Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Contractualism and the Moral Point of View

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, I argue that accounts of the normative basis of morality face the following puzzle, drawing on a case found in Susan Wolf’s influential discussion of conflicts between the moral and personal points of view. On the one hand, morality appears to constitute an independent point of view that can intelligibly conflict with, and can conceivably be overruled by, the verdicts of other points of view. On the other hand, moral demands appear to carry a distinctive sort of authority; moral reasons normally seem to take priority over other kinds of considerations, and the verdicts of morality seem to possess a distinctive place in our deliberations, in that they appear to represent standards that we are open to legitimate complaint for failing to honor. After clarifying the nature of the problem, I argue that a contractualist theory of morality can resolve the puzzle by offering a compelling vindication of the independence of the moral perspective, the normal priority of moral reasons, and the deliberative significance of moral verdicts, within a unified theoretical framework. Furthermore, I claim that this contractualist analysis can help account for the sense of deep conflict that is characteristic of the sort of troubling moral choices that Wolf calls to our attention.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In the following, I make a number of assumptions that cannot be adequately defended within the scope of a single paper. For instance, I assume that it is possible to supply a non-trivial explanation of moral authority, and I also assume the availability of a comprehensive viewpoint of all-things-considered rationality that can rationally resolve conflicts between different practical points of view, at least in principle. For arguments to the contrary, see Prichard (2002) and Copp (2007), respectively. I maintain that these limitations on the scope of the present inquiry do not deprive the project of its theoretical or practical interest. Many philosophers have been animated by precisely the kinds of questions that I set out to address (Williams 1973a, b; Scheffler 1992; Foot 2002; Wolf 2015a, b, c; Dorsey 2016), and I trust that many will be able to recognize the intelligibility of these concerns on reflection.

  2. As Wolf puts the point; “there are situations in which an agent may reasonably act on behalf of a loved one and yet a third party, whose claims the agent thereby ignores, may reasonably object, and demand reparation or apology” Wolf (2015c, 160). See also Williams (1973a, 23–24).

  3. I thank the anonymous reviewers for this journal for emphasizing the need for me to articulate this point, and for their helpful suggestions on how to do so.

  4. The idea that morality essentially has to do with our impartial concern for others is highlighted in Dorsey (2016, 72–74). Robert Louden discusses this feature of the modern conception of morality critically in Louden (1988, 364–366).

  5. There is a further sense in which speaking of the “overridingness of morality" is potentially misleading in this context, aside from its overly strong connotations. The term is usually taken to imply that there is some property that moral verdicts possess, in and of themselves, that guarantees that they will always trump other considerations; whereas the claim I have in mind is more related to how the reasons of morality may or may not cohere with our other values and concerns within a well-integrated life. Of course, putting my point in terms of the “priority” of morality, rather than “overridingness”, might be viewed problematic for similar reasons. Thus, Samuel Scheffler uses the language of possible “congruence” to express the latter idea (Scheffler 2008, 118), and an anonymous reviewer for this journal, in their helpful discussion of this issue, has suggested referring to this claim as one concerning the “reasonable centrality” of morality. For ease of exposition, however, I will continue to refer to the idea I have in mind in terms of the normal “priority” of morality (see also Scanlon 1998, 148).

  6. Elsewhere, Wolf acknowledges that respecting the demands of impartial morality can have significant value and meaning for us (Wolf 2015a, 28; Wolf 2015b, 43). However, her discussion leaves it unclear what the nature of this value is and why it has this distinctive significance. In Sect. 4 of the present paper, I will offer an answer to these questions that draws on a contractualist account of the value that is realized by living in accordance with moral ideals.

  7. Note that Shiffrin herself does not make it her goal to address the specific sort of puzzle that is the main concern of this paper. Her aim is rather to show that the view that morality is overriding can be reconciled with the view that a consideration can be a reason for an agent only if it has some connection to her antecedent motivations (Shiffrin 1999, 775–776). Despite this, I believe it is instructive to focus on her view here because it seems to clearly encapsulate the attractions of an approach that conceives of morality as a uniquely comprehensive end. I thank an anonymous reviewer for this journal for urging me to be clear on this point.

  8. In fact, there is disagreement among contractualists over whether it is possible for an act to be wrong without wronging another. As an anonymous reviewer for this journal has pointed out, some of what Scanlon himself has written seems to indicate that he accepts this possibility (Scanlon 2013, 405). By contrast, Wallace has recently developed an interpretation of contractualism that takes the notion of wronging as essential for understanding our moral obligations; see, for example, Wallace (2019, 192–200). In my view, the latter interpretation of contractualism is more compelling, since—as the discussion in this section and the next will hopefully demonstrate—one of the primary attractions of contractualism as a moral theory lies in how it draws on the relational character of moral demands to account for their distinctive normativity.

  9. For instance, some have argued that there is an important disanalogy between personal relationships like friendship and love, on the one hand, and the moral relationship, on the other. In the case of friendship and love, the relationship that fixes our legitimate expectations is an actual relationship that is partly constituted by the mutual attitudes and dispositions that the participants have towards each other by virtue of their shared history of interaction. However, it is not so clear whether, in the moral case, such an actual relationship can be said to hold between rational creatures as such (Scheffler 2010, 66–67; Wallace 2011, 360).

  10. Scheffler (1992, 128–129). As Scheffler notes, the feasibility of integrating of our moral and non-moral commitments will also depend on the social conditions and institutions that form the background of one’s choice (140).

  11. For example, how we understand the ongoing debate concerning the demandingness of morality depends, in part, on how we conceptualize the rational authority of morality (Brink 1986, 432–433; Sobel 2007, 14–16; Dorsey 2016, 78–82).

References

  • Brink D (1986) Utilitarian morality and the personal point of view. J Philos 83(8):417–438

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Copp D (2007) The ring of gyges: overridingness and the unity of reason. In: Copp D (ed) Morality in a natural world: selected essays in metaethics. Cambridge University Press, pp 284–308

  • Darwall S (2006) The second-person standpoint: morality, respect, and accountability. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Dorsey D (2016) The limits of moral authority. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Foot P (2002) Does moral subjectivism rest on a mistake? In: Foot P (ed) Moral dilemmas and other topics in moral philosophy. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 189–208

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kumar R (1999) Defending the moral moderate: contractualism and common sense. Ethics 28(4):275–309

    Google Scholar 

  • Kumar R (2003) Reasonable reasons in contractualist moral argument. Ethics 114(1):6–37

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kumar R (2005) Who can be wronged? Philos Public Aff 31(2):99–118

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Louden RB (1988) Can we be too moral? Ethics 98(2):361–378

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel T (1970) The possibility of altruism. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Paletta D (2013) How to overcome Strawson’s point: defending a value-oriented foundation for contractualism. Ethical Theory Moral Pract 16(1):9–20

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Portmore D (2011) Commonsense consequentialism. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Prichard HA (2002) Does moral philosophy rest on a mistake? In: MacAdam I (ed) Moral Writings. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 7–20

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon TM (1998) What we owe to each other. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon TM (2003) Contractualism and utilitarianism. In: Scanlon TM (ed) The difficulty of tolerance: essays in political philosophy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon TM (2008) Moral dimensions. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon TM (2013) Reply to Leif Wenar. J Moral Philos 10:400–405

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scheffler S (1992) Human morality. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheffler S (2004) Projects, relationships, and reasons. In: Wallace RJ, Pettit P, Scheffler S, Smith M (eds) Reason and value: themes from the moral philosophy of Joseph Raz. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 247–269

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheffler S (2008) Potential congruence. In: Paul B (ed) Morality and self-interest. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 117–135

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheffler S (2010) Morality and reasonable partiality. In: Scheffler S (ed) Equality and tradition: questions of value in moral and political theory. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 41–75

    Google Scholar 

  • Shiffrin SV (1999) Moral overridingness and moral subjectivism. Ethics 109(4):772–794

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sobel S (2007) The impotence of the demandingness objection. Philos ' Impr 7(8):1–17

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson PF (2008) Freedom and resentment. In: Strawson PF (ed) Freedom and resentment and other essays. Routledge, pp 1–28

  • Stroud S (1998) Moral overridingness and moral theory. Pac Philos Q 79(2):170–189

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wallace RJ (2011) Dispassionate opprobrium: on blame and the reactive sentiments. In: Wallace RJ, Kumar R, Freeman S (eds) Reason and recognition: essays on the philosophy of T.M. Scanlon. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 348–372

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wallace RJ (2012) Duties of love. Proc Aristot Soc 86(1):175–198

  • Wallace RJ (2014) The deontic structure of morality. In: Bakhurst D, Hooker B, Little MO (eds) Thinking about reasons: themes from the philosophy of Jonathan Dancy. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 137–167

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace RJ (2019) The moral nexus. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Williams B (1973a) Persons, character and morality. In: Williams B (ed) Moral luck: philosophical papers 1973–1980. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 1–19

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams B (1973b) Moral luck. In: Williams B (ed) Moral luck: philosophical papers 1973–1980. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 20–39

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams B (2006) Ethics and the limits of philosophy. Routledge, Abingdon

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wolf S (2015a) Moral saints. In: Wolf S (ed) The variety of values: essays on morality, meaning and love. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 11–29

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wolf S (2015b) Morality and partiality. In: Wolf S (ed) The variety of values: essays on morality, meaning and love. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 31–46

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wolf S (2015c) On thought too many: love, morality, and the ordering of commitment. In: Wolf S (ed) The variety of values: essays on morality, meaning and love. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 143–169

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This work was partially supported by the Japan Society for the Promotion of Science, Grant-in-Aid for JSPS Fellows (15J07262). I thank Masashi Yazawa and Jun-ichi Saito for their patient advice and criticism. I would also like to thank Takafumi Abe, Wataru Inukai, Masaya Miyamoto, Hiroki Narita, Satoshi Okuno, Ryo Ogawa, Shinichi Tabata, Yoshiki Yoshimura, and participants in seminars at Waseda University for their helpful feedback and suggestions on various versions of the manuscript. Finally, I would like to express my gratitude to the two anonymous reviewers for this journal for their very careful, constructive, and incisive comments, which resulted in substantial revisions that greatly improved the paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ken Oshitani.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author has no relevant financial or non-financial interests to disclose.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Oshitani, K. Contractualism and the Moral Point of View. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 25, 667–684 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-022-10310-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-022-10310-y

Keywords

Navigation