Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

The problem with appealing to history in defining neural representations

  • Paper in the Philosophy of the Sciences of Mind and Brain
  • Published:
European Journal for Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Representations seem to play a major role in many neuroscientific explanations. Philosophers have long attempted to properly define what it means for a neural state to be a representation of a specific content. Teleosemantic theories of content which characterize representations, in part, by appealing to a historical notion of function, are often regarded as our best path towards an account of neural representations. This paper points to the anti-representationalist consequences of these accounts. I argue that assuming such teleosemantic views will deprive representations of their explanatory role in computational explanations. My argument rests on the claim that many explanations in cognitive neuroscience are entirely independent of any historical considerations. In making this claim, I will also offer an adapted version of the famous Swampperson thought experiment, which is better suited to discussions of subpersonal neural representations.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I will sometimes use the term ‘historical teleosemantics’ to refer to such theories, and there are a few cases where I talk of ‘teleosemantics’, which should also be understood as regarding only historical accounts. In general, most teleosemantic theories, and certainly the most prominent ones, do appeal to history, but there are also non-historical teleosemantic accounts (e.g. Nanay, 2010, 2014).

  2. Perhaps one might wonder whether a simple distinction between mechanistic and etiological explanations will be good enough to make this claim (Craver, 2007, 2013). There are a couple of reasons why I do not take this route. First, it will demand some assumptions on the nature of mechanistic explanations and some commitment to the characterization of the relevant neuroscientific explanations as mechanistic. But more importantly, I do not find it to be trivially true that all mechanistic explanations are entirely independent of any historical considerations. For example, it is possible that Shea’s objection, discussed in section 5, can be construed as the claim that some mechanistic explanations (in particular, those that invoke representations) are indeed dependent on history. The line of argument in this paper is meant to deal with such objections and enable the strongest possible claim regarding the irrelevance of history, without assuming any characterization of neuroscientific explanations.

  3. See short discussion in (Neander, 2012).

  4. It is also worth noting that Porter (2020) has recently offered a different type of Swampperson argument against teleosemantics, which aims to show the existence of real-world cases of Swampperson-like representations. I thank an anonymous reviewer for bringing this to light.

  5. This explanation has already been featured in the philosophical literature numerous times (e.g. Bechtel & Shagrir, 2015; Shagrir, 2018; Hacohen, 2022), in part thanks to its simplicity.

  6. Notably, this (Robinson, 1989) explanation of VOR is consistent with the contemporary textbook explanation (see Leigh & Zee, 2015, chapters 3 and 6).

  7. Such states are consistent with Ramsey’s (2007, chapter 4) ‘receptor notion’ which he claims does not do any explanatory work as a representation.

  8. As Chomsky (1995, p. 55) says of Marr’s (1982) theory of vision: “The theory itself has no place for the [intentional] concepts that enter into the informal presentation, intended for general motivation.”

  9. In the next section I consider an objection from Shea (2018) that claims that the phenomenon of VOR, understood in this manner, is not enough to define the relevant explanandum.

  10. In general, it is highly likely that considering how something came to be, can help us understand how it currently functions. Miłkowski (2016) discusses the ways history can figure into explanations of How-questions. I agree that history can play a role in explaining how-questions, but I think that in many existing computational explanations- it doesn’t. And, as I argue later on, the extent and significance of these non-historical explanations, should give pause to any proponent of historical teleosemantics.

  11. For example, Millikan (1996) makes the claim that Swampperson would not share the same ‘real’ kind as other humans (besides Davidson), and therefore we cannot deduce anything about human intentional states by thinking about Swampperson. But the current swampperson argument doesn’t deduce anything about human intentional states. We only deduce something about the explanation of VOR. And even if Swampperson doesn’t share a real kind with humans, we can still claim that the explanation of VOR applies to Swampperson, since the same explanation can apply to different kinds. Shea (2018, p. 170) also offers some criticism of Millikan’s reply.

  12. Such a scenario was not considered in section 4, but it should not be difficult to imagine. For example, suppose someone were placed in a lab with electrodes that artificially alter the discharge rate of her primary vestibular afferents. The explanation of VOR that was given in section 3 will allow us to successfully predict that this person would not be able to maintain her steady gaze. We can also explain why not. Now, the same would be true if we imagine the physical duplicate of this person in an identical scenario. Just as before, we would be able to predict that this swampperson replica would not maintain steady gaze, and we would offer exactly the same explanation as to why not.

  13. After Swampperson has had some time to interact with its environment, Shea does think a “successful” pattern of behavior could be established, which in turn would allow Swampperson to have representational states.

  14. That is why this reflex is normally suppressed during free-head pursuit (Cullen, 2012; Ackerly & Barnes, 2011).

  15. Historical notions of function have also had to face swampperson type objections (e.g. Boorse, 1976).

  16. As mentioned earlier, there is a wide variety of representational views that are (arguably) non-historical (e.g. Fodor, 1987, 1990; Cummins, 1989, 1996; Egan, 2012, 2014, 2018; Sprevak, 2013; Hacohen, 2022; Nanay, 2010, 2014).

References

  • Ackerley, R., & Barnes, G. R. (2011). The interaction of visual, vestibular and extra-retinal mechanisms in the control of head and gaze during head-free pursuit. The Journal of Physiology, 589(7), 1627–1642.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Shagrir, O. (2015). The non-redundant contributions of Marr’s three levels of analysis for explaining information-processing mechanisms. Topics in Cognitive Science, 7(2), 312–322.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bigelow, J., & Pargetter, R. (1987). Function. Journal of Philosophy, 84(4), 181–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boorse, C. (1976). Wright on functions. The Philosophical Review, 85(1), 70–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chemero, A. (2009). Radical embodied cognitive science. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1995). Language and nature. Mind, 104(413), 1–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2001). Role functions, mechanisms, and hierarchy. Philosophy of Science, 68, 53–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2007). Explaining the brain. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2013). Functions and mechanisms: A perspectivalist view, In functions: Selection and mechanisms (pp. 133–158). Springer.

  • Cullen, K. E. (2012). The vestibular system: Multimodal integration and encoding of self-motion for motor control. Trends in Neurosciences, 35(3), 185–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, R. (1989). Meaning and mental representation. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, R. (1996). Representations, targets, and attitudes. MIT press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, R., & Roth, M. (2010). Traits have not evolved to function the way they do because of a past advantage (pp. 72–88). Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Biology.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1987). Knowing one’s own mind. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 60, 441–58.

  • Davies, P. S. (2001). Norms of nature: Naturalism and the nature of functions. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1988). Explaining behavior: Reasons in a world of causes. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1995). Naturalizing the mind. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1996). Absent qualia. Mind and Language, 11(1), 70–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Egan, F. (2012). Representationalism. In E. Margolis, R. Samuels, & S. Stich (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of cognitive science (pp.250–72). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Egan, F. (2014). How to think about mental content. Philosophical Studies, 170(1), 115–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Egan, F. (2018). The nature and function of content in computational models, in the Routledge handbook of the computational mind, M. Sprevak and M. Colombo (eds.), Routledge, 247-258.

  • Fodor, J. A. (1987). Psychosemantics: The problem of meaning in the philosophy of mind. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1990). A theory of content and other essays. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A., & Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1988). Connectionism and cognitive architecture: A critical analysis. Cognition, 28(1), 3–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garson, J. (2019). There are no ahistorical theories of function. Philosophy of Science, 86(5), 1146–1156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacohen, O. (2022). What are neural representations? A Cummins functions approach. Philosophy of Science, 1–39. https://doi.org/10.1017/psa.2022.6

  • Hardcastle, V. G. (2002). On the normativity of functions. In A. Ariew, R. Cummins, & M. Perlman (Eds.), Functions: New essays in the philosophy of psychology and biology (pp. 144–156). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D., & Myin, E. (2013). Radicalizing enactivism: Basic minds without content. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leigh, R. J., & Zee, D. S. (2015). The neurology of eye movements (Fifth ed.). Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lorente de Nó, R. (1931). Ausgewalte Kapitel aus der vergleichenden Physiologie des Labyrinthes. Die Augenmuskel-refiexe beim Kaninchen und ihre Grundlagen. Ergeb. PhysioL Bioi. Chern. Exp. PharmakoL, 32, 73–242.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lorente de Nó, R. (1933). Vestibulo-ocular reflex arc. Arch. Neurol. Psychiatr. Chicago, 30, 245–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Magnus, R. (1924). Kiirperstellung (740 pp). Springer.

  • Maley, C. J., & Piccinini, G. (2017). A unified mechanistic account of teleological functions for psychology and neuroscience. In D. M. Kaplan (Ed.), Integrating mind and brain science: Mechanistic perspectives and beyond (pp. 236–256). Oxford University Press.

  • Marr, D. (1982). Vision. W.H. Freeman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miłkowski, M. (2016). Function and causal relevance of content. New Ideas in Psychology, 40, 94–102.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (1984). Language, thought and other biological categories. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (1989). Biosemantics. Journal of Philosophy, 86, 281–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (1996). On Swampkinds. Mind & Language, 11, 103–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (2004). Varieties of meaning. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, A. (2014). Representations gone mental. Synthese, 191(2), 213–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. (2010). A modal theory of function. The Journal of Philosophy, 107(8), 412–431.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. (2014). Teleosemantics without etiology. Philosophy of Science, 81(5), 798–810.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neander, K. (1991). Functions as selected effects: The conceptual analyst’s defense. Philosophy of Science, 58(2), 168–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neander, K. (1995). Misrepresenting & malfunctioning. Philosophical Studies, 79(2), 109–141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neander, K. (1996). Swampman meets swampcow. Mind & Language, 11(1), 118–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neander, K. (2012). Teleological Theories of Mental Content. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2012 Edition). Retrieved from <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2012/entries/content-teleological/>.

  • Neander, K. (2017). A mark of the mental: In defense of informational teleosemantics. MIT Press.

  • Papineau, D. (2001). The status of teleosemantics, or how to stop worrying about swampman. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 79(2), 279–289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, G. (2008). Computation without representation. Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition, 137(2), 205–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Porter, B. (2020). Teleosemantics and tetrachromacy. Biology and Philosophy, 35(1), 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, W. (2007). Representation reconsidered. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, D. A. (1968). Eye movement control in primates. Science, 161, 1219–1224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, D. A. (1970). Oculomotor unit behavior in the monkey. Journal of Neurophysiology, 33, 393–404.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, D. A. (1989). Integrating with neurons. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 12, 33–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shadmehr, R., & Wise, S. P. (2005). The computational neurobiology of reaching and pointing: A foundation for motor learning. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shagrir, O. (2006). Why we view the brain as a computer. Synthese, 153(3), 393–416.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shagrir, O. (2012). Structural representations and the brain. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 63(3), 519–545.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shagrir, O. (2018). The brain as an input–output model of the world. Minds and Machines, 28(1), 53–75.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shea, N. (2018). Representation in cognitive science. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sprevak, M. (2011). Review of representation reconsidered by William Ramsey. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62, 669–675.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sprevak, M. (2013). Fictionalism about neural representations. The Monist, 96(4), 539–560.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tinbergen, N. (1963). On aims and methods of ethology. Zeitschrift für Tierpsychologie, 20(4), 410–433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I thank Oron Shagrir, Arnon Levy, and two anonymous reviewers for their helpful remarks. I also thank the Edelstein Center for the history and philosophy of science, for supporting this work.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ori Hacohen.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

I hereby state that this paper is an original work of which I am the sole author. Furthermore, there are no potential conflicts of interest, and there was no research involving humans/animals.

Additional information

Publisher’s note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Hacohen, O. The problem with appealing to history in defining neural representations. Euro Jnl Phil Sci 12, 45 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-022-00473-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-022-00473-x

Keywords

Navigation