Skip to main content
Log in

The fruitful death of modal collapse arguments

  • Article
  • Published:
International Journal for Philosophy of Religion Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Modal collapse arguments are all the rage in certain philosophical circles as of late. The arguments purport to show that classical theism entails the absurdly fatalistic conclusion that everything exists necessarily. My first aim in this paper is bold: to put an end to action-based modal collapse arguments against classical theism. To accomplish this, I first articulate the ‘Simple Modal Collapse Argument’ and then characterize and defend Tomaszewski’s criticism thereof. Second, I critically examine Mullins’ new modal collapse argument formulated in response to the aforementioned criticism. I argue that Mullins’ new argument does not succeed. Third, I critically examine a powers-based modal collapse argument against classical theism that has received much less attention in the literature. Fourth, I show why God’s being purely actual, as well God’s being identical to each of God’s acts, simply cannot entail modal collapse given indeterministic causation. This, I take it, signals the death of modal collapse arguments. But not all hope is lost for proponents of modal collapse arguments—for the death is a fruitful one insofar as it paves the way for new inquiry into at least two new potential problems for classical theism. Showing this is my paper’s second aim.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Hughes (2018, p. 2), Bergmann and Brower (2006, pp. 359–360), Dolezal (2017, pp. 41–42), Duby (2016, p. 2), Mullins (2021).

  2. Two notes. First, a positive ontological item is anything that exists (has being or reality). Second, what intrinsicality consists in is a matter of debate. We can make do with an intuitive understanding thereof, since nothing in my paper hangs on a precise and formalized account. I follow David Lewis’s classic articulation: “We distinguish intrinsic properties, which things have in virtue of the way they themselves are, from extrinsic properties, which they have in virtue of their relations or lack of relations to other things” (Lewis, 1986, p. 61). Intrinsic properties (else: predicates), then, characterize something as it is in itself, without reference to things wholly apart from or outside of or disjoint from the thing in question. By contrast, extrinsic properties (else: predicates) characterize something as it is in relation or connection with something wholly apart from or outside it (or as it fails to be so related). For an overview of debates concerning intrinsicality and extrinsicality, see Marshall and Weatherson (2018).

  3. This understanding of parts in connection with DDS is explicit in Spencer (2017, p. 123), Brower (2009, p. 105), Stump (2013, p. 33), Grant (2012, p. 254), Schmid and Mullins (2021), Leftow (2015, p. 48), Sijuwade (2021), and Dolezal (2011, p. xvii), inter alia.

  4. Rogers (1996, p. 167), Bergmann and Brower (2006, p. 361), Grant (2019, ch. 1).

  5. First, a note. I follow the standard usages of possibility, contingency, and necessity in modal collapse debates. I shall also use possible worlds as a semantic device without ontological import. As I use it, a possible world is just a complete, maximal, or total way reality could be. Second, some definitions. Something exists (obtains, is true) contingently if and only if it exists (obtains, is true) in some possible worlds but not others. In other words, it is possibly within reality, but it is also possibly absent from reality. It can fail to exist (obtain, be true). By contrast, something exists (obtains, is true) necessarily if and only if it exists (obtains, is true) in all possible worlds. It must be in reality; it cannot fail to exist.

  6. Assuming, of course, that reasons are or would be mental items of some kind and, hence, positive ontological items intrinsic to but distinct from God.

  7. Modal collapse arguments have been developed that also focus on God’s knowledge. For treatments, see Schmid and Mullins (2021), Grant (2012), Grant and Spencer (2015), and Moreland and Craig (2003, p. 525). I will only be focusing on modal collapse arguments based either on God’s pure actuality or else God’s identity with God’s acts. Thus, when I say ‘the modal collapse argument’, I only mean this latter type of modal collapse argument.

  8. I am thankful to an anonymous referee for bringing this line of response to my attention. See Waldrop (Forthcoming) for a further discussion of ways to rigidify ‘God’s act of creation’, including various additions of actuality operators and an essentiality thesis.

  9. Definite descriptions and singular terms, when indexed to a designated world by an actuality operator, become rigid. Cf. Waldrop (Forthcoming) and Kaplan (1979).

  10. Here, ‘the actual creation’ rigidly designates this particular creation we actually inhabit.

  11. Deterministic causation occurs just in case it is impossible that the cause C occurs without its effect E. In other words, < ~possibly, C and ~E >. This is equivalent to: < necessarily, ~(C and ~E) >, which in turn is equivalent to < necessarily, if C, then E >. Given that God’s actual act of creation is the cause of the actual creation, it follows that (5) accurately represents the relevant deterministic causal link.

  12. This is my own parody argument, but the idea of a parody along similar lines is found in Tomaszewski (2019).

  13. As I use it, traditional theism is different from classical theism. Traditional theism (again, as I use it) is simply the core theistic claims common to most (if not all) models of the theistic God—God is (i) infallibly omnipotent, (ii) omniscient, (iii) perfectly good, (iv) necessarily existent, and (v) the creator of the concrete world.

  14. Alternatively, one could say that it is only those other things that are connected or related to the act (not vice versa), where the relation they bear to the act is one of causal dependence.

  15. Why? Because (i) otherwise, C is just an inexplicable, brute happening; (ii) God contingently acts as he does at least in part because of who he is (e.g., because he is loving, merciful, just, etc.), and this means that C is explained at least in part by N; and (iii) God’s contingent acts are not arbitrary but instead are reason-based, and this means that his acts are partially explained in terms of the reasons which God essentially has (e.g. in every possible world, God has (non-necessitating) reason to actualize moral agents with whom he can share his love).

  16. Since non-classical theism requires that N is wholly necessary—in which case, it is devoid of contingency. And in that case, it is also devoid of potency. (I am assuming that the non-classical theist agrees with the classical theist that God is not a contingent being).

  17. All that’s needed is that the relevant predication is true not in virtue of how God is in himself but instead in virtue of creation’s dependence (or lack thereof) on God. In other words, all we need is that the relevant predication is extrinsic.

  18. It should be clear, from context, that in each of the previous two sentences, (iii) is intended to be read de dicto rather than de re. That is, the first instance of (iii) means: the necessary truth of the proposition < there is a C1-generating thing >, while the second instance of (iii) means: the necessary truth of the proposition < there is a divine creative act >.

  19. Could the classical theist deny that God intentionally acts? It’s hard to see how. First, this runs contrary to the explicit affirmations of at least many classical theist scholars. As Thomas Ward points out, at least for Christian classical theistic reflection on the doctrine of creation, God’s intentional action must serve as a guidepost and foundation (Ward, 2020, p. 5). And as the classical theist Ron Highfield explains, “God’s act of creating is not irrational or arbitrary but is accompanied by God’s intentions and is directed toward an end” (Highfield, 2015, p. 77). Second, part of what demarcates theism from views like deism and various non-theisms is that ultimate reality is personal (in some sense—perhaps only analogously). And surely acts intentionally is partly constitutive of being personal. Third, some of the most powerful arguments for theism not only become unavailable to classical theists if they deny that God intentionally acts, but they also become arguments against classical theism. For instance, the fine-tuning argument, all sorts of teleological arguments, and many more arguments besides—if successful—show that whatever is ultimately responsible for the universe is an intentional agent.

  20. Recall that I am not mounting these problems as positive arguments against classical theism; I am simply sketching such problems in the hopes of advancing modal collapse debates to issues about divine action raised by the death of modal collapse arguments.

  21. For some treatments of the problem of present luck for libertarianism (which is a version of the luck objection), see (inter alia) Haji (2003), ( 2013), Levy (2005), Mele (2006), Franklin (2011), and Shabo (2014).

  22. Thanks to an anonymous referee for helpful comments.

References

  • Anselm. (2001). Proslogion: With the replies of Gaunilo and Anselm. Hackett publishing company. Translated by T. Williams.

  • Augustine. (1887). The City of God. In P. Schaff (Ed.), Nicene and Post-Nicene Fathers, First Series (Vol. 2). Translated by Marcus Dods. Buffalo, NY: Christian Literature Publishing Co. Revised and edited for New Advent by Kevin Knight. Retrieved from https://www.newadvent.org/fathers/1201.htm.

  • Bergmann, M., & Brower, J. E. (2006). A theistic argument against platonism (and in support of truthmakers and divine simplicity). In D. W. Zimmerman (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brower, J. E. (2009). Simplicity and aseity. In T. P. Flint & M. C. Rea (Eds.), The oxford handbook of philosophical theology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dolezal, J. E. (2011). God without parts: Divine simplicity and the metaphysics of god’s absoluteness. Pickwick Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dolezal, J. E. (2017). All that is in god: Evangelical theology and the challenge of classical christian theism. Reformation Heritage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duby, S. J. (2016). Divine simplicity: A dogmatic account. Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fakhri, O. (2021). Another look at the modal collapse argument. European Journal for Philosophy of Religion., 13(1), 1–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franklin, C. E. (2011). Farewell to the luck (and mind) argument. Philosophical Studies, 156, 199–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franklin, C. E. (2012). The assimilation argument and the rollback argument. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 93, 395–416.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grant, W. M. (2012). Divine simplicity, contingent truths, and extrinsic models of divine knowing. Faith and Philosophy, 29, 254–274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grant, W. M. (2019). Free will and god’s universal causality: The dual sources account. Bloomsbury Academic.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Grant, W. M., & Spencer, M. K. (2015). Activity, identity, and god: A tension in aquinas and his interpreters. Studia Neoaristotelica, 12, 5–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haji, I. (2003). Alternative possibilities, luck, and moral responsibility. The Journal of Ethics, 7(3), 253–275.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haji, I. (2013). Event-causal libertarianism’s control conundrums. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 88, 227–246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Highfield, R. (2015). The faithful creator: Affirming creation and providence in an age of anxiety. InterVarsity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hughes, C. (2018). Aquinas on the nature and implications of divine simplicity. European Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 10, 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. (1979). On the logic of demonstratives. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 8, 81–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leftow, B. (2015). Divine simplicity and divine freedom. Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association, 89, 45–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, N. (2005). Contrastive explanations: A dilemma for libertarians. Dialectica, 59(1), 51–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. K. (1986). On the plurality of worlds. Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marshall, D., & Weatherson, B. (2018). Intrinsic vs. extrinsic properties. Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/intrinsic-extrinsic/.

  • Mele, A. (2006). Free will and luck. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Moreland, J. P., & Craig, W. L. (2003). Philosophical foundations for the christian worldview. InterVarsity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mullins, R. T. (2013). Simply impossible: A case against divine simplicity. Journal of Reformed Philosophy, 7, 181–203.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mullins, R. T. (2016). The end of the timeless god. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mullins, R. T. (2021). Classical theism. In J. M. Arcadi & J. T. Turner (Eds.), T&T clark handbook of analytic theology. New York: T&T Clark.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nemes, S. (2020). Divine simplicity does not entail modal collapse. In C. F. C. da Silveira & A. Tat (Eds.), Roses and Reasons: Philosophical Essays. Eikon.

  • Rogers, K. A. (1996). The traditional doctrine of divine simplicity. Religious Studies, 32(2), 165–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmid, J. C., & Mullins, R. T. (2021). The aloneness argument against classical theism. Religious Studies. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0034412520000554.

  • Shabo, S. (2014). Assimilations and rollbacks: Two arguments against libertarianism defended. Philosophia, 42, 151–172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sijuwade, J. R. (2021). Divine simplicity: The aspectival account. European Journal for Philosophy of Religion. https://doi.org/10.24204/ejpr.2021.3306

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spencer, M. K. (2017). The flexibility of divine simplicity: Aquinas, scotus, palamas. International Philosophical Quarterly, 57(2), 123–139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stump, E. (2013). The nature of a simple god. Proceedings of the ACPA, 87, 33–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomaszewski, C. (2019). Collapsing the modal collapse argument: On an invalid argument against divine simplicity. Analysis, 79(2), 275–284.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vallicella, W. F. (2019). Divine simplicity. Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/divine-simplicity/.

  • Waldrop, J. W. (Forthcoming). Modal collapse and modal fallacies: No easy defense of simplicity. American Philosophical Quarterly.

  • Ward, T. M. (2020). Divine ideas. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Funding

No funding.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Joseph C. Schmid.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The authors declare that they have no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Schmid, J.C. The fruitful death of modal collapse arguments. Int J Philos Relig 91, 3–22 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11153-021-09804-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11153-021-09804-z

Keywords

Navigation