Skip to main content
Log in

Idealizations and Partitions: A Defense of Robustness Analysis

  • Paper in Philosophy of Science in Practice
  • Published:
European Journal for Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We argue that the robustness analysis of idealized models can have confirmational power. This responds to concerns recently raised in the literature (especially by Odenbaugh & Alexandrova), according to which (a) the robustness analysis of models whose idealizations are not discharged is unable to confirm the causal mechanisms underlying these models, and (b) the robustness analysis of models whose idealizations are discharged is unnecessary. In response, we make clear that, where idealizations sweep out, in a specific way, the space of possibilities— which is sometimes, though not always, the case—they can be holistically discharged. In turn, this can be used to show that the robustness analysis of idealized models can have confirmational force after all.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. There is some debate as to what exactly the confirmation is about. As Weisberg (2006) notes, the confirmation could be from the core assumptions of the model to a predicted consequence, or it could be the other way around. In what follows, we follow Alexandrova & Odenbaugh (2011) and focus on the latter case; however, the conclusions below can be easily reformulated with a view towards the former account.

  2. Odenbaugh and Alexandrova (2011) distinguish two types of idealizations (see also Kuorikoski et al., 2010): Galilean idealizations—which remove some possible confounding causal factors—and tractability idealizations—which are mathematical “niceties” introduced to ensure the model functions at all. For present purposes, a closer analysis of this is not necessary, though.

  3. It is important to note how this criticism is distinct from concerns about the independence of models. Even if the relevant models are all independent, arguments like those expressed by Alexandrova and Odenbaugh suggest that RA fails to be confirmatory. Since none of the models in question are accurate reflections of the target system, drawing a conclusion about the target system from this set is premature. What we can derive from the RA is that the result can be achieved from many counterfactual, often simplified, situations. What needs to be done, though, is connecting at least one of these counterfactuals to the real world through discharging assumptions. But this would mean that there is no need for the RA. Regardless of how model independence is determined, there remains this further concern.

  4. Weisberg (2006) also responds to Orzack and Sober (1993). However, he does this by noting that “robust theorems” of the above sort are really only a part of RA. The latter is about determining the core, shared structure of a set of models that is responsible for deriving an empirically confirmed result, and then using a variety-of-evidence argument to obtain confirmation for the robust theorem in question. However, our point here is that there is more that can be said on behalf of the confirmational properties of RA. See also Justus (2012).

  5. Levins’s presentation of robustness had a slightly different approach, as his focus was on whether the prediction M- > P—“the robust theorem”—could be considered true. However, as also noted by Odenbaugh (2011, 1179), much of Levins’s discussion can be appropriately tweaked so as to fit the presentation of Alexandrova & Odenbaugh (2011). See also below.

  6. It is debatable how much conformation it provides. However, this can be left open here; for present purposes, it is just important that it provides some confirmation.

  7. See Pincock, 2011 pg. 99 for a discussion of deep-water wave models.

  8. Note also that the set of idealized values cannot be seen as an estimate of the depth of the ocean floor, as that depth varies. This set of idealized values is literally just the range of the depth of the ocean floor, not an estimate of it at any given point.

  9. Note that if we expected the shape, or change in depth of the ocean floor within our range of possibilities to be causally relevant, this would then be included in our set C, and so the model would be different.

  10. Of course, if the variation in the depth of the ocean floor is suspected to be causally relevant, then presenting the ocean floor as a single value would be inappropriate: the above set of models then is not a good partitioning of the space of possibilities, and would need to include the variation as well.

  11. There are other typical assumptions, such as there only being two “kinds” rather than a broader diversity.

  12. A further question that might be raised here concerns whether our response to Alexandrova and Odenbaugh’s argument surreptitiously requires models that lack independence. However, as noted above, we set this question aside here. On the one hand, while, as also noted earlier, the characterization of model independence is far from clear, there is no obvious reason why assuming the ocean floor has consistent depth of x meters and assuming it has a consistent depth of y meters (where x and y are different) are not independent assumptions (for example). On the other hand—and most importantly—we ignore the question of model independence here because, as stated above, the argument presented by Alexandrova and Odenbaugh is meant to show that RA is not confirmatory at all. If the main concern is an issue of model independence, then we can move on from Alexandrova and Odenbaugh’s argument as spurious, and the focus should be on defining model independence.

  13. Note also that Levins (1993, p. 555) responded to the criticisms leveled by Orzack and Sober (and others like them) by arguing that observation is relevant to “the choice of the core model and the selection of plausible variable parts.” Odenbaugh (2011) takes this to mean that we need to have empirical evidence for the set of core causal assumptions of the model—and then rightfully points out that, in that case, the idealizations of the model do not really matter, since we have empirical evidence for the representational parts of the model already. However, here, it is the second part of Levins’s statement that matters: What we need—and may well have—is evidence for the “variable parts of the model.”

    It is the latter kind of evidence that can give RA a confirmatory role to play.

  14. As noted in the example of models of waves, this may even be plausible for some models of wave formation in oceans, where an infinite ocean depth may be assumed.

  15. We thank an anonymous referee for useful discussion of this point.

  16. Note also that Schupbach’s account is more general and is intended to apply not just to models.

  17. Incidentally, this is quite in line with Popper’s account of corroboration: see Popper (2002, chap. 10).

  18. Levins, 1993 pg. 554.

References

  • Alexandrova, A. (2008). Making Models Count. Philosophy of Science, 75(3), 383–404.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abraham, B., & Ledolter, J. (2006). Introduction to Regression Modeling (1st ed.). Cengage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brössel, P., & Huber, F. (2015). Bayesian Confirmation: A Means with No End. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 66(4), 737–749.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1983). How the laws of physics lie. Oxford : New York: Clarendon Press ; Oxford University Press.

  • Craver, C. (2007). Explaining the brain : Mechanisms and the mosaic unity of neuroscience. Oxford : New York : Oxford University Press: Clarendon Press;.

  • De Regt, H. (2009). Understanding and Scientific Explanation. In De Regt et al.

  • de Regt, H. W., Leonelli, S., & Eigner, K. (2009). Scientific understanding : philosophical perspectives. University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Grimm, S. (2010). The goal of explanation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science. Part A, 41(4), 337–344.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grimm, S. (2018). Making sense of the world : new essays on the philosophy of understanding. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Justus, J. (2012). The Elusive Basis of Inferential Robustness. Philosophy of Science, 79(5), 795–807.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Khalifa, K. (2013) The Role of Explanation in Understanding. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science64(1): 161-187.

  • Khalifa, K. (2017) Understanding, explanation, and scientific knowledge. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press.

  • Kuorikoski, J., Lehtinen, A., & Marchionni, C. (2010). Economic Modelling as Robustness Analysis. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 61(3), 541–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levins, R. (1966). The Strategy of Model Building In Population Biology. American Scientist, 54(4), 421–431.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levins, R. (1993). A Response to Orzack and Sober: Formal Analysis and the Fluidity of Science. The Quarterly Review of Biology, 68(4), 547–555.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd, E. (2015). Model robustness as a confirmatory virtue: The case of climate science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 49, 58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, M. (2012). The world in the model : How economists work and think. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press.

  • Morrison, M. (2015). Reconstructing reality : Models, mathematics, and simulations Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Odenbaugh, J. (2011). True Lies: Realism, Robustness, and Models. Philosophy of Science, 78(5), 1177–1188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Odenbaugh, J., & Alexandrova, A. (2011). Buyer beware: Robustness analyses in economics and biology. Biology and Philosophy, 26(5), 757–771.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Orzack, S., & Sober, E. (1993). A Critical Assessment of Levins's The Strategy of Model Building in Population Biology (1966). The Quarterly Review of Biology, 68(4), 533–546.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parker, W. (2011). When Climate Models Agree: The Significance of Robust Model Predictions. Philosophy of Science, 78(4), 579–600.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pincock, C. (2011). Mathematics and scientific representation. Oxford ; New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Popper, K. (2002). The Logic of Scientific Discovery. London, UK; New York: Routledge Classics.

  • Potochnik, A. (2016). Scientific Explanation. Putting Communication First. Philosophy of Science, 83(5), 721–732.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Potochnik, A. (2017). Idealization and Aims of Science. University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schelling, T. C. (1971). Dynamic models of segregation. Journal of Mathematical Sociology, 1(2), 143–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schupbach, J. (2018). Robustness Analysis as Explanatory Reasoning. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 69(1), 275–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (2008). Evidence and Evolution : The Logic Behind the Science. Cambridge, UK ; New York: Cambridge University Press.

  • Skow, B. (2016). Reasons Why. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Skow B. (2017) Against Understanding (as a Condition on Explanation), in Grimm 2018.

  • van Fraassen, B. (1980). The Scientific Image. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. (2006). Robustness Analysis. Philosophy of Science, 73(5), 730–742.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M., & Reisman, K. (2008). The Robust Volterra Principle. Philosophy of Science, 75(1), 106–131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen : A theory of causal explanation (Oxford studies in philosophy of science). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2006). Some varieties of robustness. Journal of Economic Methodology, 13(2), 219–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gareth P. Fuller.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest

The authors report no conflict of interest.

Ethical Approval

Not applicable.

Informed Consent

Not applicable.

Additional information

Publisher’s note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Fuller, G.P., Schulz, A.W. Idealizations and Partitions: A Defense of Robustness Analysis. Euro Jnl Phil Sci 11, 107 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-021-00428-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-021-00428-8

Keywords

Navigation