Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

A Humean Non-Humeanism

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

How should we account for the extraordinary regularity in the world? Humeans and Non-Humeans sharply disagree. According to Non-Humeans, the world behaves in an extraordinarily regular way because of certain necessary connections in nature. However, Humeans have thought that Non-Humean views are metaphysically objectionable. In particular, there are two general metaphysical principles that Humeans have found attractive that are incompatible with all existing versions of Non-Humeanism. My goal in this paper is to develop a novel version of Non-Humeanism that is consistent with (and even entails) both of these general metaphysical principles. By endorsing such a view, one can have the explanatory benefits of Non-Humeanism while at the same time avoiding two of the major metaphysical objections towards Non-Humeanism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Although the terminology of “Humeanism” and “Non-Humeanism” is now entrenched, it is not at all clear that David Hume himself was a Humean (e.g. see Strawson 2014).

  2. Mumford (2004), Bird (2007), and Shoemaker (1980) defend the view that there are fundamental powers/dispositions. Carroll (1994, 2008) and Maudlin (2007) defend the view that laws are fundamental. Armstrong (1983), Dretske (1977), and Tooley (1977) defend the view that there are necessitation relations between universals.

  3. Although most self-described Humeans use this “best-system” approach to laws to account for other nomic notions, one can accept an underlying Humean metaphysics without adopting the best system approach. For example, van Fraassen (1989) has argued that Humeans should deny that there are any laws at all, and Wilson (2009) has defended an alternative Humean account of causal facts that does not appeal to general laws. See Friend (2021) for further discussion of different versions of Humeanism.

  4. For defenses of this kind of position, see Chakravartty (2003, 2007), Mumford (2004), and Bird (2007).

  5. While the distinction between categorical/dispositional properties is commonplace in discussions of natural properties, it is controversial exactly how to understand this distinction (see Taylor 2018 for a discussion of some of these controversies). It is beyond the scope of this paper to enter into the details of these controversies here, but it should be noted that for our purposes the distinction between categorical and dispositional properties is not simply a modal one. For example, Bird (2007: 66-67) defines a categorical property as any property that does not necessitate a corresponding power or disposition. However, such a definition doesn’t allow conceptual room for the “grounding view of powers” that will be introduced in the next section. See Coates (2020) for a hyperintensional characterization of the distinction between qualities and powers in terms of essence and grounding that will be suitable for our purposes.

  6. Of course, upon reflection one might come to think that colors are dispositional properties (e.g. ones that are disposed to cause certain sensations in humans in normal conditions). Chalmers’ (2006) conception of “Edenic” colors are paradigm examples of qualities.

  7. In other contexts, “qualitative” properties are meant to contrast with “haecceitistic” properties, such as the property of being Alice (e.g. see Dasgupta 2017). However, in this sense of “qualitative”, both qualities (e.g. being red) and dispositions (e.g. being fragile) are “qualitative”. For the entirety of this paper, I will be using the phrase “qualitative property” to refer to qualities rather than non-haecceitistic properties.

  8. It is a subtle question how Humeans should formulate HD more precisely. For example, a Humean might wish to reformulate HD in a way that allows there to be a necessary connection between Socrates and his singleton set. For our purposes, these kinds of counterexamples won’t be relevant, but for a wide ranging critical discussion of various different formulations of Hume’s Dictum, see Wilson (2010).

  9. The choice of defining “wholly distinct” in terms of lack of merelogical and spatiotemporal overlap comes from Wilson (2010: 604–607).

  10. For a defense of the claim that a suitably idealized kind of conceivability entails possibility, see Chalmers (2002).

  11. Here I am implicitly making the Non-Humean assumption that Humean explanations of these phenomena are inadequate. For more on the question of whether Humean laws can genuinely explain, see Lange (2013, 2018), Shumener (2019), Dorst (2019), Bhogal (2020), Kovacs (2020), Hicks (2021), and Emery (forthcoming).

  12. For example, Kimpton-Nye (2021) motivates such a view on the grounds that it avoids some of the central objections towards standard versions of “dispositional essentialism”.

  13. The label “the grounding theory of powers” comes from Tugby (2021). A closely related view to GP is the “Powerful Qualities” view, according to which fundamental physical qualities are identical to (rather than ground) dispositional properties (e.g. see Strawson 2008 and Heil 2010). Such a view is similar in spirit to the grounding view, but I will be focusing on the grounding version of the Powerful Qualities view here since it is easier to make sense of. It is interesting to note that the way that Coates (2020) makes sense of the Powerful Qualities view makes it equivalent to GP.

  14. Although Goff (2020) is skeptical that phenomenal properties are capable of grounding dispositions, he defends the possibility of closely related “consciousness + ” properties grounding dispositions.

  15. As Kimpton-Nye (2021) points out, however, one might also believe that the relevant grounding relations are “opaque”, in the sense that it is conceivable that the grounding fact obtains without the grounded fact. See Schaffer (2017) for an extended defense of the general view that opaque grounding relations are pervasive.

  16. The relevant version of GP is one that is meant to account for all nomological necessities in terms of the (grounded) dispositions of fundamental objects. Although one could in principle account for some nomological necessities using the resources of GP and account for other nomological necessities in some other way, I will be assuming that GP is a complete theory of nomological necessity throughout this paper. Thanks to an anonymous referee for raising this concern.

  17. Heller (1990), Oderberg (1993: 86), and Sider (2001: 217) each make these points.

  18. Mumford (2009) has also independently argued that a powers-based metaphysics should be combined with endurantism, but see Williams (2019: 209–213) for a critique of Mumford.

  19. For independent motivations for Monism, see Schaffer (2007, 2010a, 2010b, 2010c, 2013), Ismael and Schaffer (2020), and Builes (2021).

  20. This combination of Endurantism and Monism is also used by Builes and Teitel (forthcoming) to secure the lawful non-qualitative evolution of the universe.

  21. Such a view is still neutral on whether one should adopt an Eternalist “block universe” metaphysics, according to which the past, present, and future are equally real, or a Presentist metaphysics, according to which only present objects exist. By itself, Endurantism has been developed in both Eternalist and Presentist frameworks.

  22. It should be noted, however, that if the combination of 4-D Monism and GP could be made sense of (perhaps by saying that the 4-D universe as a whole timelessly stands in a causal relation to itself), then 4-D Monism and GP by themselves would be able to account for TSQ and HD. For those who are antecedently inclined to reject Endurantism, this view is certainly worth exploring further.

  23. This observation has also been made by Schaffer (2010b), who argues that failures of free modal recombination among some entities is a sign that those entities are not fundamental.

  24. Langton (2001, 2004) defends an interpretation of Kant in which he argues for a similar conclusion. Contemporary Russellian Monists, following Russell (1927), also endorse the same conclusion. Lastly, many (epistemic) “structural realists” in the philosophy of science argue for a similar conclusion (e.g. see Ladyman 2016).

  25. Another possible reason why Humeans may not be attracted to GP is that GP implies that any possible world with the same properties will be governed by the very same laws. However, as Bhogal and Perry (2021) have argued, the view that properties have their nomic roles necessarily is actually compatible with an underlying Humean metaphysics. Moreover, it is unclear whether Humeans should consider the view that properties can come apart from their nomic roles as a desideratum, or whether they should simply view it as a consequence of other deeper commitments of theirs.

  26. One of the arguments I won’t be covering is Lewis’ (1983: 76–77) argument that Endurantism is in tension with Humean supervenience. However, see Hawthorne, Wasserman, and Scala (2004) and Magidor (2016) for critiques of Lewis’ argument.

  27. See, for example, Sider (2001: 120–139 and 2008: Sect. 4) and Hawthorne (2006: 109).

  28. However, it is worth noting that the Priority Monist, who recognizes the existence of non-fundamental macroscopic objects, still faces these problematic cases. Partly for this reason, I believe Existence Monism is more defensible than Priority Monism. However, see Magidor (2016) for a defense of “liberal endurantism”, which is also a precise, principled, and non-anthropocentric account of how objects endure that is compatible with Priority Monism.

  29. See Lewis (1986a: 203–204) and Lewis (1988).

  30. Also see Eddon (2010) for a recent treatment of three different arguments from temporary intrinsics. Eddon argues that all three of the arguments fail.

  31. For a sophisticated development of this worry, see Balashov (2010).

  32. For an overview of the fate of absolute simultaneity in quantum mechanics and quantum gravity, see Monton (2006) and Callender (2017: ch. 4 and 5). See Maudlin (2018) for an argument that the Aharonov-Bohm effect in Quantum Mechanics suggests a preferred foliation of space-time. See Barbour (2012) for an introduction to “Shape Dynamics”, which is empirically equivalent to General Relativity (in contexts where space-time is relevantly “well-behaved”), but it (i) comes with a preferred foliation of space-time and (ii) is (Barbour argues) more amenable to quantization and thus to an eventual theory of quantum gravity. Lastly, see Carroll (2022) for an interpretation of quantum mechanics where a reference-frame-independent notion of time (but not space) is fundamental.

  33. For example, perhaps there are good independent reasons to endorse Presentism, which is often taken to require a relation of absolute simultaneity. See Builes and Impagnatiello (forthcoming) for a recent argument in favor of Presentism, which they argue is more powerful than the standard relativity argument against Presentism. Also see Emery (2019) for an argument that considerations from relativity should no more move a Presentist to Eternalism than they should move an Actualist to Modal Realism. Lastly, Builes and Teitel (forthcoming) have argued that philosophers who reject Qualitativism (the thesis that all fundamental facts are qualitative) have good reasons to believe in absolute simultaneity.

  34. Hall (2020) argues that the Humean analysis of chance is highly revisionary, and Maudlin (2007) has argued that Humeanism is in tension with quantum entanglement. See Bhogal and Perry (2017) and Ney (2021) for ways that Humeans might accommodate the phenomenon of entanglement.

  35. For independent philosophical reasons to think that the world isn’t composed of a continuum of space-time points, see Giberman (2012), Segal (2016), and Builes and Wilson (2022).

  36. Thanks to an anonymous referee for making this point.

  37. Sider’s (2011: ch. 12) discussion suggests an alternative characterization of Humeanism, according to which the world is “fundamentally non-modal”. However, according to GEM, the world is fundamentally non-modal: fundamentally speaking, all there is to the world is an enduring global world-quality. The powers/dispositions that the world-quality grounds are explicitly non-fundamental.

  38. Thanks to an anonymous referee for suggesting the following pluralist hypothesis.

  39. Thanks to Mark Balaguer, Andrew Lee, Jack Spencer, Jessica Wilson, and two anonymous referees for their helpful feedback.

References

  • Armstrong, D. (1983). What is a law of nature? Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. (1989). A combinatorial theory of possibility. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Balashov, Y. (2010). Persistence and spacetime. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Barbour, J. (2012). Shape dynamics: An introduction. In F. Finster, O. Müller, M. Nardmann, J. Tolksdorf, & E. Zeidler (Eds.), Quantum Field Theory and Gravity (pp. 257–297). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bhogal, H. (2020). Nomothetic explanation and Humeanism about laws of nature. In K. Bennett & D. Zimmerman (Eds.), Oxford studies in metaphysics (Vol. 12, pp. 164–202). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bhogal, H., & Perry, Z. (2017). What the Humean should say about entanglement. Noûs, 51(1), 74–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bhogal, H., & Perry, Z. (2021). Humean nomic essentialism. Noûs. https://doi.org/10.1111/nous.12394

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. (2007). Nature’s metaphysics: Laws and properties. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Black, R. (2000). Against Quidditism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 78(1), 87–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brower, J. (2010). Aristotelian endurantism: A new solution to the problem of temporary intrinsics. Mind, 119(476), 883–905.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Builes, D. (2020). Derivatives and consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 27(9–10), 87–103.

    Google Scholar 

  • Builes, D. (2021). The world just is the way it is. The Monist, 104(1), 1–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Builes, D. (2022). The ineffability of induction. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 104(1), 129–149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Builes, D., & Impagnatiello, M. O. (forthcoming). An empirical argument for presentism. In K. Bennett & D. Zimmerman Oxford Studies in Metaphysics Volume 14. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Builes, D., Teitel, T. (forthcoming). Lawful Persistence. Philosophical Perspectives. https://doi.org/10.1111/phpe.12171

  • Builes, D., & Wilson, J. (2022). In defense of Countabilism. Philosophical Studies, 179(7), 2199–2236.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Callender, C. (2017). What makes time special? Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, J. (1994). Laws of nature. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, J. (2008). Nailed to Hume’s cross? In T. Sider, J. Hawthorne, & D. W. Zimmerman (Eds.), Contemporary debates in metaphysics (pp. 67–81). Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, S. (2022). Reality as a vector in Hilbert space. In V. Allori (Ed.), Quantum mechanics and fundamentality: Naturalizing quantum theory between scientific realism and ontological indeterminacy (pp. 211–224). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (2003). The dispositional essentialist view of properties and laws. International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 11(4), 393–413.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (2007). A metaphysics for scientific realism: Knowing the unobservable. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2002). Does conceivability entail possibility? In T. S. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Conceivability and possibility (pp. 145–200). Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2006). Perception and the fall from Eden. In T. S. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Perceptual experience (pp. 49–125). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2015). Panpsychism and Panprotopsychism. In T. Alter & Y. Nagasawa (Eds.), Consciousness in the physical world: perspectives on Russellian Monism (pp. 246–276). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coates, A. (2020). Making sense of powerful qualities. Synthese, 198(9), 8347–8363.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dasgupta, S. (2017). Can we do without fundamental individuals? Yes. In E. Barnes (Ed.), Current controversies in metaphysics (pp. 7–23). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dorst, C. (2019). Humean laws, explanatory circularity, and the aim of scientific explanation. Philosophical Studies, 176(10), 2657–2679.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1977). Laws of nature. Philosophy of Science, 44(2), 248–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eddon, M. (2010). Three arguments from temporary intrinsics. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 81(3), 605–619.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Emery, N. (2019). Actualism without presentism? Not by way of the relativity objection. Noûs, 53(4), 963–986.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Emery, N. (forthcoming). The governing conception of laws. Ergo.

  • Friend, T. (2021). Why I’m not a Humean. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly. https://doi.org/10.1111/papq.12398

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giberman, D. (2012). Against zero-dimensional material objects (and other bare particulars). Philosophical Studies, 160(2), 305–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, I., & Pooley, O. (2006). Relativistic Persistence. Philosophical Perspectives, 20(1), 157–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goff, P. (2017). Consciousness and fundamental reality. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goff, P. (2020). Revelation, consciousness+ and the phenomenal powers view. Topoi, 39(5), 1089–1092.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hall, N. (2020). Chance and the Great Divide. In S. Dasgupta, R. Dotan, & B. Weslake (Eds.), Current controversies in philosophy of science (pp. 123–142). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haslanger, S. (1989a). Endurance and temporary intrinsics. Analysis, 49(3), 119–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haslanger, S. (1989b). Persistence, change, and explanation. Philosophical Studies, 56(1), 1–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne, J., Wasserman, R., & Scala, M. (2004). Recombination, causal constraints, and Humean Supervenience: An argument for temporal parts? In D. Zimmerman (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaphysics 1 (pp. 301–318). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne, J. (2006). Metaphysical essays. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Heil, J. (2003). From an ontological point of view. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Heil, J. (2010). Powerful qualities. In A. Marmodoro (Ed.), The metaphysics of powers: Their grounding and their manifestations. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heller, M. (1990). The ontology of physical objects: Four dimensional hunks of matter. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hicks, M. T. (2021). Breaking the explanatory circle. Philosophical Studies, 178(2), 533–557.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hildebrand, T. (2016). Two types of Quidditism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 94(3), 516–532.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ismael, J., & Schaffer, J. (2020). Quantum Holism: Nonseparability as common ground. Synthese, 197(10), 4131–4160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, M. (1987). Is there a problem about persistence? Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 61(1), 107–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kimpton-Nye, S. (2021). Reconsidering the dispositional essentialist canon. Philosophical Studies, 178(10), 3421–3441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kovacs, D. M. (2020). The oldest solution to the circularity problem for Humeanism about the laws of nature. Synthese, 198(9), 1–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J. (2016). Structural realism. In The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2016 Edition), edited by Edward N. Zalta. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/structural-realism.

  • Lange, M. (2013). Grounding, scientific explanation, and Humean laws. Philosophical Studies, 164(1), 255–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2018). Transitivity, self-explanation, and the explanatory circularity argument against Humean accounts of natural law. Synthese, 195(3), 1337–1353.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Langsam, H. (2011). The wonder of consciousness: Understanding the mind through philosophical reflection. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Langton, R. (2001). Kantian humility: Our Ignorance of things in themselves. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Langton, R. (2004). Elusive knowledge of things in themselves. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 82(1), 129–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1983). Philosophical papers (Vol. 1). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986a). On the plurality of worlds. Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986b). Philosophical papers (Vol. II). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1988). Rearrangement of particles: Reply to Lowe. Analysis, 48(2), 65–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1992). Armstrong on combinatorial possibility. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 70(2), 211–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (2009). Ramseyan Humility. In D. Braddon-Mithcell & R. Nola (Eds.), Conceptual analysis and philosophical naturalism (pp. 203–222). MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magidor, O. (2016). Endurantism vs perdurantism?: A debate reconsidered. Noûs, 50(3), 509–532.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, C. B. (2008). The Mind in Nature. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maudlin, T. (2007). The metaphysics within physics. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Maudlin, T. (2018). Ontological clarity via canonical presentation: Electromagnetism and the Aharonov-Bohm effect. Entropy, 20(6), 465.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mellor, D. H. (1981). Real time. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merricks, T. (1994). Endurance and indiscernibility. Journal of Philosophy, 91(4), 165–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, K. (2004). Enduring special relativity. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 42(3), 349–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Monton, B. (2006). Presentism and quantum gravity. In D. Dieks (Ed.), The Ontology of Spacetime (pp. 263–280). Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mørch, H. H. (2014). Panpsychism and causation: A new argument and a solution to the combination problem. PhD Thesis, Oslo.

  • Mørch, H. H. (2017). The evolutionary argument for phenomenal powers. Philosophical Perspectives, 31(1), 293–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mørch, H. H. (2018). Does dispositionalism entail panpsychism? Topoi, 39(5), 1073–1088.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mørch, H. H. (2019). The argument for panpsychism from experience of causation. In W. Seager (Ed.), The Routledge handbook of panpsychism (pp. 269–284). Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, S. (2004). Laws in nature. Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, S. (2009). Powers and persistence. In L. Honnefelder, E. Runggaldier, & B. Schick (Eds.), Unity and time in metaphysics (pp. 223–236). De Gruyter.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ney, A. (2021). The world in the wave function: A metaphysics for quantum physics. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Oderberg, D. (1993). The metaphysics of identity over time. St. Martin’s Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1927). The analysis of matter. Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2007). From Nihilism to Monism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 85(2), 175–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2010a). Monism: The priority of the whole. Philosophical Review, 119(1), 31–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2010b). The internal relatedness of all things. Mind, 119(474), 341–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2010c). The least discerning and most promiscuous Truthmaker. Philosophical Quarterly, 60(239), 307–324.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2013). The action of the whole. Aristotelian Society Supplementary, 87(1), 67–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2017). The ground between the gaps. Philosophers’ Imprint, 17(11), 1–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Segal, A. (2016). A Puzzle about points. Philosophical Perspectives, 30(1), 349–365.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shumener, E. (2019). Laws of nature, explanation, and semantic circularity. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 70(3), 787–815.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (2001). Four dimensionalism: An ontology of persistence and time. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (2008). Temporal Parts. In T. Sider, J. Hawthorne, & D. Zimmerman (Eds.), Contemporary debates in metaphysics (pp. 241–262). Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (2011). Writing the book of the world. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (1980). Causality and properties. In P. van Inwagen (Ed.), Time and cause (pp. 109–135). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, G. (2006). Realistic Monism—Why physicalism entails panpsychism. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 13(10–11), 3–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, G. (2008). The identity of the categorical and the dispositional. Analysis, 68(4), 271–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, G. (2014). The secret connexion: Causation, Realism, and David Hume: Revised Edition. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, H. (2018). Powerful qualities and pure powers. Philosophical Studies, 175(6), 1423–1440.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tooley, M. (1977). The nature of laws. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 7(4), 667–698.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tugby, M. (2021). Grounding theories of powers. Synthese, 198(12), 11187–11216.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tugby, M. (2022). Putting properties first. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. (1989). Laws and symmetry. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, N. (2019). The powers metaphysic. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, J. (2009). Resemblance-based resources for reductive singularism (or: How to be a Humean singularist about causation). The Monist, 92(1), 153–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, J. (2010). What Is Hume’s Dictum, and why believe it? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 80(3), 595–637.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, J. (2015). Hume’s Dictum and metaphysical modality: Lewis’s combinatorialism. In B. Loewer & J. Schaffer (Eds.), The Blackwell Companion to David Lewis (pp. 138–158). Blackwell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Zimmerman, D. (1998). Temporary intrinsics and presentism. In P. van Inwagen & D. Zimmrman (Eds.), Metaphysics: The big questions (pp. 206–219). Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David Builes.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Builes, D. A Humean Non-Humeanism. Philos Stud 180, 1031–1048 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-023-01927-5

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-023-01927-5

Keywords

Navigation