Skip to main content
Log in

Moral criticism, hypocrisy, and pragmatics

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

A good chunk of the recent discussion of hypocrisy concerned the hypocritical “moral address” where, in the simplest case, a person criticises another for \(\phi \)-ing having engaged in \(\phi \)-ing himself, and where the critic’s reasons are overtly moral. The debate has conceptual and normative sides to it. We ask both what hypocrisy is, and why it is wrong. In this paper I focus on the conceptual explication of hypocrisy by examining the pragmatic features of the situation where accusations of hypocrisy are made. After rejecting several extant views, I defend the idea that moral criticisms are best understood as moves in an agonistic or hostile conversation, and that charges of hypocrisy are attempts to prevent the hypocrite from gaining an upper hand in a situation of conflict. I finish by linking this idea to frame-theoretic analysis and evolutionary psychology.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Subjunctive hypocrisy: Piovarchy (2020:10–11).

  2. This brings me to another disclaimer, that criticisms not couched in moral terms are outside the scope of our discussion. This includes, e.g., the emotionally charged, angry complaints of the kind sketched in Wolf (2011).

  3. See, e.g., Wallace (2010), Rossi (2021), and every writer in the debate cited here, with the possible exception of Dover (2019a) discussed below. But whatever the consensus in the current debate over blame and hypocrisy, might we not say generally that hypocrisy is often a salutary phenomenon, so far as it serves a useful social purpose? This, for example, is a view espoused in Mandeville (1924). Yet even Mandeville assumes at the outset that hypocrisy (or at least some of its forms) is in itself odious, although we may have to tolerate it for the sake of public utility. See, e.g., Douglass (2022:469).

  4. Well, can’t there be hypocritical blame that has never been expressed verbally? Certainly. But I think it should be understood as a defect of character. It is a principally different form of hypocrisy to be given a different treatment. For example, a silent hypocrite wouldn’t be guilty of deceiving others. He should instead be criticised for his own self-deception. See Berkovski (2022) for a discussion of public and silent hypocrisies and their links to self-deception. In any event, as mentioned earlier, this form of hypocrisy is outside the purview of this paper. The present task is to reconstruct the dynamics of a verbal interaction where hypocrisy is a driving force.

  5. Presupposition triggers: Levinson (1983:178–179), Tonhauser et al. (2013:75). “Hey wait a minute!”: von Fintel (2004:316).

  6. See Potts (2015:174), Simons (2006:359).

  7. See Tonhauser et al. (2013:81).

  8. See Simons (2006:358).

  9. Conversational implicature: Potts (2015:179). Difference between observing and flouting the maxims: Levinson (1983:104–105). Wallace himself floats the idea that the critic conversationally implicates that he hasn’t \(\phi \)-ed (2010:316, 334).

  10. Since there is no presumption that \(M\) is conveyed pragmatically at all, it would be misleading to apply the usual tests of conversational implicature, like cancellabiliy or reinforceability. These tests are designed to distinguish implicature from other kinds of non-at-issue content. But if \(M\) is not such a content in the first place, it may pass these tests trivially.

  11. A version of this view is in Shoemaker and Vargas (2021). I discuss it in more detail elsewhere. The terminology of “cue” is from Maynard Smith and Harper (2003) where it is contrasted with “signals”. This contrast is loosely analogous to the one between meaning\(_{\text {N}}\) and meaning\(_{\text {NN}}\) of Grice (1957).

  12. Special conditions for the cue to become pragmatic: Grice (1989:100–104).

  13. Some typical statements: Fritz and Miller (2018:125), Todd (2019:347, 357), Wallace (2010:332), Lippert-Rasmussen (2020:672), Rossi (2021:78), and further references below.

  14. See, e.g., Shafer-Landau (2003:15) for a careful formulation of moral realism.

  15. This connects to the issue of the emotional component of Scanlon’s blame. See Wolf (2011).

  16. Compare a related discussion in Portner (2016:606).

  17. The precedent here is, of course, the original discussion in Austin (1975:16).

  18. Throughout I assume a traditional view of assertion, rather than a revisionist one like in Williamson (2000:249ff). Note too that the revisionist is likely to dispute the felicity of Cohen’s puzzle (6) on a combination of moral and epistemic grounds.

  19. Curiously, Isserow and Klein (2017:199n16) mention the possibility of exactly this kind of explanation, but declare themselves unperturbed—wrongly, in my view.

  20. See Dover (2019a:38), Dover (2019b:400).

  21. Could a known hypocrite plausibly issue a moral criticism? This interesting possibility will be addressed shortly. Secondly, what of a criticism made in private where \(A\) criticises \(B\) in a one-on-one interaction? Again, so far as \(A\)’s judgement is valuable to \(B\), the latter has an interest in protecting \(A\)’s positive judgement of himself. More generally, we may appeal to the notion of “face” and say that also in dyadic interactions people protect their face and project a positive image of themselves (Brown and Levinson 1987). Moral criticisms damage the criticised person’s face.

  22. See Shklar (1979:6), Szabados (1979:205), also Wallace (Wallace 2010:338). Whether the hypocrite deliberately deceives is an open question. See Dover (2019b:408–412) for a compelling survey of hypocrite’s intentions.

  23. See Crisp and Cowton (1994:347).

  24. See Chafe (1994:53–56, 71–78 ), Langacker (2012:107–111).

  25. Standard pragmatic account: Stalnaker (2014).

  26. Accommodation: Stalnaker (2014:6, 47ff).

  27. See the instructive remarks in Stalnaker (2014:75ff).

  28. Frames and language: Fillmore (1975), Fillmore (1985). I ignore Fillmore’s distinction between interactional and cognitive frames, and I don’t endorse his stronger claims about semantic meaning being determined by frames. Other penetrating discussions: Goffman (1974:499ff), Gumperz (1982:130ff).

  29. See, e.g., the concessions in Dover (2019a:41).

  30. Note that the constructive model also lacks an explanation why moral criticisms can regularly appear in “friendly” frames—why, in other words, they should not trigger agonistic transformation. Dover acknowledges this deficiency in (2019a:43), but offers no positive proposal.

  31. Goffman’s distinctions are refined in Levinson (1988).

  32. The “natural setting” of moral judgement: Haidt (2001:820).

  33. Judges may also praise, but as DeScioli and Kurzban note, condemnation prevails.

References

  • Alston, W. P. (2000). Illocutionary Acts and Sentence Meaning. Ithaca: Cornell Universty Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J. L. (1975). How to Do Things with Words. Clarendon Press, Oxford, 2nd edn. Edited by J. O. Urmson and M. Sbisà.

  • Bach, K., & Harnish, R. M. (1979). Linguistic Communication and Speech Acts. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berkovski, Y. S. (2022). Mandeville on self-liking, morality, and hypocrisy. Intellectual History Review, 32(1), 157–178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, P., & Levinson, S. C. (1987). Politeness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chafe, W. L. (1994). Discourse, Consciousness, and Time. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, G. A. (2013a). Casting the first stone. In Cohen (2013).

  • Cohen, G. A. (2013c). Ways of silencing critics. In Cohen (2013).

  • Cohen, G. A. (2013). Finding Oneself in the Other. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Crisp, R., & Cowton, C. (1994). Hypocrisy and moral seriousness. American Philosophical Quarterly, 31(4), 343–349.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeScioli, P., & Kurzban, R. (2009). Mysteries of morality. Cognition, 119, 281–299.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeScioli, P., & Kurzban, R. (2013). A solution to the mysteries of morality. Psychological Bulletin, 139(2), 477–496.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeScioli, P., & Kurzban, R. (2018). Morality is for choosing sides. In K. Gray & J. Graham (Eds.), Atlas of Moral Psychology. New York: Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Douglass, R. (2022). Bernard Mandeville on the use and abuse of hypocrisy. Political Studies, 70(2), 465–482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dover, D. (2019). Criticism as conversation. Philosophical Perspectives, 33, 26–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dover, D. (2019). The walk and the talk. Philosophical Review, 128(4), 387–422.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, G. (2000). Morally speaking. In E. Ullmann-Margalit (Ed.), Reasoning Practically. Oxford: Oxford Univeristy Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fillmore, C. J. (1975). Frame semantics and the nature of language. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 280(1), 20–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fillmore, C. J. (1985). Frames and the semantics of understanding. Quaderni di Semantica, 6(2), 222–254.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fritz, K. G., & Miller, D. (2018). Hypocrisy and the standing to blame. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 99, 118–139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goffman, E. (1974). Frame Analysis. New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goffman, E. (1981). Forms of Talk. Philadelphia: Univerity of Pennsylvania Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H. P. (1989). Utterer’s meaning and intentions. In Studies in the Way of Words. Harvard University Press.

  • Grice, H. P. (1957). Meaning. Philosophical Review, 66(3), 377–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gumperz, J. J. (1982). Discourse Strategies. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its rational tail. Psychological Review, 108(4), 814–834.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Isserow, J., & Klein, C. (2017). Hypocrisy and moral authority. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, 12(2).

  • Kurzban, R. (2010). Why Everyone (Else) is a Hypocrite: Evolution and the Modular Mind. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langacker, R. W. (2012). Interactive cognition: Toward a unified account of structure, processing, and discourse. International Journal of Cognitive Linguistics, 3(2), 95–125.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, S. C. (1983). Pragmatics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, S. C. (1988). Putting linguistics on a proper footing. In P. Drew & A. Wootton (Eds.), Erving Goffman: Exploring the Interaction Order. Polity PressPolity PressPolity PressPolity Press.

  • Lippert-Rasmussen, K. (2020). Why the moral equality account of the hypocrite’s lack of standing to blame fails. Analysis, 80(4), 666–674.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mandeville, B. (1924). The Fable of the Bees, volume 1. Clarendon Press. Edited by F. B. Kaye.

  • Maynard Smith, J., & Harper, D. (2003). Animal Signals. Oxford: Oxford Univeristy Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piovarchy, A. (2020). Situationism, subjunctive hypocrisy and standing to blame. Inquiry. Forthcoming.

  • Portner, P. (2016). Imperatives. In M. Aloni & P. Dekker (Eds.), The Cambridge Handbook of Formal Semantics (pp. 593–628). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Potts, C. (2015). Presupposition and implicature. In S. Lappin & C. Fox (Eds.), The Handbook of Contemporary Semantic Theory (pp. 168–202). Hoboken: Wiley Blackwell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Riedener, S. (2019). The standing to blame, or Why moral disapproval is what it is. Dialectica, 73(1–2), 183–210.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rossi, B. (2018). The commitment account of hypocrisy. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 21, 553–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rossi, B. (2021). Hypocrisy is vicious, value-expressing inconsistency. Journal of Ethics, 25, 57–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T. M. (2008). Moral Dimensions: Permissibility, Meaning. Blame: Belknap Press, Cambridge, MA and London.

  • Searle, J. R., & Vanderveken, D. (1985). Foundations of Illocutionary Logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shafer-Landau, R. (2003). Moral Realism: A Defence. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shklar, J. N. (1979). Let us not be hypocritical. Daedalus, 108(3), 1–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, D., & Vargas, M. (2021). Moral torch fishing: A signaling theory of blame. Noûs, 55(3), 581–602.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simons, M. (2006). Foundational issues in presupposition. Philosophy. Compass, 1(4), 357–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. C. (2014). Context. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Szabados, B. (1979). Hypocrisy. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 9(2), 195–210.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Todd, P. (2019). A unified account of the moral standing to blame. Noûs, 53(2), 347–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tonhauser, J., Beaver, D., Roberts, C., & Simons, M. (2013). Toward a taxonomy of projective content. Language, 89(1), 66–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trollope, A. (1985). Orley Farm. Oxford Univeristy Press. Edited by D. Skilton.

  • von Fintel, K. (2004). Would you believe it? The King of France is back! In M. Reimer & A. Bezuidenhout (Eds.), Descriptions and Beyond. Oxford: Oxford Univeristy Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, R. J. (2010). Hypocrisy, moral address, and the equal standing of persons. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 38(4), 307–341.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and Its Limits. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, S. (2011). Blame, Italian style. In R. J. Wallace, R. Kumar, & S. Freeman (Eds.), Reasons and Recognition: Essays on the Philosophy of T.M. Scanlon. Oxford: Oxford Univeristy Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I’m grateful to an anonymous referee for useful comments on an earlier draft of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Y. Sandy Berkovski.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Berkovski, Y.S. Moral criticism, hypocrisy, and pragmatics. Philos Stud 180, 1–26 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-022-01862-x

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-022-01862-x

Keywords

Navigation