Skip to main content
Log in

Expressing Gratitude as What’s Morally Expected: A Phenomenological Approach

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper addresses an alleged paradox regarding gratitude—that a duty of gratitude is odd or puzzling if not paradoxical. The gist of our position is that in prototypical cases, gratitude expression falls under a distinctive deontic category we call morally expected—which has a corresponding contrary deontic category we call morally offensive. These categories, we maintain, need recognition in normative ethics to make proper sense of the moral status of gratitude expression and other morally charged restrictions on action, and likewise to make proper sense of the moral status of failures to abide by such restrictions. We argue for our view largely on phenomenological grounds.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. On this puzzle, see Lyons 1969, Berger 1975, Weiss 1985, Card 1988, Wellman 1999, Manela 2015, and Martin 2019.

  2. See, e.g. McConnell 1993, ch. 2, Manela 2015.

  3. See, e.g. Wellman 1999, who argues there is no duty of gratitude and who thereby seems committed to this view, although he is not fully overt about gratitude expression being deontically purely optional. For a reply to Wellman (besides our own featured in this paper) see Carr 2013. See also Carr 2015 on whether gratitude (as a trait) is a virtue.

  4. Walker 198081 and McAleer 2012 recognize what the latter calls ‘propositional gratitude’—gratitude that, involving a two-place relation between a beneficiary and some welcome state of affairs. That the phenomenon in question is a genuine form of gratitude is challenged by Manela 2016a.

  5. For some empirical support for this claim see Lambert, et al. 2009.

  6. Cheshire Calhoun 2016 and Adrienne Martin 2019 defend views that recognize morally significant kinds of action (and omission) that are in some respects similar to our category of the morally expected. Calhoun argues that philosophical ethics should recognize what she calls “common decencies”—a category whose extension overlaps, if not coincides with, what we are calling the morally expected. Martin explores the nature of directed personal obligations, as for example between parents and their children, as a basis for understanding the relationship between a benefactor and their beneficiary. However, unlike us, Martin holds that there is an obligation of gratitude that is limited in scope in the sense that the benefactor has standing to direct the beneficiary to have the end of expressing gratitude, though no standing to direct the means of doing so. It seems to us that the direction in which Martin goes in attempting to accommodate the status of gratitude fits more comfortably with our proposal for recognizing the deontic category of the morally expected than it fits with her own proposal to expand the category of the obligatory. Exploring the similarities and differences between our view, Calhoun’s, and Martin’s is a topic for a separate paper.

  7. The categories of supererogation and suberogation are hybrid concepts, which include a deontic aspect and an evaluative/aretaic aspect. Supererogatory actions are deontically optional and praiseworthy to perform, while those who posit the suberogatory tend to understand it to be a hybrid category—blameworthy to perform yet having the deontic status of being purely optional. We too regard it as hybrid, although we also think that its deontic aspect is moral offensiveness. We’ll say more about the suberogatory in Sect. 6. But in any case, we have not included the categories of the supererogatory and the suberogatory in the diagram because we, like others who have deployed these categories, regard them as hybrid rather than as purely deontic. For a defense of the hybrid nature of these categories, see MacNamara 2011.

  8. We are using these labels for deontic categories, and for different kinds of reasons, in a narrow and mutually-exclusionary way, rather than widely. In a wider sense of ‘favoring’, any of these kinds of reasons for performing (not performing) A is a favoring reason for performing (not performing) A. And in wider senses of ‘expected’ and ‘offensive’, actions that are required are also expected, and actions that are wrong are also offensive.

  9. We use this term without intending any entailment of duty or obligation.

  10. For detailed discussions of the phenomenology of obligation (duty), see Horgan and Timmons 2005, 2008, and 2010a.

  11. Such positive affective experiences associated with expressing gratitude, including joy, are emphasized in Emmons 2007. However, as Manela 2016b points out, there can be cases involving negative feelings of gratitude.

  12. The experiential state-types we are here calling ‘seemings’ are distinct from the state-types we are calling experience-based judgments, even though such judgments often inherit their intentional content from the corresponding seemings. (This inheritance sometimes might be a causal relation between a token seeming and a token judgment; sometimes it might instead involve a single state-token that simultaneously tokens both the seeming-type and the judgment-type.) The Mueller Lyer illusion, for example, is a visual-experiential seeming as-of two horizontal lines being equal in length; but if one is aware of the illusory nature of this experience, one will refrain from judging that the lines are the same length. The reason we distinguish seemings from experience-based judgments will emerge in the paragraphs immediately below.

  13. Advocates of the view that gratitude expression is obligatory, insofar as they grant (as they typically do) that the benefactor has no right to demand compliance by the recipient, also face the highly non-trivial task of providing a moral-normative rationale for this lack of a correlative right to demand compliance. No such normative-ethical burden arises if, as we contend, gratitude expression normally is morally expected and hence not morally obligatory.

  14. Here we follow Driver’s 1992 influential discussion of the suberogatory.

  15. Even so, and as noted above in note 7, we agree with the standard claim that the suberogatory is a hybrid category, with evaluative and/or aretaic aspects in addition to its deontic aspect. In paradigmatic cases, for instance, the agent not only performs a morally offensive action, but also does so knowingly and willingly.

  16. For an overview of the work in question, see Davidson and Wood 2016.

  17. Gulliford and colleagues 2013 note an absence of attention by psychologists and philosophers on the intrinsic value of gratitude and speculate that it is because work on gratitude tends to suffer from ambiguity between instrumental and intrinsic justifications of gratitude.

  18. See the study by Algoe et al. 2008.

  19. For a study dissociating indebtedness (duty) from gratitude see, for example, Watkins, et al. 2006.

  20. Algoe borrows the distinction from Clark and Mills 1993, 2001 whose exchange/community distinction between relationships concerns benefits conferred, where the basic contrast is exemplified by e.g. business relationships (exchange) and relationships where “benefits are given without the donor or the recipient feeling the recipient has an obligation to repay” (2001:3). As they write, the norms governing communal relationships are such that the donor “can’t demand” the sort of responsiveness from the recipient as one can within exchange relationships (Ibid, our emphasis).

  21. We are grateful to Robert Audi, Keith Lehrer, Michael McKenna, Robert Wallace, and anonymous referees for this journal for their helpful comments on earlier drafts of this article.

References

  • Algoe SB (2012) Find, Remind, and Bind: The Functions of Gratitude in Everyday Relationships. Soc Personal Compass 6:455–469

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Algoe SB, Haidt J, Gable SL (2008). Beyond Reciprocity: Gratitude and Relationships in Everyday Life. Emotion 8:425–429

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berger F (1975) Gratitude. Ethics 85:298–309

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Calhoun C (2016) Common Decency In: Moral Aims: Essays on the Importance of Getting it Right and Practicing Morality. Oxford University Press (2016), Oxford, pp 104–122

  • Card C (1988) Gratitude and Obligation. Am Philos Q 25:115–127

    Google Scholar 

  • Carr D (2013) Varieties of Gratitude. J Value Inq 47:17–28

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carr D (2015) Is Gratitude a Moral Virtue? Philos Stud 172:1475–1484

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark MS, Mills JR (1993) The Difference between Communal and Exchange Relationships: What it is and what it is Not. Pers Soc Psychol Bull 19:684–691

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark MS, Mills JR (2001) A Theory of Communal (and Exchange) Relationships. In: Van Lange PAM, Kruglanski AW, Higgins ET (eds) Handbook of Theories of Social Psychology, vol 2. Sage, Los Angeles, CA, pp 232–250

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson A, Wood AM (2016) The State of Psychological Research into Gratitude and the Need for More Interdisciplinary Collaboration. In: Carr D (ed) Perspectives on Gratitude: An Interdisciplanary Approach. Routledge, New York, pp 215–228

    Google Scholar 

  • Driver J (1992) The Suberogatory. Australas J Philos 70:286–295

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Emmons R (2007) Thanks: How the New Science of Gratitude Can Make You Happier. Houghton Mifflin Co., Boston & New York

  • Gulliford L, Morgan B, Kristjánsson K (2013) Recent Work on the Concept of Gratitude in Philosophy and Psychology. J Value Inq 47:285–317

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horgan T, Timmons M (2005) Moral Phenomenology and Moral Theory. Philos Issues 15:56–77

  • Horgan T, Timmons M (2008) What Can Moral Phenomenology Tell Us About Moral Objectivity? Soc Phil Policy 25:267–300

  • Horgan T, Timmons M (2010a) Mandelbaum on Moral Phenomenology and Moral Realism. In Verstegan IF (ed) Maurice Mandelbaum and American Critical Realism. Routledge, New York, pp 105–126

  • Horgan T, Timmons M (2010b) Untying a Knot From the Inside Out: Reflections on the ‘Paradox’ of Supererogation. Soc Phil Policy 27:29–63

  • Lambert N, Graham S, Fincham F (2009) A Prototype Analysis of Gratitude: Varieties of Gratitude Experience. Pers Soc Psychol Bull 35:1193–1207

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lyons D (1969) The Odd Debt of Gratitude. Analysis 29:92–97

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacNamara P (2011) Supererogation, Inside and Out: Toward an Adequate Scheme for Common-Sense Morality. In: Timmons M (ed) Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics, vol 1. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 202–235

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Manela T (2015) Obligations of Gratitude and Correlative Rights. In: Timmons M (ed) Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics, vol 5. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 151–170

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Manela T (2016a) Gratitude and Appreciation. Am Philos Q 53:281–294

    Google Scholar 

  • Manela T (2016b) Negative Feelings of Gratitude. J Value Inq 50:129–140

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin AM (2019) Obligations of Gratitude: Directedness without Rights. In: Roberts R, Teloch D (eds) The Moral Psychology of Gratitude. Rowman & Littlefield, Lanham, MD, pp 59–82

    Google Scholar 

  • McAleer S (2012) Propositional Gratitude. Am Philos Q 49:55–66

    Google Scholar 

  • McConnell T (1993) Gratitude. Temple University Press, Philadelphia, PA

    Google Scholar 

  • Trivers RL (1971) The Evolution of Reciprocal Altruism. Q Rev Biol 46:35–57

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walker ADM (1980–81) Gratefulness and Gratitude. Proc Aristot Soc 81: 35–55

  • Watkins PC, Scheer J, Ovnicek M, Kolts R (2006) The Debt of Gratitude: Dissociating Gratitude and Indebtedness. Cogn Emot 20:217–241

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weiss R (1985) The Moral and Social Dimensions of Gratitude. South J Philos 23:491–501

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wellman CH (1999) Gratitude as a Virtue. Pac Philos Q 80:284–230

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mark Timmons.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest/Competing Interests

The authors have no relevant financial or non-financial interests to disclose. The authors have no conflicts of interest to declare that are relevant to the content of this article. All authors certify that they have no affiliations with or involvement in any organization or entity with any financial interest or non-financial interest in the subject matter or materials discussed in this manuscript. The authors have no financial or proprietary interests in any material discussed in this article.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Horgan, T., Timmons, M. Expressing Gratitude as What’s Morally Expected: A Phenomenological Approach. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 25, 139–155 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-021-10261-w

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-021-10261-w

Keywords

Navigation