Skip to main content
Log in

Reasons-responsiveness, modality and rational blind spots

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Many think it is plausible that agents enjoy freedom and responsibility with respect to their actions in virtue of being reasons-responsive. Extant accounts spell out reasons-responsiveness (RR) as a general modal property. The agent is responsive to reasons for and against ϕ-ing, according to this idea, if they ϕ in accordance with the balance of reasons in a suitable proportion of possible situations. This paper argues that freedom and responsibility are not grounded in such modal properties on the basis of a phenomenon I call ‘rational blind spots’. Agents have highly specific local blockages (or openings) that prevent them from seeing or reacting for a particular type of reason. When these blind spots are triggered, agents fail to be responsive to reasons in the sense relevant to freedom and responsibility. Thus, we judge that they are not free and responsible. But bind spots don’t remove the agent’s possession of general modal RR properties. Thus, extant accounts of reasons-responsiveness render the incorrect result that the agents in these cases remain responsible because they remain responsive to reasons in a general sense.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Modal accounts include Fischer and Ravizza (1998), Smith (1997, 2003); Vihvelin (2004, 2013), and many others. Differences within these views are discussed below.

  2. This is of course the structure of a Frankfurt Case, originally from Frankfurt (1969).

  3. This is also how Victor Tadros puts what is essentially the same point in Tadros (ms).

  4. If you think this is linguistically odd, note that we do use “responsive” in exactly such a way in other contexts, such as when paramedics say that a patient is responsive (by which they mean ‘is responding’) or when I say my computer is unresponsive (by which I mean’is not responding’).

  5. You might notice that these descriptions are somewhat vague about whether they express what is called in epistemology a ‘safety condition’ or a ‘sensitivity condition’. This difference isn’t discussed in work on reasons-responsiveness (with some exceptions in the work on moral worth, such as Sorensen (2014), Howard (forthcoming). I don’t have the space here to address this issue, but it won’t have impact on my arguments below anyway.

  6. To my knowledge, Manley and Wasserman (2008) were the first to propose a suitable proportion clause in the literature on dispositions.

  7. Nelkin and Brink (2013) refer to this middle ground as ‘the Goldilocks standard’.

  8. Masks are discussed in Johnston (1992) and Fara (2005), finks are discussed in Martin (1994) and Lewis (1997). Johnston (1992), Martin (1994), Lewis (1997), Bird (1998), Fara (2001) all present versions of mimicking cases.

  9. I take the parlance of auspiciousness from Fisher (2013). Similar ideas are expressed slightly differently in terms of conditions ideal for manifestation (Mumford ,1998, 88–90), in terms of conditions typical of manifestation (Malzkorn, 2000, 456–459), or typical for the trigger circumstances to occur (Fara, 2005). There are also ‘‘normal circumstances’’ (Bird, 1998, pp. 233–4), ‘‘standard conditions’’ (Gundersen, 2002, p. 407), ‘‘background conditions’’ (Cross, 2005, p. 324), and ‘‘ordinary conditions’’ (Choi, 2009, p. 576).

  10. Fara may have been unfairly lumped in with these accounts, but he is mentioned in Clarke (2008) which coined the term New Dispositionalism and is now stuck, for better or worse, with the other names on the list.

  11. The phrase ‘for that reason’ hides an enormous problem for reasons-responsiveness views which I cannot touch on here, but which is related to the discussion in this paper. The problem getting the relation designated by the ‘for’ in the formulation right is crucial to the concept of responding to reasons, which is why I should not appear in the counterfactuals used to analyse that concept. Analyses that do this will appear circular.

  12. See for example Judisch (2005), McKenna (2000, 2001), Shabo (2005), Watson (2001). Fischer (2005, 154n3) and Fischer (2006, 228) seems sympathetic to amendments that change or omit the “all of a piece” clause.

  13. Manley and Wasserman (2008) introduced such cases under the self-explanatory label of Achilles Heels, which they think are exhibited even by low-level dispositional properties like sturdiness.

  14. Todd & Tognazzini (2008) present similar cases of blindness.

  15. See Audi (1990) and Arpaly (2000).

  16. Cohen and Handfield (2007) use a very similar case, which they take to be a version of Frankfurt’s willing addict, to argue that we cannot abstract away from intrinsic interferences.

  17. Fischer & Ravizza (1998, 81) are explicit about such a clause, but their version merely requires that the action count as intentional. This is too weak. The agents in my cases all act intentionally, yet they fail to respond. I will therefore assume that the actual-sequence clause must specify that the relevant action is in fact a response to reasons—which is a stronger requirement than the requirement for intentional action.

  18. Insofar as this strategy is supposed to differentiate state-of-the-art reasons-responsiveness views from traditional accounts, which emphasise the power of the agent to actualise alternative pathways into the future, the New Dispositionalists can agree with Fischer & Ravizza about this. They, too, give an account of dispositional properties present in the actual sequence—the rational abilities and dispositions that agents possess. How exactly Fischer & Ravizza and the New Dispositionalism are in disagreement is a hairy question that goes beyond the scope of this paper (see Heering, 2021 for an attempt to answer it).

  19. For example, we might think that Razvan’s and Milena’s actions reveal their quality of character (Strawson, 1962), or that their relevant actions are still rationally assessable despite their loss of control along the lines of Smith (2005).

  20. The distinction between global and local capacities is labelled and understood slightly differently by different authors. Berofsky (2002) distinguishes between ‘type and token’ abilities, Vihvelin (2013) distinguishes between ‘narrow and wide abilities’. Maier (2014) and Jaster (2020) distinguish between ‘general and specific’ abilities. Austin (1956), 218 famously identifies ‘all in’ abilities. In the context of this paper, it is important that I use the labels ‘general’ and ‘specific’ to denote an orthogonal distinction concerning the specificity of the content of the ability—what it is an ability to do.

  21. For this sort of worry, see also Clarke (2008; Whittle 2010; Franklin 2011).

  22. Choi (2005, 2006, 2012).

  23. Levy and Mckenna (2009) also identify this dialectical move as crucial in the current debate.

  24. We might even specify these differences away, in which case we are left with a set of situations that has only one member: the actual situation.

  25. Fischer (2004, 169) argues that this means his theory does not need to provide clear individuation criteria for mechanisms.

  26. This is basically how Fischer and Ravizza (1998, 74) treat cases similar (but not identical) to my blind spot cases. In these cases, an agent suddenly resists the urge to take a drug because of “more energy and focus”. Fischer and Ravizza conclude that the agent with more energy and focus acts from a different mechanism. The present point is that blind spot cases undermine this proposal.

References

  • Arpaly, N. (2000). On acting rationally against one’s best judgment. Ethics, 110(3), 488–513.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Audi, R. (1990). Weakness of will and rational action. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 68(3), 270–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J. L. (1956). Ifs and cans. Proceedings of the British Academy, 42, 107–132.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berofsky, B. (2002). Ifs, cans, and free will: The issues. In R. H. Kane (Ed.), The oxford handbook of free will (pp. 181–201). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. (1998). Dispositions and antidotes. Philosophical Quarterly, 48, 227–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brink, D. O., & Nelkin, D. K. (2013). Fairness and the architecture of responsibility. Oxford Studies in Agency and Responsibility, 1, 284–313.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Choi, S. (2005). Dispositions and mimickers. Philosophical Studies, 122(2), 183–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Choi, S. (2006). The simple vs. reformed conditional analysis of dispositions. Synthese, 148(2), 369–379.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Choi, S. (2009). The conditional analysis of dispositions and the intrinsic dispositions thesis. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 78, 568–590.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Choi, S. (2012). Intrinsic finks and dispositional/categorical distinction. Nous, 46(2), 289–325.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, R. (2008). Dispositions, abilities to act, and free will: the New dispositionalism. Mind, 118, 323–351.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, D., & Handfield, T. (2007). Finking Frankfurt. Philosophical Studies, 135(3), 363–374.

  • Cross, T. (2005). What is a disposition? Synthese, 144, 321–341.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fara, M. (2001). Dispositions and their ascriptions. Dissertation, Princeton University, Princeton.

  • Fara, M. (2005). Dispositions and habituals. Noûs, 39(1), 43–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fara, M. (2008). Masked abilities and compatibilism. Mind, 117(468), 843–865.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J. M. (2004). Responsibility and manipulation. The Journal of Ethics, 8(2), 145–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J. M. (2005). Reply: The free will revolution. Philosophical Explorations, 8(2), 145–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J. M. (2006). The free will revolution (continued). Journal of Ethics, 10, 315–345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J. M., & Ravizza, M. (1998). Responsibility and control: A theory of moral responsibility. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, J. C. (2013). Dispositions, conditionals and auspicious circumstances. Philosophical Studies, 164(2), 443–464.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. (1969). Alternate possibilities and moral responsibility. Journal of Philosophy, 66, 829–839.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franklin, C. E. (2011). Masks, abilities and opportunities: Why the new dispositionalism cannot succeed. Modern Schoolman, 88, 89–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gundersen, L. (2002). In defence of the conditional account of dispositions. Synthese, 130, 389–411.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heering, D. (2021). Actual sequences, frankfurt-cases, and non-accidentality. Inquiry. https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174X.2021.1904644

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Howard, N. R. (forthcoming). One desire too many. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research.

  • Jaster, R. (2020). Agents’ abilities. De Gruyter.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, M. (1992). How to speak of the colors. Philosophical Studies, 68, 221–263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Judisch, N. (2005). Responsibility, manipulation, and ownership: Reflections in the Fischer/Ravizza program. Philosophical Reflections, 8(2), 115–130.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levy, N., & McKenna, M. (2009). Recent work on free will and moral responsibility. Philosophy Compass, 3, 96–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1997). Finkish dispositions. The Philosophical Quarterly, 47, 143–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maier, J. (2014). Abilities. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2014 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/abilities/>.

  • Malzkorn, W. (2000). Realism, functionalism and the conditional analysis of dispositions. Philosophical Quarterly, 50, 452–469.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manley, D., & Wasserman, R. (2008). On linking dispositions and conditionals. Mind, 117(465), 59–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, C. B. (1994). Dispositions and conditionals. The Philosophical Quarterly, 44, 1–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, M. (2000). Assessing reasons-responsive compatibilism. International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 8(1), 89–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, M. (2001). Review of John Martin Fischer and Mark Ravizza’s responsibility & control. Journal of Philosophy, 98(2), 93–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, M. (2013a). Reasons-responsiveness, agents, and mechanisms. In: Oxford studies in agency and responsibility Volume 1. Oxford University Press.

  • McKenna, M. (2013b). Watsonian compatibilism. In D. Justinoates & N. A. Tognazzini (Eds.), Oxford studies in agency and responsibility Volume 5: Themes from the Philosophy of Gary Watson. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, S. (1998). Dispositions. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartorio, C. (2016). Causation and free will. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shabo, S. (2005). Fischer and Ravizza on history and ownership. Philosophical Explorations, 8(2), 103–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A. M. (2005). Responsibility for attitudes: Activity and passivity in mental life. Ethics, 115(2), 236–271.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. (1997). A theory of freedom and responsibility. In G. Cullity & B. Gaut (Eds.), Ethics and Practical Reason (pp. 293–317). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. (2003). Rational capacities, or: How to distinguish recklessness, weakness, and compulsion. In S. Stroud & C. Tappolet (Eds.), Weakness of Will and Practical Irrationality (pp. 17–38). Clarendon Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sorensen, K. (2014). Counterfactual situations and moral worth. Journal of Moral Philosophy, 11(3), 294–319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. (1962). Freedom and resentment. Proceedings of the British Academy, 48, 1–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tadros, V. (ms). Responsibility without modality.

  • Todd, P., & Tognazzini, N. A. (2008). A problem for guidance control. Philosophical Quarterly, 58(233), 685–692.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vihvelin, K. (2004). Free will demystified: A dispositional account. Philosophical Topics, 32, 427–450.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vihvelin, K. (2013). Causes, laws, & free will. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Watson, G. (2001). Reason and responsibility. Ethics, 111, 374–394.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whittle, A. (2010). Dispositional abilities. Philosophers’ Imprint, 10(12), 1–23.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to the participants of the colloquium at the Centre for Human Abilities Berlin for many insightful comments on the manuscript.

Funding

I gratefully acknowledge funding from the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft (DFG, German Research Foundation) within the Centre for Advanced Studies in the Humanities “Human Abilities”, Grant Number 409272951.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David Heering.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Heering, D. Reasons-responsiveness, modality and rational blind spots. Philos Stud 180, 293–316 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-022-01899-y

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-022-01899-y

Keywords

Navigation