda =1\) is obvious. Therefore, assume, to begin with, that \(0<\lambda <1\), and pick any \(\mathbf {x\in }\ell _{\infty }\). Note that \(U\left( \lambda {\textbf{x}}\right) =t_{\lambda {\textbf{x}}}\) where \(t_{\lambda \textbf{ x}}\mathbf {1\sim }\lambda {\textbf{x}}\), and \(U\left( {\textbf{x}}\right) =t_{ {\textbf{x}}}\), where \(t_{{\textbf{x}}}\mathbf {1\sim x}\). Since \(t_{{\textbf{x}}} \mathbf {1\sim x}\) and \(0<\lambda <1\), it follows from A.2 that \(\lambda t_{ {\textbf{x}}}\mathbf {1\sim }\lambda {\textbf{x}}\). On the other hand, we know that \(t_{\lambda {\textbf{x}}}\mathbf {1\sim }\lambda {\textbf{x}}\); therefore, A.1 implies \(t_{\lambda {\textbf{x}}}\mathbf {1\sim }\lambda t_{{\textbf{x}}} {\textbf{1}}\); hence, \(U\left( t_{\lambda {\textbf{x}}}{\textbf{1}}\right) =t_{\lambda {\textbf{x}}}=U\left( \lambda t_{{\textbf{x}}}{\textbf{1}}\right) =\lambda t_{{\textbf{x}}}\), which finally implies \(U\left( \lambda {\textbf{x}} \right) =\lambda U\left( {\textbf{x}}\right)\). We are left with showing that property (iv) holds true also for \(\lambda >1\), as follows: we know that \(t_{\lambda {\textbf{x}}}\mathbf {1\sim }\lambda {\textbf{x}}\), \(t_{{\textbf{x}}} \mathbf {1\sim x}\), and that \(0<\frac{1}{\lambda }<1\). Therefore, by A.2 we get \(\frac{1}{\lambda }t_{\lambda {\textbf{x}}}\mathbf {1\sim x}\), so A.1 readily implies \(\frac{1}{\lambda }t_{\lambda {\textbf{x}}}\mathbf {1\sim }t_{ {\textbf{x}}}{\textbf{1}}\). Thus

$$\begin{aligned} t_{{\textbf{x}}}=U\left( t_{{\textbf{x}}}{\textbf{1}}\right) =U\left( \frac{1}{ \lambda }t_{\lambda {\textbf{x}}}{\textbf{1}}\right) =\frac{1}{\lambda }U\left( t_{\lambda {\textbf{x}}}{\textbf{1}}\right) =\frac{1}{\lambda }t_{\lambda {\textbf{x}}}, \end{aligned}$$

which yields immediately \(\lambda U\left( {\textbf{x}}\right) =U\left( \lambda {\textbf{x}}\right)\). Next, we show that the utility function U enjoys property (ii) listed above. Toward this end, pick any \(\textbf{x }\in \ell _{\infty }\) and \(t\in {\mathbb {R}}\). Define

$$\begin{aligned} \beta =U\left( 2{\textbf{x}}\right) =2U\left( {\textbf{x}}\right) \text {,} \end{aligned}$$
(6)

and note that \(\beta =t_{2{\textbf{x}}}\) with \(\beta \mathbf {1\sim }2 {\textbf{x}}\). Observe that \(2t\mathbf {1\in }\ell _{\infty }^{C}\). Therefore, letting \(\alpha =\frac{1}{2}\) and using A.2 we get \(\frac{1}{2}2\mathbf {x+} \frac{1}{2}2t\mathbf {1\sim }\frac{1}{2}\beta \mathbf {1+}\frac{1}{2}2t\textbf{ 1}\), i.e., \(\mathbf {x+}t\mathbf {1\sim }(\frac{1}{2}\beta +t){\textbf{1}}\). The previous condition and (6) readily imply

$$\begin{aligned} U\left( \mathbf {x+}t{\textbf{1}}\right) =U\left( (\frac{1}{2}\beta +t)\textbf{1 }\right) =\frac{1}{2}\beta +t=U\left( {\textbf{x}}\right) +t\text {,} \end{aligned}$$

as was to be proven. We proceed to show that the utility function is superadditive (property (iii) listed above). To this end, a straightforward application of property (iv) reveals that it will suffice to prove that for all \({\textbf{x}}\) and \({\textbf{y}}\) in \(\ell _{\infty }\)

$$\begin{aligned} U\left( \frac{1}{2}\mathbf {x+}\frac{1}{2}{\textbf{y}}\right) \ge \frac{1}{2} U\left( {\textbf{x}}\right) +\frac{1}{2}U\left( {\textbf{y}}\right) \text {.} \end{aligned}$$

To establish the above inequality, we pick any \({\textbf{x}}\) and \({\textbf{y}}\) in \(\ell _{\infty }\) and distinguish three exhaustive cases. Case (a): \(U\left( {\textbf{x}}\right) =U\left( {\textbf{y}}\right)\); case (b): \(U\left( {\textbf{x}}\right) >U\left( {\textbf{y}}\right)\); case (c): \(U\left( {\textbf{x}}\right) <U\left( {\textbf{y}}\right)\). We first deal with case (a), as follows: \(U\left( {\textbf{x}}\right) =U\left( {\textbf{y}} \right)\) implies \(\mathbf {x\sim y}\). Therefore, it follows from axiom A.5 that \(\frac{1}{2}\mathbf {x+}\frac{1}{2}\mathbf {y\succsim x}\). Hence, \(U\left( \frac{1}{2}\mathbf {x+}\frac{1}{2}{\textbf{y}}\right) \ge U\left( {\textbf{x}}\right) =\frac{1}{2}U\left( {\textbf{x}}\right) +\frac{1}{2}U\left( {\textbf{y}}\right)\), as was to be proven. Regarding case (b), let

$$\begin{aligned} t=U\left( {\textbf{x}}\right) -U\left( {\textbf{y}}\right) \text {,} \end{aligned}$$
(7)

and set \({\textbf{c}}=\mathbf {y+}t{\textbf{1}}\). By property (ii) and (7) above, we get

$$\begin{aligned} U\left( {\textbf{c}}\right) =U\left( \mathbf {y+}t{\textbf{1}}\right) =U\left( {\textbf{y}}\right) +t=U\left( {\textbf{y}}\right) +U\left( {\textbf{x}}\right) -U\left( {\textbf{y}}\right) =U\left( {\textbf{x}}\right) \text {.} \end{aligned}$$

Now, using again property (ii), we see that

$$\begin{aligned} U\left( \frac{1}{2}\mathbf {x+}\frac{1}{2}{\textbf{c}}\right) =U\left( \frac{1}{ 2}\mathbf {x+}\frac{1}{2}\mathbf {y+}\frac{1}{2}t{\textbf{1}}\right) =U\left( \frac{1}{2}\mathbf {x+}\frac{1}{2}{\textbf{y}}\right) +\frac{1}{2}t\text {.} \end{aligned}$$
(8)

On the other hand, since \(U\left( {\textbf{c}}\right) =U\left( {\textbf{x}}\right)\), we can rely on the previous case (a) and invoke property (ii) together with (8) above to conclude

$$\begin{aligned}{} & {} U\left( \frac{1}{2}\mathbf {x+}\frac{1}{2}{\textbf{y}}\right) +\frac{1}{2} t=U\left( \frac{1}{2}\mathbf {x+}\frac{1}{2}{\textbf{c}}\right) \ge \frac{1}{2} U\left( {\textbf{x}}\right) +\frac{1}{2}U\left( {\textbf{c}}\right) \\{} & {} \quad =\frac{1}{2}U\left( {\textbf{x}}\right) +\frac{1}{2}U\left( \mathbf {y+}t {\textbf{1}}\right) =\frac{1}{2}U\left( {\textbf{x}}\right) +\frac{1}{2}\left[ U\left( {\textbf{y}}\right) +t\right] =\frac{1}{2}U\left( {\textbf{x}}\right) + \frac{1}{2}U\left( {\textbf{y}}\right) +\frac{1}{2}t; \end{aligned}$$

hence, \(U\left( \frac{1}{2}\mathbf {x+}\frac{1}{2}{\textbf{y}}\right) \ge \frac{1}{2}U\left( {\textbf{x}}\right) +\frac{1}{2}U\left( {\textbf{y}} \right)\), as was to be proven. As for case (c), it turns out it can be handled very similarly to case (b).

So far, we have proven that axioms (A.1)-(A.5) give rise to a utility function U, representing preferences, which satisfies properties \((i)-(iv)\) and which is such that \(U\left( {\textbf{1}}\right) =1\).Footnote 19. Therefore, by Lemma 3.5 in Gilboa and Schmeidler (1989) there exists a non-empty, closed and convex set C of finitely additive probability measures on \(2^{{\mathbb {N}}}\) such that

$$\begin{aligned} U\left( {\textbf{x}}\right) =\min \left\{ {\mathbb {E}}_{\pi }\left[ {\textbf{x}} \right] :\pi \in C\right\} ,\text { for all }{\textbf{x}}\in \ell _{\infty }. \end{aligned}$$
(9)

Step 3 (Pinpointing the ambiguity set C ):

In what follows, we show that the risk-perception axiom A.6 pins down the ambiguity set (i.e., \(C=D\)), hence the exact form of the utility function U.

We know from Step 2 that \(-U\) is a coherent risk measure on \(\ell _{\infty }\), when the latter is ordered by \(\ell _{\infty }^{+}\) and \({\textbf{1}}\) is an order unit. Therefore, by (3) above we get \(-U\left( {\textbf{x}}\right) =\inf \left\{ t\in {\mathbb {R}}:{\textbf{x}}+t{\textbf{1}}\in {\mathcal {A}}_{-U}\right\}\) for all \(\mathbf {x\in }\ell _{\infty }\). Also, it readily follows from the definition of acceptance set and axiom A.6 that \({\mathcal {A}}_{-U}=P=\left\{ {\textbf{x}}\in \ell _{\infty }:{\mathbb {E}}_{\pi } \left[ {\textbf{x}}\right] \ge 0\text { for all }\pi \in D\right\}\). Therefore

$$\begin{aligned} -U\left( {\textbf{x}}\right) =\inf \left\{ t\in {\mathbb {R}}:{\textbf{x}}+t\textbf{ 1}\in P\right\} \text {.} \end{aligned}$$
(10)

Performing some straightforward algebra in (10), we get \(U\left( {\textbf{x}}\right) =\inf \left\{ {\mathbb {E}}_{\pi }\left[ {\textbf{x}}\right] :\pi \in D\right\} ,\) for all \({\textbf{x}}\in \ell _{\infty }\). Since every \(\pi \in D\) is a probability measure and any \({\textbf{x}}\in \ell _{\infty }\) is bounded, the \(\inf\) in the previous equation is a real number. Furthermore, because D is closed, by assumption, such infimum is actually attained. Therefore, we come to

$$\begin{aligned} U\left( {\textbf{x}}\right) =\min \left\{ {\mathbb {E}}_{\pi }\left[ {\textbf{x}} \right] :\pi \in D\right\} ,\text {for all }{\textbf{x}}\in \ell _{\infty }. \end{aligned}$$
(11)

Finally, one can readily see that preferences satisfying axiom (A.6) are non-degenerate.Footnote 20 Thus, as in Gilboa and Schmeidler (1989), the ambiguity set C in (9) above must be unique. Therefore, since D is by assumption closed and convex, (9) and (11) imply \(C=D\). The proof is now complete. \(\square\)

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Ruscitti, F., Dubey, R.S. & Laguzzi, G. Decision-making under risk: when is utility-maximization equivalent to risk-minimization?. Theory Decis (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-023-09969-1

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-023-09969-1

Keywords

Navigation