Skip to main content

Decisions of persons, the pharmaceutical industry, and donors in disease contraction and recovery assuming virus mutation

Abstract

Background

The article develops an eight-period game between N persons and a pharmaceutical company. The choices of a donor and Nature are parametric.

Methods

Persons choose between safe and risky behavior, and whether or not to buy drugs. The pharmaceutical company chooses whether or not to develop drugs. The donor chooses parametrically whether to subsidize drug purchases and drug developments. Nature chooses disease contraction, recovery, death, and virus mutation. The game is solved with backward induction.

Results

The conditions are specified for each of seven outcomes ranging from safe behavior to risky behavior and buying no or one or both drugs. The seven outcomes distribute themselves across three outcomes for the pharmaceutical company, which are to develop no drugs, develop one drug, and develop two drugs if the virus mutates. For these three outcomes the donor’s expected utility is specified.

Conclusion

HIV/AIDS data is used to present a procedure for parameter estimation. The players’ strategic choices are exemplified. The article shows how strategic interaction between persons and a pharmaceutical company, with parametric choices of a donor and Nature, impact whether persons choose risky or safe behavior, whether a pharmaceutical company develops no drugs or one drug, or two drugs if a virus mutates, and the impact of subsidies by a donor.

Background

Contribution

This article assesses the strategic choices of persons to engage in risky behavior and whether or not to buy drugs, a pharmaceutical company choosing whether to develop expensive drugs to combat disease, and a donor choosing parametrically whether to fund drug development and drug purchases for poor people in the face of declining aid flows and growing patient incomes.

An eight-period game is developed. A disease such as a HIV/AIDS or Covid-19 virus attacks a person or not, given that the person chooses risky behavior. The pharmaceutical company responds by developing or not developing drug 1 which the person buys or not and the donor subsidizes to a certain degree, or does not subsidize. The person responds positively and the virus is contained or it mutates. If it mutates, a drug 2 is or is not developed. Upon consuming or not consuming drug 2, the person recovers or dies.

The person’s expected utility is life. The pharmaceutical company’s expected profit follows from drugs being bought. The pharmaceutical company benefits if the person buys and consumes drug 1 or indeed drug 2 perpetually, like anti-retrovirus, or one off when the person recovers completely. The pharmaceutical company incurs costs of investing in drug research and development. The person pays for the drug or it is donor-funded through aid flows. Infected persons may suffer consequences such as losing their jobs or otherwise experience decreased life quality. The potential patient can also invest in acquiring knowledge on how not to contract the disease.

The article’s objectives and research questions are to determine the players’ optimal strategies, and how these strategies and the model parameters impact which of the seven outcomes emerges. The methods in the article are to solve the game with backward induction starting with period 8. In period 8 Nature chooses recovery versus death probabilistically. In period 7 a person buys drug 2, sponsored by a donor, if the benefits outweigh the costs. In period 6 the pharmaceutical company develops drug 2 sponsored by a donor, if the benefits outweigh the costs. In period 5 the virus mutates or does not mutate. In period 4 a person buys drug 1, sponsored by a donor, if the benefits outweigh the costs. In period 3 the pharmaceutical company develops drug 1 sponsored by a donor, if the benefits outweigh the costs. In period 2 Nature chooses disease contraction probabilistically. In period 1 the person chooses risky or safe behavior.

The model brings together persons which may contract a disease and purchase drugs, a pharmaceutical company which may or may not develop drugs, a donor which may or may not subsidize, a virus which may or may not mutate, and Nature which impacts disease contraction, recovery, and death.

The model’s assumptions are to consider diseases fulfilling three requirements. First, we assume that whether a person contracts the disease depends on whether the person chooses risky or safe behavior, e.g. using a condom against HIV or wearing a mask or keeping distance against Covid-19. Hence diseases are excluded which do not depend on the person’s behavior, which are genetic or hereditary, which are caused by the environment, or which depend on economic and political factors and societal trends outside the person’s control. Second, we assume that one or two drugs can be developed to potentially cure a disease. If one or two drugs cannot be developed, the model reduces to the special case where the one or two drugs are not available. Third, we assume that disease recovery is possible to some extent with or without one or two drugs. We allow for great variation in the degree of recovery, from complete recovery, via some recovery, no recovery, and death.

The model’s assumptions abstracts away healthcare workers, hospitals, governments, international organizations, and various other players in our health and political/economical systems. These other players are crucial, e.g. as advisors, facilitators, and providers of knowledge and services. By abstracting away these other players and factors, we are able to focus explicitly on the strategic interaction between the N persons, the pharmaceutical company, the donor (which is parametric in the analysis), and Nature.

The model helps understand individual behavior regarding contracting disease and the purchasing of drugs when interacting with a pharmaceutical company which may or may not develop drugs, a donor which may or may not subsidize, and Nature which may precariously determine disease contraction, recovery, death, and virus mutation. The model is integrated in the sense that it brings the relevant players together in the decision making process.

Empirical data is provided of HIV/AIDS data for prevalence, deaths, HIV expenditure, treatment costs, R&D costs and revenues, and HIV resource availability are presented. In 2019, 38 million people lived with HIV/AIDS.Footnote 1 Using the data, a procedure is presented for estimating the model parameters. An example shows how the players’ strategic decisions may cause various outcomes.

The literature

Game theoretic analysis of interaction between persons and a pharmaceutical company is uncommon. Four game theoretic studies have been identified. Hausken and Ncube [18, 19] analyze interactions between policy makers choosing resource allocation between prevention and treatment of disease, the international community choosing funding to treat disease, and Nature choosing which proportion of the population contracts disease, and which fractions remains sick or does, versus recovers. Mamani, Chick, and Simchi-Levi [29] develop a game theoretic model of international influenza vaccination coordination. Hausken and Ncube [20] consider a game between a drug company and patients which contemplate whether to purchase a drug.

Aside from these four studies, the literature is more tangential to this article. A literature does exist on disease treatment and prevention. Below we review this literature, and attempt to explain or justify their interest for this article, which is implicitly focused on disease treatment and prevention. The literature focuses strongly on treatment rather than prevention, in contrast to this article which focuses on how drugs may or may not be developed and funded as a consequence of a disease being contracted or not contracted. For example, Thomas [35], Kremer and Glennerster [25], and Kremer and Snyder [26, 27] suggest that incentives for drug development for treatment outweigh incentives for vaccine development for prevention. Potentially, with such a focus more citizens may become sick, causing more resources to treatment than prevention.

With the strong focus on treatment in the literature, Hecht et al. [21] and Izazola-Licea et al. [24] assess the financing of the response to HIV/AIDS in low-income and middle-income countries. West and Schneider [38] estimate revenues for HIV/AIDS treatment for the years 2017–2021 for various African countries. Forsythe et al. [13] assess the global costs, health achievements, and economic benefits of 20 years of ART (antiretroviral therapy) for people living with HIV. DiMasi et al. [11] stipulate $2.6 billion for HIV drug R&D costs for the years 2017–2021. Coates, Richter, and Caceres [8] evaluate behavioral strategies to reduce HIV transmission. Moxnes and Hausken [31] model acute virus influenza A infections.

For research on treatment versus prevention see Boily et al. [5], Bertozzi et al. [4], Canning [6], Alistar and Brandeau [1], Bärnighausen, Salomon, and Sangrujee [3], Gonsalves [16], Kumaranayake, Watts, Dixon, Mc Donald, and Roberts [28], and Paltiel and Stinnett [32], and the HIV Modelling Consortium Treatment as Prevention Editorial Writing Group [22]. Regarding the cost effectiveness of treatment and prevention, see Creese, Floyd, Alban, and Guinness [10], Granich et al. [17], Galárraga, Colchero, Wamai, and Bertozzi [14]. For the cost-effectiveness of prevention, see Goldie et al. [15], Cohen, Shin-Yi, and Farley [9], Walker [37], Hogan, Baltussen, Hayashi, Lauer, and Salomon [23],. Fitzpatrick, Singer, Hotez, and Galvani [12] recommend a Congressional cost-effectiveness committee to reveal underinvestment in public health compared with other sectors, and advance societal welfare and.

Section 2 provides the methods. Section 3 presents the theoretical results. Section 4 presents the empirical results. Section 5 recommends and exemplifies a procedure for estimating the model parameters. Section 6 discusses scope, limitations of the study, and future research. Section 7 concludes.

Methods

Nomenclature

Parameters

N Number of persons

G Number of persons choosing safe behavior

L Number of persons choosing risky behavior while not contracting the disease

Mj Number of persons not buying drug j, j = 1,2, with or without drug production by pharmaceutical company

m1 Number of persons buying drug 1

m12 Number of persons buying both drugs 1 and 2

Cj Drug j purchasing cost for for person i, j = 1,2; i = 1,…,N

cj Drug j production cost for the pharmaceutical company destined for person i, j = 1,2; i = 1,…,N

kj Exponential parameter scaling drug j production cost, j = 1,2

dj Drug j development cost, j = 1,2

Ei Person i’s utility of risky behavior, i = 1,…,N

Hi Person i’s utility of safe behavior, Hi < Ei, i = 1,…,N

Ri Person i’s utility when recovering from disease, Ri < Hi, i = 1,…,N

Di Person i’s utility of death, Di < Ri, i = 1,…,N

Strategic choices by person i, i = 1,…,N

Choice between risky behavior and safe behavior in period 1

Choice whether to buy drug 1 or not buy drug 1 in period 4

Choice whether to buy drug 2 or not buy drug 2 in period 7

Strategic choices by pharmaceutical company

Choice whether to develop drug 1 at cost d1 in period 3

Choice whether to develop drug 2 at cost d2 in period 6

Strategic choices by donor

X1 Subsidy fraction of drug 1 development cost d1 in period 3

S1 Subsidy fraction of drug 1 purchasing cost C1 for person i in period 4

X2 Subsidy fraction of drug 2 development cost d2 in period 6

S2 Subsidy fraction of drug 2 purchasing cost C2 for person i in period 7

Strategic choices by Nature

q Disease contraction probability in period 2

x Disease recovery probability without drug 1 in periods 4 and/or 5

r Virus mutation probability in period 5

w Disease recovery probability with drug 1 in period 6

v Disease recovery probability without drug 2 in periods 7 and/or 8

s Disease recovery probability with drug 2 in period 8

Dependent variables

p Fraction of the N persons choosing risky behavior

Ui Person i’s expected utility, i = 1,…,N

u Pharmaceutical company’s expected profit

V Donor’s expected utility

The model

We consider a population of N persons and the complete information eight-period game in Fig. 1 with four players and 13 choice (decision) nodes. The eight periods have been designed to reflect the natural flow of strategic choices by the players. The game naturally starts in period 1 with person i choosing risky or safe behavior. Also naturally, in period 2 Nature chooses whether risky behavior causes disease contraction. Intuitively, with the presence of disease contraction, in period 3 the pharmaceutical company needs to determine whether to develop drug 1. Consequently, if drug 1 is developed, in period 4 person i and the donor need to determine whether to buy and subsidize drug 1. Given the presence of drug 1 in some of the N persons, the natural next step, by Nature in period 5, is whether the virus mutates. If the virus mutates, again the pharmaceutical company needs to make a strategic choice, in period 6, i.e. whether to develop drug 2, since drug 1 is no longer operational after the mutation. If drug 2 is developed in period 6, that naturally has similar consequences as after drug 1 was developed in period 3. That is, in period 7 person i and the donor determine whether to buy and subsidize drug 2. Finally, in period 8 Nature chooses whether person i recovers or dies.

Fig. 1
figure 1

Eight-period game for person i, the pharmaceutical company, the donor, and Nature

Person i has three choice nodes. The two last of these nodes are influenced by the donor (which may consist of multiple donors considered as one collective unit) subsidizing the costs C1 and C2 of drugs 1 and 2 with a fraction Sj for drug j, 0 ≤ Sj ≤ 1, j = 1,2, so that person i pays the remaining fraction 1-Sj. The pharmaceutical company has two choice nodes, influenced by the donor subsidizing the costs d1 and d2 of the development of drugs 1 and 2 with a fraction Xj for drug j, 0 ≤ Xj ≤ 1, j = 1,2, so that the pharmaceutical company pays the remaining fraction 1-Xj. Nature has eight choice nodes and six strategic choices. To ensure tractability all the N persons start the game at the same time and proceed through the eight periods at the same pace. Each person i prefers safe versus risky behavior differently, and assigns different utilities to remaining healthy without or with excitement, to death, and to recovery. The game may end after each period. The game generally ends in different periods for each person i depending on the different strategic choices.

Person i decides in period 1 whether to engage in risky or safe behavior. Risky behavior gives positive utility Ei if not contracting the disease. Safe behavior gives positive utility Hi < Ei which means remaining healthy. A fraction p and hence pN persons choose risky behavior, where p follows from which of the N persons choose risky behavior. Nature chooses in period 2 that risky behavior causes disease contraction with probability q. Thus pqN persons contract the disease. The pharmaceutical company chooses in period 3 either to develop drug 1 at cost d1 subsidized with a fraction X1, or to develop no drug at no cost. With no drug, Nature chooses in period 4 recovery with probability x and positive utility Ri < Hi for person i, or death with probability 1-x and negative utility Di < Ri for person i, and the game ends. If drug 1 is developed, person i chooses in period 4 either not to buy it (causing Nature to choose recovery or death with the same probabilities x and 1-x as if the drug were not developed), or to buy it at cost C1 subsidized by donors with a fraction S1. If drug 1 is bought, in period 5 the virus is contained with probability 1-r (and Nature chooses recovery vs death in period 6) or the virus mutates with probability r. In the latter event the pharmaceutical company chooses in period 6 either to develop drug 2 at cost d2 subsidized with a fraction X2, or to develop no drug at no cost. With no drug, Nature chooses in period 7 recovery or death and the game ends. If drug 2 is developed, person i chooses in period 7 either not to buy it (causing Nature to choose recovery or death in period 8), or to buy it at cost C2 subsidized by donors with a fraction S2. If drug 2 is bought, in the final period 8 Nature chooses recovery vs death with probabilities s and 1-s respectively.

Summing up, person i has three strategic choice variables. It chooses risky or safe behavior in period 1, chooses whether or not to buy drug 1 in period 4 (if the pharmaceutical company has developed it in period 3), and chooses whether or not to buy drug 2 in period 7 (if the pharmaceutical company has developed it in period 6). The pharmaceutical company has two strategic choice variables, i.e. whether or not to develop drug 1 in period 3, and whether or not to develop drug 2 in period 6. The donor has four strategic choice variables. It chooses the subsidy fraction X1 to pay for drug 1 development in period 3, the subsidy fraction S1 to pay for each person i’s drug 1 purchase in period 4, the subsidy fraction X2 to pay for drug 2 development in period 6, and the subsidy fraction S2 to pay for each person i’s drug 2 purchase in period 7. Nature has six strategic choice variables in eight choice nodes. It chooses the disease contraction probability q in period 2, the recovery probability x in period 4 if drug 1 is not developed, the same recovery probability x in period 5 if drug 1 is developed but not bought (and thus not applied), the virus mutation probability r in period 5, the recovery probability w in period 6 if drug 1 is bought (and applied) and the virus is contained, the recovery probability v in period 7 if drug 2 is not developed, the same recovery probability v in period 8 if drug 2 is developed but not bought (and thus not applied), and the recovery probability s in period 8 if drug 2 is bought (and applied).

Individual persons’ behavior, benefits, and costs

Figure 1 has seven outcomes when not counting Nature’s probabilistic choice of recovery or death. Counting these seven outcomes from the root in the game tree and outwards through the branches, and listing them from condition 1 through condition 7, person i’s expected utility is

$$ {U}_i=\left\{\begin{array}{c}{H}_i\kern0.5em if\kern0.5em safe\kern0.5em behavior\kern27.5em \\ {}{E}_i\kern0.5em if\kern0.5em risky\kern0.5em behavior\kern0.5em and\kern0.5em no\kern0.5em disease\kern0.5em contraction\kern17em \\ {}\left(1-x\right){D}_i+{xR}_i\kern0.5em if\kern0.5em risky\kern0.5em behavior\& disease\kern0.5em contraction\& no\kern0.5em drug\kern0.5em 1\kern0.5em development\kern3.5em \\ {}\begin{array}{l}\left(1-x\right){D}_i+{xR}_i\kern0.5em if\kern0.5em risky\kern0.5em behavior\& disease\kern0.5em contraction\& drug\kern0.5em 1\kern0.5em development\kern0.5em only\kern3em \\ {}\kern1em \& no t\kern0.5em buy\kern0.5em drug\kern0.5em 1\end{array}\\ {}\begin{array}{l}\left(1-r\right)\left[\left(1-w\right){D}_i+{wR}_i\right]+r\left[\left(1-v\right){D}_i+{vR}_i\right]-\left(1-{S}_1\right){C}_1\kern0.5em if\kern0.5em risky\kern0.5em behavior\& disease\kern3em \\ {}\kern1em contraction\& drug\kern0.5em 1\kern0.5em development\kern0.5em only\& buy\kern0.5em drug\kern0.5em 1\kern0.5em only\end{array}\\ {}\begin{array}{l}\left(1-v\right){D}_i+{vR}_i-\left(1-{S}_1\right){C}_1\kern0.5em if\kern0.5em risky\kern0.5em behavior\& disease\kern0.5em contraction\& drug\kern0.5em 1\kern0.5em development\\ {}\& buy\kern0.5em drug\kern0.5em 1\kern0.5em \& virus\kern0.5em mutation\& no t\kern0.5em buy\kern0.5em drug\kern0.5em 2\end{array}\\ {}\begin{array}{l}\left(1-s\right){D}_i+{sR}_i-\left(1-{S}_1\right){C}_1-\left(1-{S}_2\right){C}_2\kern0.5em if\kern0.5em risky\kern0.5em behavior\& disease\kern0.5em contraction\& drug\kern0.5em 1\kern1em \\ {}\kern1em development\& buy\kern0.5em drug\kern0.5em 1\kern0.5em \& virus\kern0.5em mutation\& drug\kern0.5em 2\kern0.5em development\& buy\kern0.5em drug\kern0.5em 2\end{array}\end{array}\right. $$
(1)

Equation (1) contains four parameters Hi, Ei, Di, Ri which differ for each person i, i = 1,…,N, two strategic choice variables (which are parametric in the analysis) S1 and S2 chosen by the donor which are equivalent for the N persons, five strategic choice variables (drawn by a random generator) x,r,w,v,s chosen by Nature, and which also are equivalent for the N persons, and the N persons’ drug purchasing costs C1 and C2. Nature’s strategic choice q of the disease contraction probability in period 2 is implicitly present in (1) since it impacts which of the seven conditions emerges. Which of the seven conditions in (1) emerges depends on the pharmaceutical company’s two strategic choices of whether to develop drug 1 in period 3 and develop drug 2 in period 6. Which of the seven conditions in (1) emerges also depends on person i’s three strategic choices, i.e. whether to choose risky or safe behavior in period 1, whether or not to buy drug 1 in period 4 (if available), and whether or not to buy drug 2 in period 7 (if available). Equation (1) may be defined as a distribution function in the sense that Nature’s five strategic choice variables x,r,w,v,s, drawn by a random generator, causes distribution across the outcomes if drawing from the random generator is done repeatedly. All parameters are common knowledge for all the players.

Condition 1 in (1) is valid for a risk averse person i which assigns high utility Hi to safe behavior and low expected utility to the outcomes of risky behavior when assessing the probabilities, drug production and costs. Condition 2 is valid when Nature chooses no disease contraction, that is q = 0, which gives utility Ei > Hi. Conditions 3 and 4 in (1) are equivalent since if person i does not buy drug 1, then it is irrelevant whether drug 1 is developed or not. Condition 5 states that person i buys drug 1 at cost (1-S1)C1 after which the virus is contained with probability 1-r and mutates with probability r. Condition 6 states that the virus mutates which is a precondition for drug 2 development, and that person i does not buy drug 2. Outcome 6 appears twice in Fig. 1 since the pharmaceutical company may or may not develop drug 2. The final condition 7 states that drug 2 is developed and that person i buys it at cost (1-S2)C2.

Overall, with no drug development, only the first three outcomes in (1) are possible. The third outcome gives death with probability 1-x and recovery with probability x. Hence all four utilities Hi,Ei,Di,Ri are possible. If the pharmaceutical company develops drug 1 but not drug 2, the first five outcomes are possible. If the pharmaceutical company develops both drugs 1 and 2, all the seven outcomes are possible. The N persons have different Hi,Ei,Di,Ri, and thus distribute themselves across the three or five or seven outcomes, depending on no drug development, development of drug 1 but not drug 2, and development of both drugs, respectively.

Pharmaceutical company’s behavior, benefits, and costs

The expected profit of the pharmaceutical company depends on the numbers of persons buying drugs 1 and 2, the drug prices, and the costs of drug development. We assume that m1 persons buy drug 1 (and may or may not buy drug 2) which allows outcomes 5–7, and that a weakly smaller number m12, m12 ≤ m1 persons buy both drugs 1 and 2, which allows only outcome 7. This assumption is in accordance with Fig. 1 where persons are not allowed to enter the game in later periods. Hence m1-m12 persons buy only drug 1 which allows outcome 5. Furthermore, assuming that person i has bought drug 1, in order to buy drug 2 the virus has to mutate, and the pharmaceutical company must develop drug 2. The pharmaceutical company’s expected profit is

$$ u=\left\{\begin{array}{l}0\kern0.5em if\kern0.5em no\kern0.5em drug\kern0.5em development\\ {}{m}_1{C}_1-{\left({m}_1{c}_1\right)}^{k_1}-\left(1-{X}_1\right){d}_1\kern0.5em if\kern0.5em only\kern0.5em drug\kern0.5em 1\kern0.5em development\\ {}{m}_1{C}_1+{m}_{12}{C}_2-{\left({m}_1{c}_1\right)}^{k_1}-{\left({m}_{12}{c}_2\right)}^{k_2}-\left(1-{X}_1\right){d}_1-\left(1-{X}_2\right){d}_2\\ {} if\kern0.5em r=1\kern0.5em \&\kern0.5em drug\kern0.5em 1\kern0.5em \&\kern0.5em drug\kern0.5em 2\kern0.5em development\end{array}\right. $$
(2)

where kj scales the production cost for drug j, and cj is the drug production cost for drug j, j = 1,2, for the pharmaceutical company in the amount required for person i, i = 1,…,N. Equation (2) contains two strategic choice variables (which are parametric) X1 and X2 chosen by the donor, one strategic choice variable (drawn by a random generator) r chosen by Nature, and the nine parameters m1,c1,k1,d1,m12,k2,d2,C1,C2. Which of the four conditions in (2) emerges depends on the pharmaceutical company’s two strategic choices of whether to develop drug 1 in period 3 and develop drug 2 in period 6, and depends on the strategic choices by the N persons, the donor, and Nature.

When kj = 1, production cost is linear. When 0 < kj < 1, production cost is concave (economy of scale). When kj > 1, production cost is convex (diseconomy of scale). Condition 1 in (2) corresponds to m1 = m12 = 0 where the N persons distribute themselves across outcomes 1–3, condition 2 corresponds to m1 ≥ 0 = m12 where the N persons distribute themselves across outcomes 1–5, and condition 3 presumes virus mutation r = 1 and corresponds to m1 > 0 and m12 ≥ 0 where the N persons distribute themselves across all seven outcomes.

Although person i has three choice nodes and the pharmaceutical company has two choice nodes, four of these five choice nodes are not reached if all N persons choose safe behavior (outcome 1), or if those that choose risky behavior do not contract the disease (outcome 2). For the pharmaceutical company to develop drug 1 in its first node, at least one person must contract the disease and then that person can choose whether or not to buy drug 1. For the pharmaceutical company to develop drug 2 in its second node, the virus must mutate and then persons can choose whether or not to buy drug 2.

Table 1 lists the seven outcomes in the first row, and the number of persons choosing each outcome in row 2, where G is the number of persons choosing safe behavior and L (for lucky) is the number of persons choosing risky behavior while not contracting the disease. We define Mj as the number of persons not buying drug j despite drug j being produced by the pharmaceutical company, j = 1,2. With these definitions, N-G-L-M1-m1 is the unfortunate number of persons with outcome 3 contracting the disease while no drugs are available. Row 3 lists person i’s strategy. Of interest to the pharmaceutical company are row 4 showing the number m1 of persons buying drug 1 and row 5 showing the number m12 of persons buying both drugs 1 and 2. Drug 2 is developed only if the virus mutates. Row 6 shows that the pharmaceutical company earns zero or negative expected profit for outcomes 1–4, and may earn positive expected profit for outcomes 5–7. The bottom row 7 shows the pharmaceutical company’s drug development strategies.

Table 1 Outcomes, number of persons choosing the various strategies, and the pharmaceutical company’s drug development strategies

In summary, the pharmaceutical company does not develop drugs in outcomes 1–3, where expected profits are zero. The pharmaceutical company does develop drug 1 in outcomes 4 and 5, and subsequently develops drug 2 in outcomes 6 and 7.

Donor’s behavior, benefits, and costs

We assume that the donor’s benefit is the sum of the N persons’ benefits Hi,Ei,Di,Ri accounting for the probabilities q,r,s,v,w,x, strategies, and numbers of persons choosing the seven outcomes. The donor subsidizes the development cost of drug j with Xjdj, where Xj is the donor subsidy fraction, j = 1,2. The donor subsidizes the drug purchasing cost of drug j for person i with SjCj, where Sj is the donor subsidy fraction, j = 1,2; i = 1,…,N. Since m1 persons purchase drug 1, the donor subsidizes drug 1 with m1S1C1. Since m12 persons purchase drug 2, the donor subsidizes drug 2 with m2S2C2. The subsidy fractions Sj and Xj are assumed to be parametric and thus the strategic choices of the donor are not considered. For the donor’s expected utility we get the same three conditions as for the pharmaceutical company’s expected profit in (2), i.e.

$$ V=\left\{\begin{array}{c}\sum \limits_{i=1}^G{H}_i+\sum \limits_{i=G+1}^{G+L}{E}_i+\sum \limits_{i=G+L+1}^{N-{M}_1-{m}_1}\left[\left(1-x\right){D}_i+{xR}_i\right]\kern0.5em and\kern0.5em {M}_1={m}_1=0\kern0.5em if\kern0.5em no\kern0.5em drug\kern0.5em development\\ {}\begin{array}{l}\sum \limits_{i=1}^G{H}_i+\sum \limits_{i=G+1}^{G+L}{E}_i+\sum \limits_{i=G+L+1}^{N-{M}_1-{m}_1}\left[\left(1-x\right){D}_i+{xR}_i\right]+\sum \limits_{i=N-{M}_1-{m}_1+1}^{N-{m}_1}\left[\left(1-x\right){D}_i+{xR}_i\right]\kern4.5em \\ {}\kern1em +\sum \limits_{i=N-{m}_1+1}^{N-{M}_2-{m}_{12}}\left(\left(1-r\right)\left[\left(1-w\right){D}_i+{wR}_i\right]+r\left[\left(1-v\right){D}_i+{vR}_i\right]-{S}_1{C}_1\right)\\ {}\kern1em -{X}_1{d}_1\kern0.5em and\kern0.5em {M}_2={m}_{12}=0\kern0.5em if\kern0.5em only\kern0.5em drug\kern0.5em 1\kern0.5em development\end{array}\\ {}\begin{array}{l}\sum \limits_{i=1}^G{H}_i+\sum \limits_{i=G+1}^{G+L}{E}_i+\sum \limits_{i=G+L+1}^{N-{M}_1-{m}_1}\left[\left(1-x\right){D}_i+{xR}_i\right]+\sum \limits_{i=N-{M}_1-{m}_1+1}^{N-{m}_1}\left[\left(1-x\right){D}_i+{xR}_i\right]\\ {}\kern1em +\sum \limits_{i=N-{m}_1+1}^{N-{M}_2-{m}_{12}}\left(\left(1-v\right){D}_i+{vR}_i-{S}_1{C}_1\right)+\sum \limits_{i=N-{M}_2-{m}_{12}+1}^{N-{m}_{12}}\left(\left(1-v\right){D}_i+{vR}_i-{S}_1{C}_1\right)\kern3em \\ {}\kern1em +\sum \limits_{i=N-{m}_{12}+1}^N\left(\left(1-s\right){D}_i+{sR}_i-{S}_1{C}_1-{S}_2{C}_2\right)\kern0.5em -{X}_1{d}_1-{X}_2{d}_2\\ {}\kern1em if\kern0.5em r=1\kern0.5em \&\kern0.5em drug\kern0.5em 1\kern0.5em \&\kern0.5em drug\kern0.5em 2\kern0.5em development\end{array}\end{array}\right. $$
(3)

The first condition in (3) covers outcomes 1–3 with no subsidies. The second condition covers outcomes 1–5 with subsidies S1C1 and X1d1. The third condition covers outcomes 1–7 with subsidies SjCj and Xjdj, j = 1,2. Equation (3) contains four parameters Hi, Ei, Di, Ri which differ for each person i, i = 1,…,N, four strategic choice variables (which are parametric) S1,X1,S2,X2 chosen by the donor which are equivalent for the N persons, five strategic choice variables (drawn by a random generator) x,r,w,v,s chosen by Nature, and the nine parameters G,L,N,M1,m1,M2,m12,C1,C2. Which of the three conditions in (3) emerges depends on whether no drug is developed, only drug 1 is developed, and both drugs 1 and 2 are developed. Healthcare workers are not explicitly present in Fig. 1, but play a role by advising persons on risky versus safe behavior and whether or not to buy the drugs, and advising the pharmaceutical about the attributes of the disease and other factors relevant for drug development.

Theoretical results

We solve the game with backward induction starting with period 8. Nature’s strategies are probabilistic with the probabilities in Fig. 1. Hence we start with period 7 where person i buys drug 2 if the benefits from buying is at least as large as not buying it, that is, if

$$ {\displaystyle \begin{array}{l}\left(1-s\right){D}_i+{sR}_i-\left(1-{S}_1\right){C}_1-\left(1-{S}_2\right){C}_2\ge \left(1-v\right){D}_i+{vR}_i-\left(1-{S}_1\right){C}_1\\ {}\Rightarrow \left(s-v\right)\left({R}_i-{D}_i\right)\ge \left(1-{S}_2\right){C}_2\end{array}} $$
(4)

If (4) is not satisfied for m12 persons, the pharmaceutical company does not develop drug 2. Otherwise in period 6 the pharmaceutical company develops drug 2 if the expected profit from developing drug 2 outweigh those of not developing drug 2, that is, if

$$ {m}_1{C}_1+{m}_{12}{C}_2-{\left({m}_1{c}_1\right)}^{k_1}-{\left({m}_{12}{c}_2\right)}^{k_2}-\left(1-{X}_1\right){d}_1-\left(1-{X}_2\right){d}_2\ge {m}_1{C}_1-{\left({m}_1{c}_1\right)}^{k_1}-\left(1-{X}_1\right){d}_1\Rightarrow {m}_{12}{C}_2-{\left({m}_{12}{c}_2\right)}^{k_2}\ge \left(1-{X}_2\right){d}_2 $$
(5)

In period 4 person i buys drug 1 if the benefits of consuming drug 1 outweigh the benefits of not consuming drug 1, that is, if

$$ {\displaystyle \begin{array}{l}\left(1-r\right)\left(\left(1-w\right){D}_i+{wR}_i\right)+r\left[\left(1-v\right){D}_i+{vR}_i\right]-\left(1-{S}_1\right){C}_1\ge \left(1-x\right){D}_i+{xR}_i\\ {}\Rightarrow \left(w-x+r\left(v-w\right)\right)\left({R}_i-{D}_i\right)\ge \left(1-{S}_1\right){C}_1\end{array}} $$
(6)

If (6) is not satisfied for m1 persons, the pharmaceutical company does not develop drug 1. Otherwise in period 3 the pharmaceutical company develops drug 1 if it is profitable to do so, that is, if

$$ {m}_1{C}_1-{\left({m}_1{c}_1\right)}^{k_1}-\left(1-{X}_1\right){d}_1\ge 0\Rightarrow {m}_1{C}_1-{\left({m}_1{c}_1\right)}^{k_1}\ge \left(1-{X}_1\right){d}_1 $$
(7)

In period 1 person i makes the following considerations, given that it does not know whether the virus mutates in period 5. If neither drug 1 nor drug 2 are optimal for it to buy, it chooses risky behavior if

$$ \left(1-q\right){E}_i+q\left(\left(1-x\right){D}_i+{xR}_i\right)\ge {H}_i $$
(8)

If drug 1 is optimal for it to buy whereas drug 2 is not optimal for it to buy, it chooses risky behavior if

$$ \left(1-q\right){E}_i+q\left(\left(1-r\right)\left(\left(1-w\right){D}_i+{wR}_i\right)+r\left[\left(1-v\right){D}_i+{vR}_i\right]-\left(1-{S}_1\right){C}_1\right)\ge {H}_i $$
(9)

If both drugs 1 and 2 are optimal for it to buy, it chooses risky behavior if

$$ \left(1-q\right){E}_i+q\left(\left(1-r\right)\left(\left(1-w\right){D}_i+{wR}_i\right)+r\left[\left(1-s\right){D}_i+{sR}_i-\left(1-{S}_2\right){C}_2\right]-\left(1-{S}_1\right){C}_1\right)\ge {H}_i $$
(10)

With no disease contraction, inserting q = 0 into (8), (9), or (10) gives

$$ {E}_i\ge {H}_i $$
(11)

which is satisfied by assumption guaranteeing risky behavior. Outcome 1 means that person i prefers safe behavior, which occurs if neither (8) nor (9) nor (10) are satisfied. Table 2 lists the seven outcomes O in the left column, lists the equations that apply in the middle column, and lists the conditions in the right column.

Table 2 The seven outcomes O, the equations that apply, and an example (section 5, i.e. the section labelled "Estimating and exemplifying the model parameters"). Yes and No in the rightmost column specify whether each example inequality matches whether the inequality in the corresponding equation should be satisfied

Empirical results

Between 2000 and 2007, the median price for first-line therapy in developing countries fell from $10,000 to below $100 per patient per year, which approximately is also the price today [30]. In 2017 the Clinton Health Access Initiative [7] and partners announced an agreement to produce a single HIV pill HIV to public sector purchasers in low- and middle-income countries to around $75 per person per year. Pillai et al. [33] find that the mean yearly cost of pre-ART HIV care is $158.52.

Many “People Living With HIV/AIDS” require second-line treatment due to resistance to first-line drug treatment or not tolerating first-line drugs. The World Health Organization [40] announces in 2007 that the median price for the most frequently used first- and second-line HAART (abacavir + didanosine + lopinavir/ritonavir) treatment for low-income countries was $1214. The World Health Organization [40] announces that for 2008, in middle-income countries, the price for second-line therapy was $3306 per year, as compared to $91 for first-line therapy. Médecins Sans Frontières [30] announces $87 as the cheapest first-line price and $749 (tenofovir + emtricitabine + lopinavir/ritonavir) as the cheapest second-line price.

Companies such as GlaxoSmithKline, Merck, Bristol Myers Squibb, offering ARV, adjust prices depending on the countries’ socioeconomic status, applying their own categorizations [30] or categorizations developed by the World Bank [39]. Prices are also determined by acquisition processes and third party negotiation [7]. Also, as expected, The World Health Organization [40] announces that large-scale production causes lower process.

During 2017–2021 DiMasi et al. [11] estimate $2.6 billion in HIV drug R&D costs, and West and Schneider [38] estimate $2.2 billion in revenues for South Africa, Nigeria, Tanzania, Ethiopia, the Democratic Republic of the Congo, and Egypt; $4.3 billion in revenues for the Middle East and North Africa and Sub-Saharan Africa; and $6.1 billion in worldwide revenues.

Table 3 shows in row 1 the HIV resource availability in US$ billion for low- and middle-income countries in 2018, and as percentages in row 2.

Table 3 Total HIV resource availability in US$ billion for low- and middle-income countries in 2018, and as percentages of the sum

Estimating and exemplifying the model parameters

Let us estimate the model’s parameters, including the donor’s strategic choices X1,S1,X2,S2 and Nature’s strategic choices q,x,r,w,v,s, see the nomenclature in the beginning of the Methods section. The drug purchasing cost Cj for drug j, j = 1,2, for person i, i = 1,…,N, is estimated as Cj = $100 per year, which falls within $75–$158.52 per year estimated in the previous section. The drug production cost cj for drug j, j = 1,2, for the pharmaceutical company destined for person i, i = 1,…,N, is estimated as $80 per person per year, which is 20% below Cj = $100. The exponential parameter kj scaling the drug production cost for drug j, j = 1,2, is estimated as kj = 0.5, which assumes sufficiently large markets and efficient production (since kj < 1, concave production, economy of scale). (That contrasts with kj = 1 which would mean linear production and kj > 1 which would mean convex production and diseconomy of scale.) The drug development cost dj for drug j, j = 1,2, is in the previous section estimated to be dj = $2.6 billion, where we due to simplicity assume equivalent costs of developing the two drugs.

Using Appelbaum’s [2] estimate $6.1–$9.1 million of the value of statistical life, person i’s utility Di of death is estimated as Di = −$7 million. (Such valuations typically depend on how a person strikes a balance between health risks and rewards, or on weighing wages against death risk in the labor market.) Person i’s utility Ei of risky behavior, i = 1,…,N, is estimated as 1/7 of the value of statistical life, i.e. Ei = 1 million. Person i’s utility Hi of safe behavior, Hi < Ei, i = 1,…,N, is estimated as Hi = 0.5Ei = $0.5 million. Person i’s utility Ri when recovering from disease, Di < Ri < Hi, i = 1,…,N, is estimated as Ri = 0.4Hi = $0.2 million.

The subsidy fraction Xj, j = 1,2, of drug development cost d1 in period 3 and d2 in period 6 is estimated intermediately as Xj = 0.5. (Since the pharmaceutical company is usually profit-seeking, the subsidy fraction Xj of the drug development cost is usually below one.) Similarly, the subsidy fraction Sj, j = 1,2, of drug purchasing cost C1 for person i in period 4 and C2 for person i in period 7 is estimated intermediately as Sj = 0.5. (Countries with extensive social welfare programs may choose a higher subsidy fraction Sj.) The estimates of Xj and Sj may be assessed further in view of the percentages in Table 3.

The disease contraction probability q in period 2 is estimated as q = 0.1, influenced by HIV/AIDS data from UNAIDS [36] which show the HIV prevalence fractions among adults aged 15–49. Although these prevalence fractions range from < 0.1 for many countries to 0.273 for Eswatini, q is usually higher than the prevalence. In fact, frequent risky behavior in interaction with persons who have contracted the disease, or in environments with high HIV prevalence, may cause q to be close to one, though with very low HIV prevalence it can be much lower. The disease recovery probability x without drug 1 in periods 4 and/or 5 is estimated as x = 0.1. It can be expected to be low, and close to or equal to zero for serious or deadly diseases. The virus mutation probability r in period 5 is estimated as r = 0.5. The disease recovery probability w with drug 1 in period 6 if the virus is contained is estimated as w = 0.9, thus assuming that drug 1 is useful. The disease recovery probability v without drug 2 in periods 7 and/or 8 is estimated as v = 0.1, assuming that refraining from using drug 2 is risky. The disease recovery probability s in period 8 if drug 2 is bought (and applied) is estimated as s = 0.9, thus assuming that drug 2 is useful.

The inequalities in the rightmost column in Table 2 follow from assuming the parameter values above, assuming that m1 = 20 million persons buy drug 1, and that m12 = 14 million persons buy drug 2. Outcome 1 does not follow since (9) and (10) are satisfied, while (8) is not satisfied, which induces risky behavior. If person i’s utility Hi = $0.5 million of safe behavior increases above Hi = $0.847993 million, then (10) is not satisfied, and person i chooses safe behavior instead. If person i chooses risky behavior, with subsequent disease contraction, outcomes 1 and 2 are impossible, and outcomes 3,4,5,6 or 7 arise instead. Outcome 2 with risky behavior is possible (with probability 1-q) since (8) or (9) or (10) is satisfied, and arises with probability 1-q chosen by Nature of no disease contraction. Outcome 3 does not follow since (4),(5),(6),(7) are satisfied, while (8) is not satisfied, and hence the pharmaceutical company proceeds to develop drug 1. The pharmaceutical company develops drug 1 if at least m1 = 14 million persons buy drug 1. Since m1 = 20 million, drug 1 is developed. Outcome 4 does not follow since (4),(5),(6),(7) are satisfied, while (8) is not satisfied. Hence the pharmaceutical company proceeds to develop drug 1, person i buys it, and the donor subsidizes it. Outcome 5 with death (probability 1-w) or recovery (probability w) is possible since (4), (5), (6), (7), (9) are satisfied, and arises with probability 1-r chosen by Nature of virus containment. Outcome 6 with death (probability 1-v) or recovery (probability v) is possible since (4), (5), (6), (7), (9) are satisfied, and arises with probability r chosen by Nature of virus mutation. Outcome 6 is possible if the pharmaceutical company does not develop drug 2, or the pharmaceutical company develops drug 2 but person i does not buy it. The pharmaceutical company develops drug 2 if at least m12 = 14 million persons buy drug 2, which is satisfied. Outcome 7 is the only row in Table 2 which specifies Yes to all the inequalities. That is, (4), (5), (6), (7), 10) are satisfied. Outcome 7 means that person i chooses risky behavior, contracts the disease, and buys both drugs 1 and 2, which means that the pharmaceutical company develops both drugs. Outcome 7 assumes that Nature chooses disease contraction with probability q and virus mutation with probability r. Outcome 7 means that person i dies with probability 1-s or recovers with probability s. Inserting the parameter values into (1), person i’s expected utility is

$$ {U}_i=\left\{\begin{array}{c}\$0.5\times {10}^6\kern0.5em if\kern0.5em safe\kern0.5em behavior\kern21.5em \\ {}\${10}^6\kern0.5em if\kern0.5em risky\kern0.5em behavior\kern0.5em and\kern0.5em no\kern0.5em disease\kern0.5em contraction\kern12em \\ {}-\$6.28\times {10}^6\kern0.5em if\kern0.5em risky\kern0.5em behavior\& disease\kern0.5em contraction\& no\kern0.5em drug\kern0.5em 1\kern0.5em development\kern1em \\ {}\begin{array}{l}-\$6.28\times {10}^6\kern0.5em if\kern0.5em risky\kern0.5em behavior\& disease\kern0.5em contraction\& drug\kern0.5em 1\kern0.5em development\kern0.5em only\\ {}\kern1em \& no t\kern0.5em buy\kern0.5em drug\kern0.5em 1\end{array}\\ {}\begin{array}{l}-\$3.40\times {10}^6\kern0.5em if\kern0.5em risky\kern0.5em behavior\& disease\kern0.5em contraction\& drug\kern0.5em 1\kern0.5em development\kern0.5em only\\ {}\kern1em \& buy\kern0.5em drug\kern0.5em 1\kern0.5em only\end{array}\\ {}\begin{array}{l}-\$6.28\times {10}^6\kern0.5em if\kern0.5em risky\kern0.5em behavior\& disease\kern0.5em contraction\& drug\kern0.5em 1\kern0.5em development\kern2em \\ {}\kern1.5em \& buy\kern0.5em drug\kern0.5em 1\kern0.5em \& virus\kern0.5em mutation\& no t\kern0.5em buy\kern0.5em drug\kern0.5em 2\end{array}\\ {}\begin{array}{l}-\$5.20\times {10}^5\kern0.5em if\kern0.5em risky\kern0.5em behavior\& disease\kern0.5em contraction\& drug\kern0.5em 1\kern0.5em development\kern2em \\ {}\kern1em \& buy\kern0.5em drug\kern0.5em 1\kern0.5em \& virus\kern0.5em mutation\& drug\kern0.5em 2\kern0.5em development\& buy\kern0.5em drug\kern0.5em 2\end{array}\end{array}\right. $$
(12)

In (12) person i prefers outcome 2 (line 2) if the disease is not contracted. If the disease is contracted after risky behavior, person i prefers outcome 5 if the virus is contained (line 5), or outcome 7 (line 7) if the virus mutates which gives the highest expected utility − 5.2 × 105. Weighing outcome 2 and either outcome 5 or outcome 7 against each other with the given probabilities chosen by Nature, person i chooses risky behavior rather than safe behavior. Consequently, with these parameter values, the availability of both drugs induces risky behavior. Inserting the parameter values into (2), the pharmaceutical company’s expected profit is

$$ u=\left\{\begin{array}{c}0\kern0.5em if\kern0.5em no\kern0.5em drug\kern0.5em development\kern10em \\ {}\$7.00\times {10}^8\kern0.5em if\kern0.5em only\kern0.5em drug\kern0.5em 1\kern0.5em development\kern6.1em \\ {}\$8.00\times {10}^8\kern0.5em if\kern0.5em r=1\kern0.5em \&\kern0.5em drug\kern0.5em 1\kern0.5em \&\kern0.5em drug\kern0.5em 2\kern0.5em development\end{array}\right. $$
(13)

Hence the pharmaceutical company prefers to develop drug 1 if the virus is contained, develop both drugs if the virus mutates. The donor’s expected utility requires specifying the five additional parameters N,G,L,M1,M2. The number N of persons is assumed to be N = 100 million, which is the population one studies, e.g. a country in the data provided by UNAIDS UNAIDS [36], or chosen from a statistics database. The number G of persons choosing safe behavior is estimated to be G = 40 million. The number must evidently be less than N, and may be corroborated e.g. by purchases of protections against sexually transmitted diseases (e.g. condoms), or by other indicators of safe behavior. The number L of persons choosing risky behavior while not contracting the disease is estimated to be L = 30 million. It must evidently be less than N-G = 70 million. The number of m1 of persons buying drug 1 was estimated above to be m1 = 20 million. It must evidently be less than N-G-L = 30 million, since person i will not buy drug 1 without disease contraction. The number M1 of persons not buying drug 1 despite drug production by the pharmaceutical company is estimated to be M1 = 7 million. It must evidently be less than N-G-L-m1 = 10 million. The number of m12 of persons buying drug 2 was estimated above to be m12 = 14 million. It must evidently be less than N-G-L = 30 million, since person i will not buy drug 2 without disease contraction. The number M2 of persons not buying drug 2 despite drug production by the pharmaceutical company is estimated to be M2 = 4 million. It must evidently be less than N-G-L-m12 = 16 million. The above estimates implies that N-G-L-M1-m1 = 3 million persons contract the disease without drugs being available, since the pharmaceutical company does not develop drugs. We assume that all persons are equivalent to person i. Inserting these parameter values into (3), the donor’s expected utility is

$$ V=\left\{\begin{array}{c}-\$1.384\times {10}^{14}\kern0.5em and\kern0.5em {M}_1={m}_1=0\kern0.5em if\kern0.5em no\kern0.5em drug\kern0.5em development\kern2em \\ {}-\$8.080\times {10}^{13}\kern0.5em and\kern0.5em {M}_2={m}_{12}=0\kern0.5em if\kern0.5em only\kern0.5em drug\kern0.5em 1\kern0.5em development\\ {}-\$5.776\times {10}^{13}\kern0.5em if\kern0.5em r=1\kern0.5em \&\kern0.5em drug\kern0.5em 1\kern0.5em \&\kern0.5em drug\kern0.5em 2\kern0.5em development\kern3em \end{array}\right. $$
(14)

Equation (14) implies that the donor prefers the development of both drugs if the virus mutates, which gives the highest expected utility, and prefers that drug 1 is developed if the virus is contained. The lowest expected utility in line 1 in (14), with no drug development, follows from the third sum in (3) which sums the negative expected utility (1 − x)Di + xRi for person i over N-G-L persons, instead of summing over N-M1-m1-G-L persons as in line 2. The fourth sum in line 2 in (3) also sums the negative expected utility (1 − x)Di + xRi for person i, over M1 persons who do not buy drug 1. In contrast, the fifth sum in line 3 in (3) sums the expected utility ((1 − r)[(1 − w)Di + wRi] + r[(1 − v)Di + vRi] − S1C1) for person i, which is higher than (1 − x)Di + xRi since r = 0.5 and 0.1 = v = x ≤ w = 0.9, over m1 persons who buy drug 1. When m1 is sufficiently high, that causes line 2 in (14) to be higher than line 1. That all three lines in (14) are negative may be common for a donor. It may be due to factors not accounted for in this article, e.g. non-monetary rewards (e.g. a reputation for being altruistic), charitable contributions, or aid from governments or public or private enterprises which may seek economic welfare which may follow when the labor force is more healthy.

Discussion

This section discusses the scope and implications of the study, highlights the limitations, and considers future research. The model’s scope involves strategic interaction between N persons choosing risky versus safe behavior, a pharmaceutical company choosing whether or not to develop one or two drugs depending on virus mutation, a donor assumed to be parametric, and Nature. The seven outcomes are that person i chooses safe behavior, chooses risky behavior without disease contraction, contracts the disease without drug 1 availability, contracts the disease with drug 1 availability but without buying drug 1, contracts the disease with drug 1 availability and buying drug 1, not buying drug 2, and buying drug 2. The parameter estimation in the previous section 5 illustrates the realization of the seven outcomes. We chose to illustrate outcome 7 which captures movement through the entire eight-period game in Fig. 1, while also illustrating why outcomes 1–6 do not arise with these parameter values.

As science, society, technology, and economic conditions change, the parameter values may change, which may cause any of the seven outcomes to emerge. For example, drugs may become cheaper or more efficient, viruses may mutate in unknown ways, pharmaceutical companies may become more efficient, donors may subsidize more or less, Nature may choose the probabilities differently, and persons may change balances they strike between risky and safe behavior. Insight into such changes may enable the players themselves, and non-modeled players such as healthcare workers, hospitals, governments, and international organizations to choose better strategies.

Various limitations exist for this study. First, as a useful first step we confine attention to N persons, one pharmaceutical company, one donor, and Nature, which means that we do not model other players in the health system, such as healthcare workers, hospitals, governments, regulators, politicians, and international organizations. Second, although the N persons differ in their utilities Ei of risky behavior, Hi of safe behavior, Ri when recovering from disease, and Di of death, i = 1,…,N, we do not formalize the probability distributions for these utilities, which may change over time. Third, we consider one pharmaceutical company, which abstracts away competition between multiple pharmaceutical companies and market conditions which may impact prices, drug quality, etc. Fourth, we consider one parametric donor instead of multiple donors as strategic players potentially competing or facing a collective action problem. Fifth, we assume that Nature chooses disease contraction, recovery, mutation and death, some of which may be impacted by strategic choices made by non-modeled players.

Some of these limitations can be addressed in various ways in future research. First, research may classify different kinds of people according to age, sex, occupation, ethnicity, race, etc., and model probability distributions of various preferences and beliefs including risky versus safe behavior and how they recover from disease. Second, research may model more than one pharmaceutical company with different economic and scientific capabilities, preferences, and beliefs; may enable strategic choices by multiple donors, may incorporate more choices by Nature, and may model more players. Third, research may model different kinds of recovery from disease, depending on people’s different characteristics, economic capabilities, geographical location, etc. Fourth, research may model how disease contraction, recovery, and death impact and are impacted by drug production, drug quality, drug availability and costs, geographical distribution of drugs, and countries’ GDP, debt, productivity, income earnings, economic growth, societal conditions, and cultural preferences. Fifth, future research may model multiple donors as strategic players competing to donate in multifarious ways, may endogenize Nature’s parametric choices which may be extended beyond those considered in this article, e.g. by considering proliferation of virus mutation potentially spreading out of control. Sixth, the disease contraction probability with and without one or several drugs may be assumed to depend on multiple gradations and classifications of each person’s risky and safe behavior, the characteristics of persons, each person’s earlier medical history including exposure to infectious diseases, the number of persons having previously contracted the disease, and different kinds of matching of infected and non-infected persons. Seventh, various kinds of vaccinations prior to potential disease contraction may be incorporated into an analysis in combination with or matched against various kinds of drugs designed to ensure recovery after disease contraction. Eighth, the disease recovery probability may be endogenized by modeling the biological process by which viruses evolve [31, 34]. Ninth, research may model how people choose various kinds of behaviors, including potential vaccination if available, at different stages of drug development, i.e. at early stages where drugs may have uncertain quality and side effects, versus mature stages where the quality may have been improved and side effects ameliorated or removed. Tenth, research may incorporate different expectations by the players about future disease development, virus mutation, and drug availability. Eleventh, research may model how people may contract the disease at different points in time, and how the various players may make strategic choices at different points in time. Twelfth, research may tailor models to the specifics of various diseases. Thirteenth, future research should compile empirical data on a variety of infectious diseases including HIV/AIDS and Covid-19 to test the model in this article and future models that may be developed.

Conclusion

An eight-period game is developed between N persons and a pharmaceutical company. Each person chooses either risky or safe behavior. Risky behavior may lead to disease, e.g. HIV/AIDS or Covid-19. The pharmaceutical company develops one or two drugs under various conditions. Drug 1 is developed if it is profitable, i.e. if sufficiently many persons contract the disease and choose to buy drug 1. Drug 2 is developed if the virus mutates, and if sufficiently many persons who have contracted the disease choose to buy drug 2. The donor chooses parametrically whether to subsidize the pharmaceutical company’s development of drug 1 and/or drug 2, and whether to subsidize each person’s purchases of drug 1 and/or drug 2. The donor’s choices thus impact both the pharmaceutical company’s choices and each person’s choices. This illustrates the game theoretic nature of the phenomenon. Nature chooses probabilistically whether a person with risky behavior contracts the disease, whether the person recovers without drug 1, whether the virus mutates, whether the person recovers with drug 1, whether the person recovers without drug 2, and whether the person recovers with drug 2.

Each person’s expected utility depends on seven outcomes, i.e. safe behavior, risky behavior without disease contraction, risky behavior with disease contraction and no drug 1 availability, drug 1 availability without buying drug 1, buying drug 1, virus mutation and not buying drug 2, and virus mutation and buying drug 2. The pharmaceutical company’s expected profit depends on three outcomes, i.e. no drug development (outcomes 1–3 for the persons), only drug 1 development (outcomes 4–5 for the persons), and virus mutation and drug 1 and drug 2 development (outcomes 6–7 for the persons). The donor’s expected utility also depends on these three outcomes.

Backward induction is applied to solve the game depending on conditions for the seven outcomes. The parameter values are estimated and exemplified in a procedure which applies HIV/AIDS data for prevalence, deaths, HIV expenditure, treatment costs, R&D costs and revenues, and HIV resource availability, for various countries. The model constitutes a tool or mechanism to comprehend a person’s choices between safe and risky behavior, whether to purchase one or several drugs, whether a pharmaceutical company should develop one or several drugs, whether a donor should subsidize drug development and drug purchases, accounting for how Nature chooses disease contraction, recovery, virus mutation, and death, with and without drugs.

Availability of data and materials

All data has been included in the article.

Notes

  1. https://www.amfar.org/about-hiv-and-aids/facts-and-stats/statistics%2D%2Dworldwide/, retrieved February 20, 2021.

Abbreviations

HIV:

Human immunodeficiency virus infection

AIDS:

Acquired immune deficiency syndrome

R&D:

Research and development

ART:

Antiretroviral therapy

UNAIDS:

The Joint United Nations Programme on HIV/AIDS

HAART:

Highly Active Antiretroviral Therapy (abacavir + didanosine + lopinavir/ritonavir)

References

  1. Alistar SS, Brandeau ML. Decision making for HIV prevention and treatment scale up: bridging the gap between theory and practice. Med Decis Mak. 2012;32(1):105–17. https://doi.org/10.1177/0272989x10391808.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. Appelbaum, B. (2011). As U.S. agencies put more value on a life, businesses fret. The New York Times. Retrieved from http://www.nytimes.com/2011/02/17/business/economy/17regulation.html

    Google Scholar 

  3. Bärnighausen T, Salomon JA, Sangrujee N. HIV treatment as prevention: issues in economic evaluation. PLoS Med. 2012. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pmed.1001263.

  4. Bertozzi S, Padian NS, Wegbreit J, DeMaria LM, Feldman B, Gayle H, et al. HIV/AIDS prevention and treatment. Dis Control Priorities Dev Countries. 2006;2:331–70.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Boily M-C, Mâsse B, Alsallaq R, Padian NS, Eaton JW, Vesga JF, et al. HIV treatment as prevention: considerations in the design, conduct, and analysis of cluster randomized controlled trials of combination HIV prevention. PLoS Med. 2012;9(7):e1001250. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pmed.1001250.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  6. Canning D. The economics of HIV/AIDS in low-income countries: the Case for prevention. J Econ Perspect. 2006;20(3):121–42. https://doi.org/10.1257/jep.20.3.121.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  7. Clinton Health Access Initiative. (2018). Annual Report 2018. Retrieved from http://clintonhealthaccess.org/wp-content/uploads/2019/12/CHAI-ANNUAL-REPORT.pdf

    Google Scholar 

  8. Coates TJ, Richter L, Caceres C. Behavioural strategies to reduce HIV transmission: how to make them work better. Lancet. 2008;372(9639):669–84. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0140-6736(08)60886-7.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  9. Cohen D, Shin-Yi W, Farley T. Cost-effective allocation of government funds to prevent HIV infection. Health Aff. 2005;24(4):915–26. https://doi.org/10.1377/hlthaff.24.4.915.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Creese A, Floyd K, Alban A, Guinness L. Cost-effectiveness of HIV/AIDS interventions in Africa: a systematic review of the evidence. Lancet. 2002;359(9318):1635–42. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0140-6736(02)08595-1.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  11. DiMasi JA, Grabowski HG, Hansen RW. Innovation in the pharmaceutical industry: new estimates of R&D costs. J Health Econ. 2016;47:20–33. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jhealeco.2016.01.012.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  12. Fitzpatrick MC, Singer BH, Hotez PJ, Galvani AP. Saving lives efficiently across sectors: the need for a congressional cost-effectiveness committee. Lancet. 2017;390(10110):2410–2. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0140-6736(17)31440-X.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  13. Forsythe SS, McGreevey W, Whiteside A, Shah M, Cohen J, Hecht R, et al. Twenty years of antiretroviral therapy for people living with HIV: global costs, health achievements, economic benefits. Health Aff. 2019;38(7):1163–72. https://doi.org/10.1377/hlthaff.2018.05391.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Galárraga O, Colchero MA, Wamai RG, Bertozzi SM. HIV prevention cost-effectiveness: a systematic review. BMC Public Health. 2009;9(Suppl 1):S5. https://doi.org/10.1186/1471-2458-9-S1-S5.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  15. Goldie SJ, Yazdanpanah Y, Losina E, Weinstein MC, Anglaret X, Walensky RP, et al. Cost-effectiveness of HIV treatment in resource-poor settings — the Case of Côte d'Ivoire. N Engl J Med. 2006;355(11):1141–53. https://doi.org/10.1056/NEJMsa060247.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  16. Gonsalves G. HIV/AIDS prevention and treatment. Lancet. 2002;360(9326):87. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0140-6736(02)09344-3.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  17. Granich R, Kahn JG, Bennett R, Holmes CB, Garg N, Serenata C, et al. Expanding ART for treatment and prevention of HIV in South Africa: estimated cost and cost-effectiveness 2011-2050 (expanding ART for HIV treatment and prevention). PLoS One. 2012;7(2):e30216. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0030216.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  18. Hausken K, Ncube M. Policy makers, the international community and the population in the prevention and treatment of diseases: Case study on HIV/AIDS. Heal Econ Rev. 2017;7(1):1–12. https://doi.org/10.1186/s13561-016-0139-x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. Hausken K, Ncube M. Policy makers, the international community and people living with HIV/AIDS: the need for new commitment mechanisms. Int J Public Policy. 2018;14(3/4):275–301. https://doi.org/10.1504/IJPP.2018.091958.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Hausken K, Ncube M. Game theoretic analysis of persons, the pharmaceutical industry, and donors in disease contraction and recovery. Humanit Soc Sci Commun. 2020;7(150):1–17. https://doi.org/10.1057/s41599-020-00626-4.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Hecht R, Stover J, Bollinger L, Muhib F, Case K, de Ferranti D. Financing of HIV/AIDS programme scale-up in low-income and middle-income countries, 2009–31. Lancet. 2010;376(9748):1254–60. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0140-6736(10)61255-X.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  22. HIV Modelling Consortium Treatment as Prevention Editorial Writing Group. HIV treatment as prevention: models, data, and questions—towards evidence-based decision-making. PLoS Med. 2012;9(7):e1001259. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pmed.1001259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Hogan DR, Baltussen R, Hayashi C, Lauer JA, Salomon JA. Cost effectiveness analysis of strategies to combat HIV/AIDS in developing countries. BMJ. 2005;331(7530):1431–7. https://doi.org/10.1136/bmj.38643.368692.68.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  24. Izazola-Licea JA, Wiegelmann J, Arán C, Guthrie T, De Lay P, Avila-Figueroa C. Financing the response to HIV in low-income and middle-income countries. JAIDS J Acquir Immune Defic Syndr. 2009;52(Supplement 2):S119–26. https://doi.org/10.1097/QAI.0b013e3181baeeda.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  25. Kremer M, Glennerster R. Strong medicine : creating incentives for pharmaceutical research on neglected diseases. Princeton: Princeton University Press; 2004.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Kremer M, Snyder CM. Why are drugs more profitable than vaccines? (Vol. 9833). Cambridge, Mass: National Bureau of Economic Research; 2003.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  27. Kremer M, Snyder CM. Preventatives versus treatments. Department of Economics: Harvard University, USA; 2015.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Kumaranayake L, Watts C, Dixon S, Mc Donald S, Roberts J. Resource allocation and priority setting of HIV/AIDS interventions: addressing the generalized epidemic in sub-Saharan Africa. J Int Dev. 2001;13(4):451–66. https://doi.org/10.1002/jid.797.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  29. Mamani H, Chick SE, Simchi-Levi D. A game-theoretic model of international influenza vaccination coordination. Manag Sci. 2013;59(7):1650–70. https://doi.org/10.1287/mnsc.1120.1661.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Médecins Sans Frontières. (2020). Access to Medicines: Medicines Shouldn't Be a Luxury. Retrieved from https://www.msf.org/access-medicines-depth

    Google Scholar 

  31. Moxnes JF, Hausken K. Mathematical modelling of acute virus influenza a infections. Math Comput Model Dyn Syst. 2012;18(5):521–38. https://doi.org/10.1080/13873954.2012.669387.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. Paltiel AD, Stinnett AA. Resource allocation and the funding of HIV prevention. In: Handbook of economic evaluation of HIV prevention programs. Springer; 1998. p. 135–52.

  33. Pillai N, Foster N, Hanifa Y, Ndlovu N, Fielding K, Churchyard G, et al. Patient costs incurred by people living with HIV/AIDS prior to ART initiation in primary healthcare facilities in Gauteng, South Africa. PLoS One. 2019;14(2):e0210622. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0210622.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  34. Sun J, He W-T, Wang L, Lai A, Ji X, Zhai X, et al. COVID-19: epidemiology, evolution, and cross-disciplinary perspectives. Trends Mol Med. 2020;26(5):483–95. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.molmed.2020.02.008.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  35. Thomas P. Big shot: passion, politics, and the struggle for an AIDS vaccine. New York: Public Affairs; 2001.

    Google Scholar 

  36. UNAIDS. (2019). AIDSinfo. Retrieved from http://aidsinfo.unaids.org/

    Google Scholar 

  37. Walker D. Cost and cost-effectiveness of HIV/AIDS prevention strategies in developing countries: is there an evidence base? Health Policy Plan. 2003;18(1):4–17. https://doi.org/10.1093/heapol/18.1.4.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  38. West, D. M., & Schneider, J. (2018). Measuring revenue streams and profitability for HIV drugs. Retrieved from https://www.brookings.edu/research/measuring-revenue-streams-and-profitability-for-hiv-drugs/

    Google Scholar 

  39. World Bank. (2019). New country classifications by income level: 2019–2020. Retrieved from http://blogs.worldbank.org/opendata/new-country-classifications-income-level-2019-2020

    Google Scholar 

  40. World Health Organization. (2020). Global price reporting mechanism for HIV, tuberculosis and malaria. Retrieved from https://www.who.int/hiv/amds/gprm/en/

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

No acknowledgements exist so far.

Funding

No funding was received.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

All authors contributed to the article. The author(s) read and approved the final manuscript.

Authors’ information

Authors’ information has been included in the article.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kjell Hausken.

Ethics declarations

Ethics approval and consent to participate

The article does not include participants and thus ethics approval is not required.

Consent for publication

Both authors consented to publishing the article.

Competing interests

No competing interests exist.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Open Access This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence, and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this article are included in the article's Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If material is not included in the article's Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/. The Creative Commons Public Domain Dedication waiver (http://creativecommons.org/publicdomain/zero/1.0/) applies to the data made available in this article, unless otherwise stated in a credit line to the data.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Hausken, K., Ncube, M. Decisions of persons, the pharmaceutical industry, and donors in disease contraction and recovery assuming virus mutation. Health Econ Rev 11, 26 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1186/s13561-021-00320-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1186/s13561-021-00320-4

Keywords