Skip to main content
Log in

From Turing to Peirce. A semiotic interpretation of computation

  • Published:
Foundations of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

A Correction to this article was published on 15 November 2022

This article has been updated

Abstract

The thesis of the paper is that semiotic processes are intrinsic to computation and computational systems. An explanation of computation that does not take this semiotic dimension into account is incomplete. Semiosis is essential to computation and therefore requires a rigorous definition. To prove this thesis, the author analyzes two concepts of computation: the Turing machine and the mechanistic conception of physical computation. The paper is organized in two parts. The first part (Sects. 2 and 3) develops a re-interpretation of the Turing machine starting from Peirce’s semiotics. The author shows how this reinterpretation allows overcoming the dualism between a purist and a realist version of the Turing machine. The second part of the paper (Sect. 4) shows how a mechanistic explanation of physical computation such as the one developed by Piccinini is incomplete without considering semiotic relations. The paper intends to be a contribution to the philosophical debate on computation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Change history

Notes

  1. This paper is a re-formulation and development of Possati (2022, Chap. 5).

  2. Peirce played a small role in the history of the computer along with his disciple Alan Marquand. Peirce was the first to propose a computer built from electric circuits, and thus saw his own theory as amenable to computation. I thank the anonymous reviewer for this note.

  3. Here a purist description of TM: “A Turing machine is a specific kind of idealized machine for carrying out computations, especially computations on positive integers represented in monadic notation. We suppose that the computation takes place on a tape, marked into squares, which is unending in both directions—either because it is actually infinite or because there is someone stationed at each end to add extra blank squares as needed. Each square either is blank, or has a stroke printed on it. (We represent the blank by S0 or 0 or most often B, and the stroke by S1 or | or most often 1, depending on the context.) And with at most a finite number of exceptions, all squares are blank, both initially and at each subsequent stage of the computation. At each stage of the computation, the computer (that is, the human or mechanical agent doing the computation) is scanning some one square of the tape.” (Boolos et al., 2007, 25).

  4. For a comment on the passage, see Spinks (1991, 52–53).

  5. I do not want to analyze the oscillation, very present in Peirce’s texts, between a psychological reading and a communicative and non-psychological reading of the concept of semiosis. See Fadda (2013, 173–175).

  6. I cannot analyze here, for reasons of space, on the debate on iconism in 1970–1980 semiotics. I only mention the famous criticisms of Goodman and Eco. I quote, in response to these criticisms, the position of Deacon (a long but important passage): “When we apply these terms to particular things, for instance, calling a particular sculpture an icon, a speedometer an indicator, or a coat of arms a symbol, we are engaging in a sort of tacit shorthand. What we usually mean is that they were designed to be interpreted that way, or are highly likely to be interpreted that way. So, for example, a striking resemblance does not make one thing an icon of another. Only when considering the features of one brings the other to mind because of this resemblance is the relationship iconic. Similarity does not cause iconicity, nor is iconicity the physical relationship of similarity. It is a kind of inferential process that is based on recognizing a similarity. As critics of the concept of iconicity have often pointed out, almost anything could be considered an icon of anything else, depending on the vagueness of the similarity considered. The same point can be made for each of the other two modes of referential relationship: neither physical connection nor involvement in some conventional activity dictates that something is indexical or symbolic, respectively. Only when these are the basis by which one thing invokes another are we justified in calling their relationship indexical or symbolic” (Deacon, 1997, 71).

  7. I refer here to the manuscripts cited by Bellucci (2017). By the abbreviation R I refer to A Harvard manuscript (Charles S. Peirce Papers, 1787–1951, MS Am 1632, Houghton Library, Harvard University) as listed in Richard Robin, Annotated Catalog of the Papers of Charles S. Peirce (Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1967); the abbreviation CSP refers to the Peirce pagination.

  8. Piccinini does not deny that computational systems can be semantic. He only states that these systems do not presuppose semantics. “Of course, many (though not all) computational vehicles do have semantic properties, and such semantic properties can be used to individuate computing systems and the functions they compute. The functions computed by physical systems that operate over representations can be individuated either semantically or non-semantically; the mechanistic account provides non-semantic individuation conditions” (Piccinini, 2015, 118).

  9. The vehicles are not exactly identical to the components; vehicles are not objects with a fixed state, but concrete or abstract variables; see Piccinini (2015, 119).

References

  • Andersen, P. (1997). A Theory of Computer Semiotics. Cambridge University Press

  • Anellis, I. (1993). “Review of A Peircean Reduction Thesis.” Modern Logic (3)4: 401–406

  • Akrich, M., & Latour, B. (1992). “A Summary of a Convenient Vocabulary for the Semiotics of Human and Nonhuman Assemblies.”. In W. E. Bijker, & J. Law (Eds.), Shaping Technology/Building Society. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Barbieri, M. (2015). Code Biology. Dordrecht: Springer

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bateson, G. (1972). Steps to an Ecology of Mind. London: Aronson

    Google Scholar 

  • Bellucci, F. (2017). Peirce’s Speculative Grammar. Logic as Semiotics. London-New York: Routledge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Burch, R. (1993). “A Peircean Reduction Thesis.” Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 29 (1): 101–107

  • Cellucci, C. (2019). Diagrams in Mathematics. Foundations of Sciences, 24, 583–604

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2011). A computational foundation for the study of cognition. Journal of Cognitive Science, 12(4), 323–357

    Google Scholar 

  • Coeckelberg, M., & Reijers, W. (2020). Narrative and Technology Ethics. New York/London: Palgrave Macmillan

    Google Scholar 

  • Copeland, J. (2017). “Turing’s Great Invention: The Universal Computing Machine.”. In J. Copeland, J. Bowen, M. Sprevak, & R. Wilson (Eds.), The Turing Guide. Oxford University Press

  • Copeland, J., & Shagrir, O. (2011). Do Accelerating Turing Machines Compute the Incomputable? Minds and Machines, 21, 221–239

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deacon, T. (1997). The Symbolic Species. London-New York: Norton & Company

    Google Scholar 

  • Deacon, T. (2012). Incomplete Nature. London-New York: Norton & Company

    Google Scholar 

  • Eco, U. (1975). Trattato di semiotica generale. Milano: Bompiani

    Google Scholar 

  • Fadda, E. (2013). Peirce. Roma: Carocci

    Google Scholar 

  • Kohn, E. (2013). How Forests Think. Berkeley-Los Angeles-London: University of California Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B. (1984). Les microbes: guerre et paix. Paris: La découverte

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B. (1987). Science in Action. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B. (1993). We Have Never Been Modern. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B. (1994). On Technical Mediation. Common Knowledge, 3/2, 29–64

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B. (1999a). Pandora’s Hope. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B. (1999b). Politics of Nature. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Marrone, G., & Mangano, D. (2018). Semiotics of Animals in Culture. Zoosemiotics 2.0. Dordrecht: Springer

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nadin, M. (2007). “Semiotic Machine. Public Journal of Semiotics, 1(1), 57–75

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ogden, C. K., and Richards, I. A. 1923. The Meaning of Meaning. New York: Harcourt.

  • Peirce, C. 1931–1958. Collected Papers. C. Hartshorn, P. Weiss (eds.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Peirce, C. 1976. The New Elements of Mathematics. C. Eisele (ed.). The Hague: Mouton Press.

  • Piccinini, G. 2015. Physical Computation. Oxford University Press.

  • Piccinini, G. 2016. “The Computational Theory of Cognition.” In V. C. Müller (ed.),Fundamental Issues of Artificial Intelligence. Dordrecht: Springer.

  • Possati, L. 2022. Unconscious Networks. Philosophy, Psychoanalysis, and Artificial Intelligence. New York: Routledge.

  • Primiero, G. 2020. On the Foundations of Computing. Oxford University Press.

  • Putnam, H. 1967. Psychological predicates. University of Pittsburgh Press.

  • Romele, A. 2019. Digital Hermeneutics. London-New York: Routledge.

  • Salanskis, M. 2013. L’herméneutique formelle. L’infini, le continu, l’espace. Paris: Klincksieck.

  • Sebeok, T. 1994. Signs: An Introduction to Semiotics. University of Toronto Press.

  • Shagrir, O. 2006. “Why We View the Brain as a Computer.” Synthese 153(3): 393–416.

  • Skiena, S. 2008. The Algorithm Design Manual. Dordrecht: Springer.

  • Spinks, C. W. 1991. Peirce and Triadomania: A Walk in the Semiotic Wilderness. Berlin-New York: de Gruyter.

  • Stjernfelt, F. 2000. “Diagrams as Centerpiece of a Peircean Epistemology.” Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 36/3: 357–384.

  • Stjernfelt, F. 2014. Natural Propositions. The Actuality of Peirce’s Doctrine of Dicisigns. Boston: Docent Press.

  • Turing, A. M. 1936. “On Computable Numbers, with an Application to the Entscheidungsproblem.”Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society, 42: 230–265.

  • Wooldridge, M. 2021. The Road to Conscious Machines. The Story of AI. New York: Random House.

  • Notes

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Luca M. Possati.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Possati, L.M. From Turing to Peirce. A semiotic interpretation of computation. Found Sci 28, 1085–1110 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-022-09878-6

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-022-09878-6

Navigation