In a recent paper Storrs-Fox (2021) has argued against the A-theory of time on the grounds that it cannot adequately account for the explanation of actions. Storrs-Fox’s argument makes use of the idea that explanation is forever. He argues that this is incompatible with the A-theory because the reasons people act for are the explanantia of their actions, though according to the A-theory, these reasons, that is facts, often do not obtain forever and therefore nor do the explanations. I will argue that particular explanatory relations clearly are not forever because reasons for actions must often fade as a person cannot now have a reason to do something at an earlier time. Generally, people cannot affect the past and therefore cannot have rational obligations to do so. This means that anyone who, on the basis of an instance of acting for a reason, infers that at later times that reason is still an explanans is making an inference that involves two gaps: because that particular explanatory relation of acting for a reason does not occur at those later times and because that particular reason does not occur at those later times. This shows that the A-theorist can coherently refuse to accept that inference and hence deny that explanation is forever, thus avoiding Storrs-Fox’s problem. In fact, the A-theory says what ought to be said and arguably accounts for the wider phenomena of action explanation better than the B-theory.

In the first section of this paper I will outline Storrs-Fox’s argument against the A-theory which focuses on explaining an action of Anna’s. In Sects. 2 and 3 I will highlight two particular explanatory relations that arise in Anna’s case and show that neither supports Storrs-Fox’s claim that explanation by Anna’s reason is forever. In Sect. 4 I will respond to a semantic concern Storrs-Fox raises arguing it is more of a problem for the B-theory than A-theory. In Sect. 5 I will point out that there is one sense in which explanation is forever, explanations at one time give rise to different explanations at later times, though this does not mean reasons/explanantia must exist forever and so is not problem for the A-theory. Finally, in Sect. 6, I will outline an argument for thinking that the A-theory is in fact better placed than the B-theory to account for the explanation of actions as it is better placed to account for the rational requirement that agents have tensed beliefs when acting. It is often the case that an agent acts rationally only if that agent acts on the basis of a present tensed belief. This implies that present tensed beliefs capture facts that no tenseless beliefs do, because the rationality of an action is determined solely by the reasons, that is facts, an agent acts for, not the beliefs through which the agent is aware of these. However, the B-theory, unlike the A-theory, denies there are any facts thus uniquely captured by present tensed beliefs.

1 Storrs-Fox’s argument

Storrs-Fox gives his argument as an argument against the A-theory of time, which he is understanding as a theory committed to two points, factual-futurism and propositional temporalism. According to factual futurism there are facts that obtain but that at some point will not obtain (temporary facts). According to propositional temporalism, there are propositions that are true but not always true (temporary propositions). For example, it is currently sunny so according to this A-theory the fact that it is sunny currently obtains and the proposition that it is sunny is currently true, but later, when the clouds roll in, the fact will no longer obtain and the proposition will no longer be true.

The A-theory is contrasted with the B-theory which involves the denial of both factual futurism and propositional temporalism. According to this B-theory, there will not be a temporary fact of it being sunny now, though, given it is now noon on the 20th of May 2022, there will be a permanent fact of it being sunny at noon on the 20th of May 2022. Likewise, although there will not be the temporary proposition of it being sunny now, there will be the permanently true proposition that it is sunny at noon on the 20th of May 2022. According to this B-theory, our tensed utterances will express such unchanging facts and propositions, not, as one might initially think, temporary facts or propositions.Footnote 1

Storrs-Fox gives his argument by considering an example of an action by Anna. The example is broadly as follows. On MondayFootnote 2 it is raining and Anna, on her way to a meeting, hails a taxi. Her friend Bernard truthfully utters S1.

S1, “Anna’s reason for hailing a taxi is that it is raining”.

On Tuesday, it is no longer raining and Bernard, thinking back, utters S2 and subsequently S3 and S4.

S2, “Anna’s reason for hailing the taxi was that it was raining”.

S3, “If Anna’s reason for hailing the taxi was that it was raining, then the fact that it was raining explains why she was hailing the taxi”.

S4, “Therefore, the fact that it was raining explains why Anna was hailing the taxi”.

Storrs-Fox assumes, as I agree, that the reasons people act for, the reasons that motivate them to act, are facts. In this instance, the reason/fact that Anna is motivated by is supposed to be picked out by the clause ‘it is raining’ in S1. According to the A-theory, this clause in S1 will pick out a temporary fact, a fact that no longer obtains on Tuesday. Storrs-Fox refers to this as fact R.

Storrs-Fox suggests that on Tuesday Bernard ought to be able to refer to R using the clause ‘it was raining’ in S2 and hence in S3 and S4. He concludes from this, that if we accept S3 and S4 as true, then on Tuesday R explains why Anna was hailing the taxi. However, Storrs-Fox argues that explanation is factive, by which he means that if x explains y, then x and y must obtain. Therefore, R must obtain on Tuesday because it is then an explanans for the explanation picked out by S4, an explanation that obtains on Tuesday. Therefore, the A-theory must be wrong to say R does not obtain on Tuesday and, more generally, it must be wrong to take facts like R to be temporary because cases like Anna’s are common and various.

On the other hand, the B-theory will not take a temporary fact like R to be Anna’s reason. Instead, it will take Anna’s reason to be a fact such as the fact that it rains on Monday, 12th of July, 2021. Let us refer to this fact as RB. RB will always obtain according to the B-theory and so can be both Anna’s reason on Monday and the explanans on Tuesday. The B-theory therefore does not face the same problem and is hence indirectly supported by Storrs-Fox’s argument.

2 The motivation explanatory relation

Storrs-Fox’s argument seems to commit the A-theory to a contradiction: R both does and does not obtain on Tuesday. It does not because it is a temporary fact and it does because on Tuesday it is an explanans in an explanatory relation that obtains on Tuesday.

I suggest that the A-theory ought to respond to this argument by denying that R is an explanans that obtains on Tuesday. Crucially, R needn’t be an explanans that obtains on Tuesday, because S4 does not capture an explanation with R as explanans that obtains on Tuesday.

Storrs-Fox’s argument takes reasons to be facts. In order to clarify this point and my reply, it is helpful to get a little more clear about reasons. Reasons are commonly distinguished into two kinds, normative reasons and motivating reasons. Normative reasons are reasons that promote or justify an action, they are considerations that stand in favour of acting. Motivating reasons are reasons that agents act for, they are reasons that motivate actions.Footnote 3 To talk of two kinds of reasons here can be potentially misleading, insofar as it is not being suggested that normative reasons are different kinds of entities from motivating reasons. Rather, both kinds of reasons can be taken to be facts.Footnote 4 The difference concerns the different roles that a fact can play. If a fact justifies an action, then it is a normative reason for that action. If someone becomes aware of that reason and hence becomes motivated by it to perform the action, then the fact is also a motivating reason for the action. Often normative reasons and motivating reasons will coincide in this way. Though, the two can come apart, for example, if a fact is a normative reason to perform an action, but an agent is not aware of it and so not motivated by it to act (the fact that my toast is burning is a normative reason for me to turn off the toaster, but unaware of that fact, I will not perform that act and the fact will not be a motivating reason).

Now, Storrs-Fox’s argument is that R is a motivating reason for Anna to act to hail a taxi on Monday. Anna is motivated by R to hail a taxi on Monday. Plausibly, however, R is also a normative reason for Anna to hail a taxi on Monday. In fact, plausibly it is in part because R is a normative reason for the action that it motivates Anna to perform the action: it is a motivating reason in part because it is a normative reason.

Given R motivates Anna’s action on Monday, it is plausible to say that R explains Anna’s action on Monday. Crucially, the explanatory relation here appears to be realised by the motivation relation: the relation of motivation is an explanatory relation. (I will refer to this motivation relation as M. M is a relation that holds between the fact/reason R, and Anna’s action.)Footnote 5

Turning to Tuesday, it is important to note something. Anna cannot perform the action talked of earlier in this section on Tuesday. That is, on Tuesday Anna cannot perform the action of hailing a taxi on Monday.Footnote 6 Because Anna cannot perform that action on Tuesday, Anna also cannot on Tuesday have a normative reason to perform that action. One cannot have a normative reason to perform an action that it is impossible for one to perform.Footnote 7 Following from this, it is also implausible that Anna would be motivated on Tuesday to perform the action of hailing a taxi on Monday.Footnote 8 Thus, on Tuesday Anna also does not have a motivating reason to perform the action.

Thus, it is clear that whilst relation M occurs on Monday, it does not occur on Tuesday. This shows that there is an important sense in which explanation is not forever: a particular explanatory relation can occur at one time and not others.

Let us now return to Bernard and his utterances. M, our motivating/explanatory relation, holds on Monday. So, S1 is plausibly true. Bernard would also speak the truth if on Monday he uttered S1*.

S1*, “That it is raining explains Anna’s hailing a taxi”.

M does not occur on Tuesday. So, what should we make of S2? Well, S2 does not seem to say that M occurs on Tuesday. S2 is in the past tense, the implication of it is that at a time earlier than Tuesday Anna was motivated by a reason. S2 is hence true.

However, S3 and S4 occur on Tuesday and speak of explanation in the present tense. So far, we have been given no explicit reason for taking S3 and S4 to be true: all we have established is that an explanatory relation, M, occurs on Monday and not Tuesday. Nevertheless, if Bernard had made two closely related utterances, S3* and S4* on Tuesday, these would have been true.

S3*, “If Anna’s reason for hailing the taxi was that it was raining, then the fact that it was raining explained why she was hailing the taxi”.

S4*, “Therefore, the fact that it was raining explained why Anna was hailing the taxi”.

S3* and S4* concern an explanatory relation that obtains on Monday, not Tuesday. (They are utterances concerning an explanation that is in the past on Tuesday.) Because the truth of S3* and S4* does not commit us to there being an explanatory relation that obtains on Tuesday, it also does not commit us to the explanans of this relation obtaining on Tuesday. Hence, we are also not committed by them to taking R to obtain on Tuesday, pace Storrs-Fox.

A careful consideration of Anna’s acting for a reason gives us a ground for thinking R obtains on Monday but not on Tuesday, because the motivation relation it is a relatum of is an explanatory relation that occurs on Monday but not Tuesday.

Storrs-Fox does not anticipate this argument, however, he does anticipate the kind of response it supports, that is, that on Tuesday it is not true to say that R explains Anna’s action, only that it explained it (2021: 4249). Storrs-Fox provides a positive and a negative comment on such a response. The positive comment, as related to the specifics of my argument, is that the close link between S3* and S4* on the one hand, and S3 and S4 on the other, provides an error theory for why one might have mistakenly thought S3 and S4 accurately portray R as an explanans on Tuesday. I accept and would also wish to press this positive point. After giving the positive comment, Storrs-Fox goes on to give the negative one.

Of course, there are other truths in the vicinity—most notably, that if Anna’s reason for hailing the taxi was R, then R explained (at the time of action) why she was hailing the taxi. But the futurist also needs to say something about what later explains (at the time of (S3)’s utterance) why Anna was hailing the taxi. It would be very odd if there were no longer any explanation of her action, or if the explanation no longer includes facts about the rain.” (2021: 4249)

Thus, Storrs-Fox is supposing that it would be odd if on Tuesday there were no longer an explanation of Anna’s action. The challenge to a reply like mine is that it is stuck with this oddness. However, I would deny that there is in fact anything odd here at all. It might be odd if Anna’s action was devoid of explanation, but that is not the case. The action obtained on Monday, the explanans/motivating reason obtained on Monday, and the explanatory/motivating relation obtained on Monday. Anna’s action was explained. On Tuesday, however, the reason no longer obtains, the action no longer obtains, the motivation/explanatory relation no longer obtains.Footnote 9

Rather, I have argued that it would be odd to suppose that the explanation does obtain on Tuesday. Anna can’t perform the action on Tuesday, and so cannot have a normative reason to perform it on Tuesday, and so does not have a motivation or motivational reason to perform it on Tuesday. Therefore, it would be odd to take there to be an explanation on Tuesday on the basis of a consideration of Anna’s motivation. If there is an oddity here, it is one that is faced by Storrs-Fox, not the A-theorist.

Before closing this section we should note that Storrs-Fox does provide an argument to try to further motivate the idea that it would be odd to deny that Anna’s action is explained on Tuesday. He invites us to consider that Anna’s phone was stolen whilst she was hailing the taxi and that the thief later put the phone on his dresser where it remained on Tuesday. Storrs-Fox says the following:

It seems that the fact that it was raining explains … why Anna’s phone is later on the thief’s dresser. And the fact that it was raining explains the phone’s position because it explains the fact that Anna was hailing the taxi …It is hard to see how the fact that it was raining could explain (at the later time) why the phone is on the thief’s dresser, unless that fact explains (at the later time) why Anna was hailing the taxi.” (2021: 4249)

In the following section I will account for this case in a way that makes it clear that it is not odd to deny that R is an explanans on Tuesday.

3 The historical explanatory relation

Storrs-Fox’s motivation for speaking of explanation in Anna’s case seems to fundamentally lie with the fact that Anna’s action was motivated by a reason. He speaks of explanation because of the motivating role of this reason. However, we have just seen that a careful examination of this motivation in fact gives us no direct ground for thinking that Anna’s reason does any explaining at a later time. The reason and the explanatory relation that is the motivation relation do not occur on Tuesday. Nevertheless, one might wonder if there are distinct explanatory relations that occur on Tuesday because the motivation relation occurred on Monday. I will now move to considering such a suggestion.

Whilst pressing the idea that there is explanation obtaining on Tuesday, Storrs-Fox says the following. “At the time of Bernard’s utterances of (S2) and (S3), R explains why Anna was (earlier) hailing the taxi.” (2021: 4245).Footnote 10 One point of note here, is that what is being proposed as explanandum is the fact, on Tuesday, that Anna was earlier hailing a taxi. This explanandum is distinct from Anna’s action. The explanandum here concerns something about Tuesday, namely that Anna was hailing a taxi earlier than then. We might put a more clear A-theory twist on this by describing it as a fact of the form ‘Anna was, earlier than now [Tuesday], hailing a taxi’. I will refer to this explanandum as AP and I will refer to the explanandum of M as AN.

Given AP concerns Tuesday I suggest that it is appropriate to think that the explanans for this explanandum also concerns Tuesday. In particular, I propose the fact that it was raining earlier than then: Anna is hailing earlier than Tuesday because it is raining earlier than Tuesday. Or, to put an A-theory twist on this, I propose the explanans is a fact of the form ‘it was, earlier than now [Tuesday], raining’. This is the sort of temporary fact that an A-theorist might expect to be picked out by an utterance, on Tuesday, of ‘it was raining’. I will refer to this fact as R*.

This explanatory relation that occurs on Tuesday thus plausibly involves facts about the past, and hence I will refer to it as a historical relation, relation H. H is a historical relation that is an explanatory relation and that occurs on Tuesday.

Crucially, H is not M and R* is not R. Therefore, the A-theorist can admit that there is an explanation that obtains on Tuesday. Though, the explanans of this explanation is R*, not R, so it is R*, not R, that must in light of this obtain on Tuesday.

Storrs-Fox anticipates that an A-theorist may respond to his argument by offering an alternative fact to R as explanans on Tuesday. He suggests that this form of response would land the A-theory with an additional cost and so the A-theory is still cast in a negative light by the discussion. He brings out the problem in the following way.

Either R* was among Anna’s reasons for hailing the taxi, or it was not. Suppose firstly that it was not. In that case, it appears that the explanation of Anna’s action at the later time of Bernard’s utterances is rather different in structure from the explanation at the time of her action. At the time of her action, the explanation includes her reason for acting (i.e., R). But at the later time, this reason drops out of the explanation and is replaced by a fact that was not her reason (i.e., R*). The later explanation therefore seems to miss something.” (2021: 4249–4250)

The reply I am outlining here is thus supposed to arrive at a problem, because R* is not amongst Anna’s reasons for acting. However, I would push back against the idea that this is a problem, or at least a problem for the A-theory.

Above I have argued that Anna cannot on Tuesday have a normative or motivating reason for her action. Therefore, any explanans that obtains on Tuesday must fail to be a reason for her action. This means that there must be a gap between the motivating reason obtaining on Monday, and the explanans obtaining on Tuesday. If this gap is a problem, it is a problem that must face all theories (including Storrs-Fox’s B-theory) that take there to be an explanatory relation and explanans obtaining on Tuesday.

Further, Storrs-Fox is here simply assuming that on Tuesday Anna’s action is an explanandum, or a relatum of an explanatory relation that obtains on Tuesday. However, so far our examination of Anna’s case has not led us to this conclusion. Rather, we have uncovered two relations that are explanatory, M and H. M has Anna’s action, AN, as explanandum, but occurs on Monday not Tuesday. H occurs on Tuesday but does not have Anna’s action as explanandum (rather, the explanandum of H is the fact that Anna was earlier acting, AP). So, it is not the case that on Tuesday we shift to explaining Anna’s action in terms of something other than a reason for her action.

We are now in a better position to deal with the case of Anna’s phone raised at the end of the last section. Storrs-Fox’s argument seems to be that Anna’s action must have an explanation on Tuesday as her phone’s being on the dresser has an explanation on Tuesday. But, what explains her phone’s being on the dresser on Tuesday is not its being stolen then, but specifically its being stolen earlier than Tuesday, and relatedly, what explains it being stolen earlier than Tuesday is Anna’s hailing earlier than Tuesday, and what explains Anna’s hailing earlier than Tuesday is that it is raining earlier than Tuesday. We are again dealing with a form of historical explanation. In more A-theoretical terms, the explanantia on Tuesday are that it was earlier than now [Tuesday] stolen, because Anna was earlier than now [Tuesday] hailing, because it was earlier than now [Tuesday] raining. That is, on Tuesday it is R*, not R, that is an explanans and the explanation of the phone’s location involves H, not M.

4 Semantics

Let us now address a semantic concern that Storrs-Fox raises for the A-theorist. Storrs-Fox says that the B-theorist can render the semantics of S2-4 in something like the following way.

S-SIMPLE-B:

S2: Anna’s reason for hailing the taxi was RB.

S3: If Anna’s reason for hailing the taxi was RB, then RB explains why she was hailing the taxi.

S4: Therefore, RB explains why Anna was hailing the taxi.

Storrs-Fox says the A-theorist, however, will have to render it in something like the following way.

S-ALTERNATIVE:

S2: Anna’s reason for hailing the taxi was R.

S3: If Anna’s reason for hailing the taxi was R, then R* explains why she was hailing the taxi.

S4: Therefore, R* explains why Anna was hailing the taxi.

Storrs-Fox argues that the semantics of S-SIMPLE-B is more simple than the semantics of S-ALTERNATIVE. It is more simple because RB occurs throughout S-SIMPLE-B, making the inference straightforward, whilst there is a shift from R to R* in S-ALTERNATIVE. This is therefore a cost for the A-theorist that takes this line of response.

I wish to respond to this by denying that the A-theorist is saddled with S-ALTERNATIVE. Rather, following the argument of Sect. 2, the A-theorist can adopt S-SIMPLE-A and deny that S3 and S4 are true (they are not true as S2 refers to M, and M occurs on Monday and not Tuesday). In addition, they can offer S3* and S4* which are true, the semantics of which may look something like the following.

S-SIMPLE-A:

S2: Anna’s reason for hailing the taxi was R.

S3: If Anna’s reason for hailing the taxi was R, then R explains why she was hailing the taxi.

S4: Therefore, R explains why Anna was hailing the taxi.

S-SIMPLE*:

S2: Anna’s reason for hailing the taxi was R.

S3*: If Anna’s reason for hailing the taxi was R, then R explained why she was hailing the taxi.

S4*: Therefore, R explained why Anna was hailing the taxi.

The semantics of S-SIMPLE-A and S-SIMPLE* are at least as simple as that of S-SIMPLE-B, and therefore the A-theorist has no cost here.

The explanatory relation uncovered in Sect. 3 is the historical relation H. H and M have distinct explananda, namely AP and AN respectively. It is of note that this distinction between AP and AN is one that can be recognised by both A-theorists and B-theorists. For an A-theorist, AN is a hailing by Anna that (presently) occurs on Monday, whilst AP is a Tuesday temporary fact that Anna was hailing. For a B-theorist AN is a hailing by Anna that (tenselessly/permanently) occurs on Monday, whilst AP is the permanent fact that Anna hailed earlier than Tuesday. (I thus use the labels ‘AN’ and ‘AP’ in a way that allows for an A-theory or B-theory interpretation, allowing context to settle which is at issue if just one is.)

I now wish to turn to Storrs-Fox’s semantics and consider it with AP and AN thus clearly distinguished. Storrs-Fox seems to be concerned with AN as an explanandum on Tuesday (though, we have seen it is not clear AN, as opposed to AP, actually is an explanandum on Tuesday). With this in mind the B-Theory semantics of S2-S4 can be clarified as S-SIMPLE-B-AN.

S-SIMPLE-B-AN:

S2: Anna’s reason for AN was RB.

S3: If Anna’s reason for AN was RB, then RB explains AN.

S4: Therefore, RB explains AN.

If we also clarify the A-theory semantics of S-SIMPLE* in this way we get S-SIMPLE*-AN.

S-SIMPLE*-AN:

S2: Anna’s reason for AN was R.

S3*: If Anna’s reason for AN was R, then R explained AN.

S4*: Therefore, R explained AN.

At this stage, it is in fact the B-Theory semantics, not the A-theory semantics that comes at a cost, contra Storrs-Fox. Assuming that a motivation relation can be an explanatory relation, the inference in S-SIMPLE*-AN is straightforward. M gives us this. However, the inference in S-SIMPLE-B-AN is not. In the latter inference S3 contains a crucial shift from RB being a reason for AN on Monday, to RB being an explanans of AN on Tuesday. This shift opens up two important gaps, one concerning reasons and one concerning explanatory relations.

As stressed above, Anna can’t on Tuesday perform the action at issue in AN. She did earlier perform it, but can’t then. So, on Tuesday, Anna cannot have a reason to perform it. Thus, if RB occurs on Tuesday, it cannot do so as a reason for that action. Perhaps it was on Monday a reason for it, but it is no longer a reason for it on Tuesday. In this way, Storrs-Fox’s semantics seems to suffer from a form of the problem that we saw he himself raises in Sect. 3. The explanatory relation that occurs on Tuesday must be of a different form to that which holds on Monday. This is the first gap passed over in S3 and the inference for the B-theorist.

The second gap concerns the explanatory relations themselves. M is an explanatory motivating relation with AN as explanandum. M is at issue in S2 and the antecedent of S3. However, M occurs on Monday and not Tuesday. Therefore, M is not at issue in the consequent of S3 or S4. Storrs-Fox is simply assuming that because one explanatory relation holds on Monday a different one with AN as explanandum will hold on Tuesday (this is his assumption that explanation is forever). But, this is not something he has argued for. Nor is it something we have directly observed as occurring in assessing Anna’s case.

The gaps just highlighted for the B-theorist do not disprove the B-theory position. There might be a way to justify the inference. However, it has been shown that the B-theorist is saddled with a cost that the A-theorist is not.

(These gaps in the B-theory inference have analogues in the inference given in S-SIMPLE-A. The gaps in this latter inference also give the A-theorist grounds to deny its validity, and hence deny that R is an explanans on Tuesday.)

5 The A-theory reply

The A-theory reply to Storrs-Fox’s argument that I propose combines the observations of the last three sections. The point is essentially this. If we take S3 and S4 to concern R as explanans, then we ought to take them to be false, though replaceable by the true S3* and S4* (along the lines of Sect. 2). On the other hand, if we take there to be explanation occurring on Tuesday, we ought to take the explanans to be something other than R (along the lines of Sect. 3). Crucially, this might be understood to vary with context, so that in some contexts we are focused on R (and for example M) and in others on current explanation (and for example H). In neither case are we committed to taking there to be an explanatory relation that occurs on Tuesday with R as explanans.

I would like to emphasise that the reply that I have given, whilst coinciding with the metaphysics of temporary facts adopted by the A-theory, is in fact motivated independently of this metaphysics. The key motivation, throughout, has stemmed from two points, that one cannot have a reason to do something that it is impossible for one to do and that one cannot possibly at one time perform an action at an earlier time.Footnote 11 These two points have a plausibility independently of the A-theory. They motivate my reply by making it clear that the A-theorist can coherently deny that there is an explanation obtaining on Tuesday with R as explanans. The general nature of these points also means that the form of reply that I have here outlined concerning Anna’s case would also apply to other cases.

Before closing this section I would like to say a little more about the relation between M and H. In the last section we considered the explanation of AN. Nevertheless, plausibly, as with H, Anna’s case does give us grounds for thinking AP can be explained. This gives us two further forms of the inference as captured in S2 to S4. The A-theory form is given by S-MIX-A and the B-theory form is given by S-MIX-B.

S-MIX-A:

S2: Anna’s reason for AN was R.

S3: If Anna’s reason for AN was R, then R* explains AP.

S4: Therefore, R* explains AP.

S-MIX-B:

S2: Anna’s reason for AN was RB.

S3: If Anna’s reason for AN was RB, then RB explains AP.

S4: Therefore, RB explains AP.

Both of these inferences clearly involve gaps. Though, I suggest that it is not obvious the gaps are more problematic in one case than the other, or hence, that these inferences preference either the A-theory or B-theory.

Both involve a shift from an explanatory relation occurring at one time (namely M) to a different explanatory relation (such as H) with a different explanandum (namely AP) occurring at a later time.

S-MIX-B, unlike S-MIX-A has the same fact as reason in the motivating relation and as explanans in the later explanatory relation. I suggest it is not clear that this is an advantage. Given general features of the A-theory of time R and R* will be fundamentally linked: unless time ends facts such as R are necessarily followed by facts such as R* due to the flow of time.Footnote 12 The B-theory inference has the fundamental tie of identity where the A-theory inference has a fundamental tie of necessary covariance. (In neither case can you have the reason on Monday without the explanans on Tuesday. And, in both cases, given the passing of time, the existence of the entity that is reason on Monday is followed by the existence of the entity that is explanans on Tuesday.)

It is true that the lack of identity means that R*, unlike R, is not a reason for AN. However, as noted above, RB cannot on Tuesday, and hence in the explanatory relation at issue here, be a reason for AN either (even if it was earlier one).Footnote 13 Both inferences hence involve a similar shift from a motivation relation concerning a reason, to an explanatory relation the explanans of which is not a reason.

The A-theory reply I have given does make use of explanatory relations like M and H, relations that are no doubt linked. However, this is not a cost that the A-theory has that the B-theory lacks.

Storrs-Fox’s argument assumes that explanation is forever. I have approached this claim by focusing on specific explanatory relations (something Storrs-Fox does not do). Looking at the explanatory relation M, we have seen that there is an important sense in which the claim that explanation is forever is false. Some explanatory relations occur at one time and not at another. Focusing on the link between the explanatory relations M and H, we have seen that there is another different sense in which the claim is true. Given the explanatory relation M occurs on Monday, the related explanatory relation H occurs on Tuesday (and relatedly for later times). However, neither of these points give us what Storrs-Fox needs, namely that R explains on Monday and at later times. (Storrs-Fox’s criticism of the A-theory relies on committing the A-theory to R being an explanans on Tuesday. What I have argued, is that the A-theory is not committed to this.)

6 A problem for the B-theory

Having argued that responding to reasons does not pose a particular problem for the A-theory, in this section I will present an argument to show that it does present a problem for the B-theory.

Bilal has a meeting today. He knows that the meeting is at midday on the 20th of May 2022 and he fully intends on going to the meeting. However, as the meeting nears, Bilal remains in his office tidying his papers. Suddenly, Bilal stops what he is doing and heads for the meeting. It seems that Bilal’s action of heading to the meeting must be explained by his forming a present tensed belief, such as the belief that ‘it is now 11:55am’.Footnote 14 It seems no related tenseless belief could account for his action, because he could have such a tenseless belief all morning without being moved to act. For example, he could believe all morning ‘the meeting occurs at 12pm, 20th of May 2022’ and ‘it takes 5 minutes to travel from my office to the meeting room’.

This is, of course, an instance of one of Perry’s (1979) cases of the essential indexical.Footnote 15 Something that it is important to note regarding such cases, however, is that the essentiality here stems from rationality. Bilal must have the present tensed belief in order to act rationally. It is not, for example, a physiological demand. We could imagine Bilal forming a tenseless belief and then suddenly because of this heading for the meeting. But, Bilal would be irrational if he acted in this way. Bilal does not require the present tensed belief to act, he requires it in order to act rationally.

For example, we could imagine Bilal forming the tenseless belief ’11:55am is 11:55am’, and on the basis of this heading to his meeting. But, he would be irrational if he did so. Alternatively, we could imagine Bilal suddenly forming the belief that ‘the meeting occurs at 12pm, 20th of May 2022’ and on the basis of this leaving his office. But, again, he would be irrational if he did so. Or, at least, he would be irrational if he did so without also forming a present tensed belief such as that ‘it is now 11:55am’. Bilal can act on a tenseless belief, even a relevant tenseless belief, but if he does not also act on a relevant present tensed belief, he will act irrationally.Footnote 16 Why then must Bilal have a present tensed belief in order to act rationally?

I will here assume that reasons are facts (as opposed, for example, to beliefs or desires). Here is not the place to defend this theory of reasons, but it is of note that such a theory has been forcefully defended, is a live option in the literature, and appears to be adopted by Storrs-Fox.Footnote 17

I will also assume that the demands of rationality stem from reasons: what one rationally ought to do, is what one has normative reason to do. Again, here is not the place to defend an account of rationality (it would take us too far away from the central point and take too much space). However, it is again of note that such a theory has been forcefully defended and is a live option in the literature.Footnote 18

Bringing these points together,Footnote 19 we can say, broadly, one is rational if one acts for reasons that justify one’s action, that is, if one’s motivating reasons are normative reasons, that is, facts that justify the action.Footnote 20 So, the demand that rationality places on Bilal is that he acts for relevant normative reasons, that the facts that motivate his action justify his action.

However, reasons are facts and in order to be able to respond to a fact Bilal must be aware of it. That is, in order for Bilal to have a normative reason as his motivating reason, he must have a belief with that fact as content.Footnote 21 The rational demand that Bilal acts for relevant normative reasons therefore gives rise to the demand that he acts on beliefs with those facts as content.

Therefore, if there is a belief or type of belief that rationality demands Bilal to act in light of, then that is because there is a normative reason that rationality demands Bilal acts for and only that belief or that type of belief has that normative reason, that is fact, as content.

Rationality demands that Bilal acts because of his belief that ‘it is now 11:55am’ (or for a present tensed belief of a related type, such as the belief ‘the time is currently 11:55am’). It demands this because it demands that he acts because of the fact that is the content of this belief (or the content of this type of belief). If Bilal does not act for that normative reason, he does not act for facts that justify his action, and therefore his action is not rational.

Thus, if Bilal must have a present tensed belief such as the belief that ‘it is now 11:55am’ to act rationally in heading for the meeting, then it must be that such a present tensed belief captures a fact not captured by any other non-present tensed beliefs. This point is readily accommodated by the A-theory, because according to the A-theory present tensed beliefs will capture temporary facts that other tenseless beliefs do not (such as the fact that it is now 11:55am). The B-theory, however, cannot account for this. According to the B-theory any present tensed belief will have a permanent fact as content. Permanent facts, however, can also be the content of tenseless beliefs.

We can bring out the difficulty here by considering Bilal’s belief that ‘it is now 11:55am’. There are two prominent B-theory accounts of the truthmakers of such tensed beliefs. According to the first, date account, Bilal’s belief would be made true by the permanent fact that 11:55am is 11:55am. According to the second, token reflexive account, it would be made true by the permanent fact that Bilal’s belief occurs at 11:55am.Footnote 22 Both of these permanent facts can be the contents of tenseless beliefs, such as the belief ‘11:55am is 11:55am’ and the belief ‘B occurs at 11:55am’ (where ‘B’ is a name for that belief). However, Bilal would be irrational if he acted on the basis of either of these tenseless beliefs.Footnote 23

Further, the truthmakers proposed by the B-theory for Bilal’s present tensed belief do not pick out normative reasons essential for justifying his action. The fact that 11:55am is 11:55am is not a reason for him to attend his meeting. All entities are self-identical whether or not Bilal ought to attend the meeting. The fact that a particular belief of Bilal’s occurs at 11:55am is also not an essential reason for him to attend the meeting. He ought to attend even if he does not have that particular belief.Footnote 24 The tenseless truthmakers proposed by the B-theory are not normative reasons for Bilal’s action, and tenseless beliefs with these facts as contents also do not make his action rational. The truthmakers proposed by the B-theory for Bilal’s present tensed belief therefore play no role in explaining why rationality would demand that he had such a present tensed belief.

On the other hand, let us consider permanent facts that a B-theorist might propose as essential normative reasons for Bilal’s action. These might include the fact that the meeting occurs at 12pm, 20th of May 2022 and the fact that it takes 5 min to travel from Bilal’s office to the meeting room.Footnote 25 Both of these facts could be the contents of beliefs that Bilal has all morning. Furthermore, both of these beliefs could play a part in motivating Bilal to act.Footnote 26 Nevertheless, rationality would still demand that Bilal must, in addition, have and act on a present tensed belief (such as the belief that ‘it is now 11:55am’). Therefore, whilst the facts the B-theorist picks out could be amongst Bilal’s motivating reasons, they are not sufficient normative reasons to make his act rational.Footnote 27 Thus, there must be a normative reason for Bilal’s action beyond these permanent facts, a normative reason essential for justifying Bilal’s action. The B-theory appears to be at a loss to offer such a fact.

The points just made can be summarised as follows. The demands of rationality are firstly that the motivating reasons for an action are normative reasons that justify it. The demands of rationality are hence, derivatively, that the beliefs we act on have as contents normative reasons that justify our actions. Therefore, if two different beliefs have as contents the same normative reason, rationality will not demand that an agent acts on one of these beliefs over the other. On the other hand, if rationality demands an agent acts on one belief instead of another, then that belief must have as content a normative reason the other fails to capture. Rationality demands that Bilal acts on a present tensed belief instead of or in addition to any tenseless beliefs. Therefore, Bilal’s present tensed belief must capture a normative reason distinct from any normative reasons captured by tenseless beliefs. The A-theory can readily accommodate this point by taking the required normative reason to be a temporary fact. The B-theorist cannot readily accommodate this point, as all B-theory facts can be captured by tenseless beliefs in addition to tensed ones. The B-theory therefore faces a problem when we consider actions performed for reasons.Footnote 28

Storrs-Fox does briefly mention essential indexical beliefs such as Bilal’s (2021: 4251). He says that a belief such as the present tensed belief ‘it is raining now’, will have as content a permanent fact. Further, this will be a permanent fact that might also be the content of a tenseless belief, perhaps, for example, the belief that ‘it is raining at 12pm, 20th of May 2022’. Storrs-Fox suggests that the beliefs differ because they present that permanent fact under different guises. More generally, tensed beliefs and tenseless beliefs differ despite having the same facts as content, because they present those facts under a different guises.

It is not clear exactly what a guise is in this context. But, it is clear that according to this account tensed and tenseless beliefs have the same reasons as content. Storrs-Fox’s reference to guises therefore does not account for the rational demand that Bilal has a tensed belief. To put the point differently, rationality is concerned with what reasons Bilal has and acts for, not with what guises those reasons occur to him under. Therefore, a reference to guises does not account for the rational demands placed on Bilal (or other similar agents).

The point just made makes it clear that the argument of this section is importantly different from arguments such as Prior’s (1959) thank goodness argument that have been extensively discussed in the literature. Prior’s argument establishes that tensed and tenseless beliefs can play different roles in our lives, so cannot have the same meaning (in some broad sense of the term). A prominent B-theorist reply to Prior’s argument is to suggest that tensed and tenseless beliefs differ in meaning but nevertheless concern the same facts.Footnote 29 This reply relies on the observation that beliefs can be opaque, that is, that two beliefs might concern the same fact without a believer recognising this. Storrs-Fox’s reference to guises is no doubt linked to this claim, guises are supposed to account for such opacity.

However, by focusing on rationality and the role of facts and motivating reasons, the argument of this section goes beyond Prior’s. My argument specifically focuses on the facts beliefs concern. (Where Prior’s argument highlights a difference in roles, my argument, via a consideration of reasons, specifically ties this to a difference in facts concerned.) Therefore, reference to meaning, opacity, or guises is not sufficient to provide a B-theory response to my argument (so long as it is assumed there is no difference in facts picked out).

7 Conclusion

Storrs-Fox has argued that the A-theory is wrong, because it takes motivating reasons to often be temporary facts though motivating reasons can be explanantia and as such ought to obtain forever. However, I have argued that motivating reasons often do not obtain forever, because an agent cannot at one time have a reason to perform an action at an earlier time. The A-theory can therefore coherently deny explanation is forever and does not face the problem Storrs-Fox suggests.

I have also argued that Storrs-Fox’s B-theory does face a problem related to acting for a reason. It is common for there to be a rational demand on an agent to act on the basis of a tensed belief. The B-theory does not appear to be able to account for this, because the rational demand is a demand for beliefs with particular facts as contents and according to the B-theory, tensed beliefs will share contents with tenseless beliefs and so will not be demanded in place of them.

Storrs-Fox’s discussion has helped to make it clear that the manner in which people respond to reasons, the rationality of people, is something that can inform the debate between the A-theory and the B-theory of time. However, Storrs-Fox’s discussion fails to establish that it is the latter theory that gains credence over the former in light of this.