Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Biodiversity vs. paleodiversity measurements: the incommensurability problem

  • Paper in the Philosophy of the Life Sciences
  • Published:
European Journal for Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Estimating whether the Earth’s biota is in the middle of a crisis relies heavily on comparisons between present and past data about biodiversity or biodiversity surrogates. Although the past is a crucial source of information to assess the severity of the current biodiversity crisis, substantive conceptual and methodological questions remain about how paleodiversity and biodiversity are to be properly compared. I argue that to justify claims of a current biodiversity crisis is harder than it appears. More precisely, I claim that paleodiversity measurements are incommensurable with contemporary measurements, given the different ways that biodiversity is conceptualized and operationalized. I conclude by proposing three possible ways of overcoming this incommensurability problem.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This type of conceptualizing and measuring species richness mostly applies to plant and animal community at a macroscale. Microbial diversity cannot be measured in this way (see O’Malley 2014; Malaterre 2013)

  2. Suppose you sample a plot p twice, obtaining: a) 100 individuals belonging to 28 species at time t1; b) 200 individuals belonging to 36 species an time t2. According to S, the second dataset is more diverse. Nevertheless, this conclusion might be an artifact of simply having sampled more individuals.

  3. Suppose you have two datasets of 100 individuals, each made up of three species A, B and C, but represented respectively by 30 As , 30 Bs, 40 Cs, and 90 As, 10 Bs, 10 Cs. The diversity value resulting from applying Menhinick’s index to the first and second dataset will show two equally diverse communities (dataset one: \(D_{Mn} =3/10\); dataset 2: \(D_{Mn} =3/10\)).

  4. If an evenly distributed community of one million species were to be annihilated except for 100 species, the \(D_{Gini}\) will drop from 0.999999 to 0.99 (1% drop)—not representing the real damage sustained by the community (Daly 2018, p.11). For a fuller philosophical review, see Crupi (2019) and Justus (2011).

  5. This statement does not distinguish between various purposes of biodiversity measure, which might validate any of the indices above for a specific purpose. Assessing whether single indices can be validated for specific purposes is beyond the scope of this paper.

  6. For example, Pierre Taberlet and colleagues (2012), using large-scale multispecies vegetation data, demonstrated that species richness does not co-vary with genetic diversity, another important aspect of biodiversity that should be accounted for in a biodiversity operationalization. Similarly, ecologist Helmut Hillebrand and collegues argue that measurements of species richness are not informative enough of biodiversity fluctuations and crisis as they “changes in species richness and its underlying components do not necessarily correlate with species compositional turnover” (Hillebrand et al. 2018, p.171), which constitute a critical metric in ecological studies.

  7. Faith’s PD index is only one of the many measures of biodiversity conceived as phylogenetic distance. These measurements are made possible because of the increasing availability of molecular and genetic data (see Vellend 2011)

  8. Some exceptions are Bokulich (2021) and Watkins (2021)

  9. Bokulich also argues that paleocurves are better thought of not as representations of taxa fluctuations obtained from “pure data”. Rather, they should be conceived of as “data models”, namely as the outcome of filtering and improving inevitably incomplete data using post-collection techniques that have been shown to be effective. This improved data displays higher degree of fidelity to the phenomenon of interest and is more useful to paleontologists than raw taxic diversity estimates.

  10. The old trope in paleontology to assert that the fossil record is not an exhaustive or reliable source of evidence is still alive. This is unfortunate because eminent studies oppose this view and demonstrate that the fossil record can adequately serve specific purposes. For example, Gould and Eldredge most famously defended the completeness of the fossil record and used it to overturn traditional views on the mode and tempo of macroevolutionary patterns (Gould and Eldredge 1972). Furthermore, sophisticated analytical techniques have been developed to deal with incompleteness (Kidwell and Holland 2002), such as reconstructing phylogenetic trees for specific lineages (Woolley et al. 2022).

  11. It should be made clear here that talking about an ongoing biodiversity crisis and talking about entering a mass extinction are two separate issues. A mass extinction event is usually characterized by high rates of species extinction unbalanced by species origination or by a significant increase over the background extinction rate. Bocchi et al. (in press) provides a meticulous philosophical analysis of the concept of mass extinction and the evidence needed to support the claim that we are entering an extinction event comparable to those of the past). A biodiversity crisis is a more complex and multifaceted issue to assess than a mass extinction event. As I have already hinted at and as I will make explicit in Section 4, the former requires a type of evidence that is not reducible to evidence for an escalation of species extinction.

  12. In Sepkoski’s historical reconstruction, E.O Wilson championed the past-present analogy to enhance his scientific agenda. Wilson and other environmentalists (Barbara Ward, René Dubos,Paul and Anne Erlich, David Ehrenfeld, Norman Myers) strongly advocated for the analogy regardless of their being aware of the speculative character of their estimates, as well as the protestations of paleontologists.

  13. Species loss is a definitional feature of a mass extinction, which are catastrophic events measured on a global scale during which an meaningful portion of extant species went extinct. For a biodiversity crisis to be occurring, this condition does not necessarily need to be met (Racki 2021).

  14. Some studies can quite accurately represent species fluctuations, but are generally rare and focused only on restricted numbers of taxa at lower spatial scales. See Fan et al., (2020)

  15. Even if excellent work has been done in modelling how higher taxa track the diversity trends of lower taxa since the paleobiology revolution in the 1980s Grantham (2009), the strength of some of these methods in describing species patterns from genus or family patters are successful only when an accurate identification of species, genus and family has been carried out (de Oliveira Jr et al. 2020, p.8). This excludes the possibility of applying some of these method to the fossil record, where higher taxa and not species are normally identified

  16. I am grateful to Thomas Hegna for a useful email exchange about genera extinction.

  17. A great deal has been written about what Kuhn and Feyerabend meant by “incommensurability”, as well as about Kuhn’s reformulation of the concept from The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1970) to The Road since Structure (2000). A conceptual distinction, introduced by Sankey and Hoyningen-Huene (2001) is that between semantic (or taxonomic) and methodological incommenesurability. Two theories are said “semantically incommensurable” when the theoretical terms they employ cannot be co-opted in other theories, because their definition is embedded within the specific context within which that concept was developed (see Sankey and Hoyningen-Huene 2001, p. ix). The semantic aspect of incommensurability is the most commonly mentioned in philosophy. Two theories are said “methodologically incommensurable” if they abide by different standards when it comes to adjudicating which, of two competing theories, best fits the data (see Sankey and Hoyningen-Huene 2001, p. xiii).

  18. This meaning of incommensurability is still bound to that Kuhn adopted in Structure as a holistic concept expressing a possible relationship between two heterogeneous domains (see also Oberheim & Hoyningen-Huene 2018; Patton 2015).

References

  • Alroy, J., Aberhan, M., Bottjer, D. J., Foote, M., Fürsich, F. T., Harries, P. J., Hendy, A. J. W., Holland, S. M., Ivany, L. C., Kiessling, W., Kosnik, M. A., Marshall, C. R., McGowan, A. J., Miller, A. I., Olszewski, T. D., Patzkowsky, M. E., Peters, S. E., Villier, L., Wagner, P. J., Bonuso, N., Borkow, P. S., Brenneis, B., Clapham, M. E., Fall, L. M., Ferguson, C. A., Hanson, V. L., Krug, A. Z., Layou, K. M., Leckey, E. H., Nürnberg, S., Powers, C. M., Sessa, J. A., Simpson, C., Tomašových, A., Visaggi, C. C. (2008). Phanerozoic Trends in the Global Diversity of Marine Invertebrates. Science, 321 (5885), 97–100. Retrieved 2021 10–13, from https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1156963

  • Barnosky, A. D., Hadly, E. A., Gonzalez, P., Head, J., Polly, P. D., Lawing, A. M., Eronen, J. T., Ackerly, D. D., Alex, K., Biber, E., Blois, J., Brashares, J., Ceballos, G., Davis, E., Dietl, G. P., Dirzo, R., Doremus, H., Fortelius, M., Greene, H. W., Hellmann, J., Hickler, T., Jackson, S. T., Kemp, M., Koch, P. L., Kremen, C., Lindsey, E. L., Looy, C., Marshall, C. R., Mendenhall, C., Mulch, A., Mychajliw, A. M., Nowak, C., Ramakrishnan, U., Schnitzler, J., Das Shrestha, K., Solari, K., Stegner, L., Stegner, M. A., Stenseth, N. C., Wake, M. H., Zhang, Z. (2017). Merging paleobiology with conservation biology to guide the future of terrestrial ecosystems. Science, 355(6325), eaah4787. Retrieved 2021-10-13, from https://doi.org/10.1126/science.aah4787

  • Barnosky, A. D., Matzke, N., Tomiya, S., Wogan, G. O. U., Swartz, B., Quental, T. B., Marshall, C., McGuire, J. L., Lindsey, E. L., Maguire, K. C., Mersey, B., Ferrer, E. A. (2011). Has the Earth’s sixth mass extinction already arrived?. Nature, 471(7336) 51–57, Retrieved 2021-10-13, from https://doi.org/10.1038/nature09678

  • Benson, R. B. J., & Mannion, P. D. (2012). Multi-variate models are essential for understanding vertebrate diversification in deep time. Biology Letters, 8(1), 127–130. https://doi.org/10.1098/rsbl.2011.0460

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bocchi, F., Bokulich, A., Castillo-Brache, L., Grand-Pierre & Watkins, A. (forthcoming). Are we in a sixth mass extinction? the challenges of answering and value of asking. British Journal for Philosophy of Science

  • Bokulich, A. (2021). Using models to correct data: paleodiversity and the fossil record. Synthese, 198(S24) 5919–5940. Retrieved 2022-01-30 from https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1820-x

  • Bokulich, A., & Parker, W. (2021). Data models, representation and adequacy-for-purpose. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 11(1), 1–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ceballos, G., Ehrlich, P. R., Barnosky, A. D., García, A., Pringle, R. M., Palmer, T. M. (2015). Accelerated modern human-induced species losses: Entering the sixth mass extinction. Science Advances, 1(5) e1400253. Retrieved 2022-02-04, from https://doi.org/10.1126/sciadv.1400253

  • Crupi, V. (2019) Measures of biological diversity: Overview and unified framework

  • Daly, A., Baetens, J., De Baets, B., (2018) Ecological Diversity: Measuring the Unmeasurable. Mathematics, 6(7)119, Retrieved 2021-10-13, from https://doi.org/10.3390/math6070119

  • de Oliveira Jr, S. S., Ortega, J. C. G., dos Santos Ribas, L. G., Lopes, V. G., & Bini, L. M. (2020). Higher taxa are sufficient to represent biodiversity patterns. Ecological Indicators, 111, 105994.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Ricqlés, A., Padian, K., Knoll, F., Horner, J. R. (2008) On the origin of high growth rates in archosaurs and their ancient relatives: Complementary histological studies on Triassic archosauriforms and the problem of a “phylogenetic signal” in bone histology. Annales de Paléontologie, 94(2)57–76. Retrieved 2022-02-04, from https://doi.org/10.1016/j.annpal.2008.03.002

  • Edwards, P. N. (2010) A vast machine: computer models, climate data, and the politics of global warming. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press. (OCLC: ocn430736496)

  • Faith, D. P. (1992) Conservation evaluation and phylogenetic diversity. Biological Conservation, 61(1) 1-10. Retrieved 2021-10-13, from https://doi.org/10.1016/0006-3207(92)91201-3

  • Fan, J.-X., Shen, S.-Z., Erwin, D. H., Sadler, P. M., MacLeod, N., Cheng, Q.-M., Hou, X.-D., Yang, J., Wang, X.-D., Wang, Y., et al. (2020). A high-resolution summary of cambrian to early triassic marine invertebrate biodiversity. Science, 367(6475), 272–277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forey, P. L., Fortey, R. A., Kenrick, P., Smith, A. B. (2004). Taxonomy and fossils: a critical appraisal. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series B: Biological Sciences 359 (1444) 639–653, https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2003.1453,

  • Gingerich, P. D. (1979). The Stratophenetic Approach to Phylogeny Reconstruction in Vertebrate Paleontology. In J. Cracraft & N. Eldredge (Eds.), Phylogenetic Analysis and Paleontology (pp. 41-78). Columbia University Press. Retrieved 2022-02-04, from https://doi.org/10.7312/crac92306-004

  • Gini, C. (1912). Variabilitá e mutabilitá (variability and mutability) (p. 156). Bologna: Cuppini.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gleason, H. A. (1922). On the relation between species and area. Ecology, 3(2), 158–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J., & Eldredge, N. (1972). Punctuated equilibria: an alternative to phyletic gradualism. Models in paleobiology, 1972, 82–115.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grantham, T. (2009). Taxic paleobiology and the pursuit of a unified evolutionary theory. The Paleobiology Revolution, 215-238.

  • Hartmann, K., & André, J., (2013). Should evolutionary history guide conservation? Biodiversity and Conservation, 22 (2), 449-458. Retrieved 2021-10-13, from https://doi.org/10.1007/s10531-012-0422-z

  • Hillebrand, H., Blasius, B., Borer, E. T., Chase, J. M., Downing, J. A., Eriksson, B. K., Filstrup, C. T., Harpole, W. S., Hodapp, D., Larsen, S., Lewandowska, A. M., Seabloom, E. W., Van de Waal, D. B., Ryabov, A. B. (2018). Biodiversity change is uncoupled from species richness trends: Consequences for conservation and monitoring. Journal of Applied Ecology, 55 (1), 169-184. Retrieved 2022-02-01, from https://doi.org/10.1111/1365-2664.12959

  • Justus, J. (2011). A Case Study in Concept Determination: Ecological Diversity. In: Handbook of The Philosophy of Science: Philosophy of Ecology (pp. 147-168). San Diego: North Holland: Elsevier.

  • Kidwell, S. M., & Holland, S. M. (2002). The quality of the fossil record: implications for evolutionary analyses. Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics, 33(1), 561–588.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1970). The structure of scientific revolutions (Vol. 111). Chicago, University of Chicago Press.

  • Lane, A., & Benton, M. (2003). Taxonomic level as a determinant of the shape of the phanerozoic marine biodiversity curve. The American Naturalist , 162 (3), 265-276. Retrieved 2021-10-13, from https://doi.org/10.1086/377188

  • Lean, C., & Maclaurin, J. (2016). The value of phylogenetic diversity. In Biodiversity conservation and phylogenetic systematics (pp. 19-37). Springer, Cham.

  • Leonelli, S. (2016). Data-centric biology: a philosophical study. Chicago ; London: The University of Chicago Press.

  • Louys, J. (Ed.). (2012). Paleontology in ecology and conservation. Berlin Heidelberg: Springer.

  • Maclaurin, J., & Sterelny, K. (2008). What is biodiversity? Chicago: University of Chicago Press. (OCLC: ocn156874812)

  • Magurran, A. E., & McGill, B. J. (Eds.). (2011). Biological diversity: frontiers in measurement and assessment. Oxford ; New York: Oxford University Press. (OCLC: ocn642283168)

  • Malaterre, C. (2013). Microbial diversity and the “lower-limit’’ problem of biodiversity. Biology & Philosophy, 28(2), 219–239.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Margalef, R. (1958). Information theory in biology. General Systems Yearbook, 3, 36–71.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menhinick, E. F. (1964). A comparison of some species-individuals diversity indices applied to samples of field insects. Ecology, 45 (4), 859-861. Retrieved 2021-10-13, from https://doi.org/10.2307/1934933

  • Milot, E., Béchet, A., & Maris, V. (2020). The dimensions of evolutionary potential in biological conservation. Evolutionary Applications, 13 (6), 1363-1379. Retrieved 2021-12-05, from https://doi.org/10.1111/eva.12995

  • Mora, C., Tittensor, D. P., Adl, S., Simpson, A. G. B., & Worm, B. (2011). How Many Species Are There on Earth and in the Ocean? PLoS Biology, 9 (8), e1001127. Retrieved 2021-10-13, from https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pbio.1001127

  • Morlon, H., Parsons, T. L., & Plotkin, J. B. (2011). Reconciling molecular phylogenies with the fossil record. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 108 (39), 16327-16332. Retrieved 2022-02-03, from https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1102543108

  • Oberheim, E., & Hoyningen-Huene, P. (2018). The incommensurability of scientific theories. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2018 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/incommensurability/

  • Odenbaugh, J. (2021). Conservation biology. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2020 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2021/entries/conservation-biology/

  • O’Malley, M. (2014). Philosophy of microbiology. Cambridge University Press.

  • Patton, L. (2015). Incommensurability and the bonfire of the meta-theories: Response to mizrahi. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective, 4(7), 51–58.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pereira, H. M., Ferrier, S., Walters, M., Geller, G. N., Jongman, R. H. G., Scholes, R. J., Bruford, M. W., Brummitt, N., Butchart, S. H. M., Cardoso, A. C., Coops, N. C., Dulloo, E., Faith, D. P., Freyhof, J., Gregory, R. D., Heip, C., Hoft, R., Hurtt, G., Jetz, W., Karp, D. S., McGeoch, M. A., Obura, D., Onoda, Y., Pettorelli, N., Reyers, B., Sayre, R., Scharlemann, J. P. W., Stuart, S. N., Turak, E., Walpole, M., Wegmann, M. (2013) Essential biodiversity variables. Science, 339 (6117), 277-278. Retrieved 2021-10-13, from https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1229931

  • Pio, D. V., Broennimann, O., Barraclough, T. G., Reeves, G., Rebelo, A. G., Thuiller, W., Guisan, A., & Salamin, N. (2011). Spatial predictions of phylogenetic diversity in conservation decision making. Conservation Biology, 25(6), 1229–1239.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plotnick, R. E., Smith, F. A., & Lyons, S. K. (2016). The fossil record of the sixth extinction. Ecology Letters, 19 (5), 546-553. Retrieved 2021-10-13, from https://doi.org/10.1111/ele.12589

  • Racki, G. (2021). Big 5 Mass Extinctions. In Encyclopedia of Geology (pp. 603-616). Elsevier. Retrieved 2022-01-30, from https://doi.org/10.1016/B978-0-12-409548-9.12028-7

  • Raup, D. M., & Sepkoski, J. J. (1982). Mass Extinctions in the Marine Fossil Record. Science, 215 (4539), 1501-1503. Retrieved 2021-10-13, from https://doi.org/10.1126/science.215.4539.1501

  • Reydon, T. A. (2019). Are species good units for biodiversity studies and conservation efforts? In: From assessing to conserving biodiversity (pp. 167-193). Springer, Cham.

  • Sankey, H., & Hoyningen-Huene, P. (2001). Introduction: Incommensurability and related matters. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 216, 7–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Santana, C. (2014). Save the planet: eliminate biodiversity. Biology & Philosophy, 29 (6), 761-780. Retrieved 2021-10-13, from https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-014-9426-2

  • Santana, C. (2018). Biodiversity is a chimera, and chimeras aren’t real. Biology & Philosophy, 33 (1-2), 15. Retrieved 2021-10-24, from https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-018-9626-2

  • Sarkar, S. (2005). Biodiversity and Environmental Philosophy: An Introduction., 278

  • Sepkoski, D. (2020). Catastrophic thinking: extinction and the value of diversity. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Simpson, E. H. (1949). Measurement of diversity. nature, 163(4148), 688–688.

    Google Scholar 

  • Soulé, M. E. (1985). What is conservation biology? BioScience, 35(11), 727–734.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taberlet, P., Zimmermann, N. E., Englisch, T., Tribsch, A., Holderegger, R., Alvarez, N., Niklfeld, H., Coldea, G., Mirek, Z., Moilanen, A., Ahlmer, W., Marsan, P. A., Bona, E., Bovio, M., Choler, P., Cieślak, E., Colli, L., Cristea, V., Dalmas, J.P., Frajman, B., Garraud, L., Gaudeul, M., Gielly, L., Gutermann, W., Jogan, N., Kagalo, A. A., Korbecka, G., Küpfer, P., Lequette, B., Letz, D. R., Manel, S., Mansion, G., Marhold, K., Martini, F., Negrini, R., Niño, F., Paun, O., Pellecchia, M., Perico, G., Piȩkoś Mirkowa, H., Prosser, F., Puşcaş, M., Ronikier, M., Scheuerer, M., Schneeweiss, G. M., Schönswetter, P., Schratt Ehrendorfer, L., Schüpfer, F., Selvaggi, A., Steinmann, K., Thiel Egenter, C., Loo, M., Winkler, M., Wohlgemuth, T., Wraber, T., Gugerli, F. (2012). Genetic diversity in widespread species is not congruent with species richness in alpine plant communities. Ecology Letters, 15 (12), 1439-1448. Retrieved 2022-02-01, from https://doi.org/10.1111/ele.12004

  • Takacs, D. (1996). The idea of biodiversity: philosophies of paradise

  • Tal, E. (2013). Old and new problems in philosophy of measurement. Philosophy Compass, 8(12), 1159–1173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomas, K. (2000). The road since structure

  • Vellend, M., Cornwell, W. K., Magnuson-Ford, K., & Mooers, A. (2011). Measuring phylogenetic biodiversity, 14

  • Watkins, A. (2021). The Epistemic Value of the Living Fossils Concept. Philosophy of Science, 88 (5), 1221-1233. Retrieved 2022-01-30, from https://doi.org/10.1086/714875

  • Wilson, E. O. (Ed.). (1988). Biodiversity. Washington, D.C: National Academy Press. (Meeting Name: National Forum on BioDiversity)

  • Woolley, C. H., Thompson, J. R., Wu, Y. -H., Bottjer, D. J., Smith, N. D. (2022). A biased fossil record can preserve reliable phylogenetic signal. Paleobiology, 1–16

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to Alisa Bokulich, Aja Watkins and the Phi-Geo research group, as well as the audience at the 2021 EPSA conference in Turin. I am especially grateful to Emily Parke, Lydia Patton, and two anonymous reviewers for useful feedback on a previous version of this manuscript.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Federica Bocchi.

Ethics declarations

Ethical Statement

The author declares no conflict of interest. This research did not receive any financial support. No human or animal trials were performed in this study.

Additional information

Publisher’s note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

This article belongs to the Topical Collection: EPSA21: Selected papers from the biennial conference in Turin

Guest Editors: A.C. Love, C. Marchionni, M. Redei, J. Williamson

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bocchi, F. Biodiversity vs. paleodiversity measurements: the incommensurability problem. Euro Jnl Phil Sci 12, 64 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-022-00494-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-022-00494-6

Keywords

Navigation