Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-2lccl Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-27T02:22:14.245Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Distributing the costs of change: property transitions and pacts

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 June 2022

Rachael Walsh*
Affiliation:
Assistant Professor, School of Law, Trinity College Dublin, Dublin, Ireland
*
*Corresponding author. E-mail: rachael.walsh@tcd.ie

Extract

In A Liberal Theory of Property (2021), Hanoch Dagan makes an important, thought-provoking contribution to property theory – one that unifies divergent, and at time apparently dichotomous, strands of thought in property theory and revives rich dormant ideas. Dagan persuasively centres property's justification and design on the value of autonomy and on the basic need for reciprocal recognition of the individual right to self-determination. He does so without excluding the relevance and significance of other property values, both public and private. The theory deepens existing debates within property scholarship about values such as freedom and personhood, and provides a wide-reaching analysis of how autonomy functions as property's telos. That telos is used to justify structural pluralism in property law and to delimit owners’ rights. In this way, for Dagan, property's justification determines the nature and ambit of private authority over resources.

Type
Review Symposium
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Alexander, GS (2018) Property and Human Flourishing, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Calfee, C (2006) Kelo v. City of New London: the more things stay the same, the more they change. Ecology Law Quarterly 33, 545581.Google Scholar
Capper, D (2015) Contracts for the sale of land: understanding the impecuniosity defence. In Lichere, F and Weaver, RL (eds), Remedies and Property, Vol. 2. Presses Universitaires d'Aix-Marseille, pp. 3756. Available at: https://pureadmin.qub.ac.uk/ws/portalfiles/portal/29105467/CONTRACTS_FOR_THE_SALE_OF_LAND.pdf (accessed 7 September 2021).Google Scholar
Dagan, H (2021) A Liberal Theory of Property. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kochan, DJ (1998) ‘Public use’ and the independent judiciary: condemnation in an interest-group perspective. Texas Review of Law and Policy 3, 49116.Google Scholar
Lehavi, A (2010) The dynamic law of property: theorizing the role of legal standards. Rutgers Law Journal 42, 81140.Google Scholar
Merriam, D (2016) Time to make lemonade from the lemons of the Kelo case. Connecticut Law Review 48, 15691591.Google Scholar
Michelman, FI (1992) Liberties, fair values, and constitutional method. University of Chicago Law Review 59, 91114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peterson, AL (1989) The Takings Clause: in search of underlying principles: Part I: A critique of current takings clause doctrine. California Law Review 77, 12991363.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Radin, MJ (1995) Reinterpreting Property. Chicago: Chicago University Press.Google Scholar
Rose, CM (1984) Mahon reconstructed: why the takings issue is still a muddle. Southern California Law Review 57, 561599.Google Scholar
Underkuffler, LS (2007) Property as constitutional myth: utilities and dangers. Cornell Law Review 92, 12391254.Google Scholar
Van der Walt, AJ and Walsh, R (2017) Comparative constitutional property law. In Graziadei, M and Smith, L (eds), Comparative Property Law: Global Perspectives. Cheltenham/Northampton: Edward Elgar, pp 193215.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Waldron, J (1990) The Right to Private Property. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walsh, R (2021) Property Rights and Social Justice: Progressive Property in Action. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar