Skip to main content
Log in

The Trio of Time: On Merleau-Ponty’s Phenomenology of Time

  • Theoretical / Philosophical Paper
  • Published:
Human Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The transition from “natural” sensation to “phenomenological” perception is revealed since the dynamic temporality within perception is elaborated by Merleau-Ponty. Inheriting Husserl’s phenomenology of time-consciousness and clarifying temporal elements within body schema, Merleau-Ponty assimilates phenomenological temporality into phenomenal body. With the analyses of spatial synthesis in terms of “depth,” the original unity between temporality of perception and spatiality of body is illuminated. It makes the transition from “temporality of (perceptual) consciousness,” to “temporality of body (perceiving)” possible. Further, by introducing the corporeal temporality and its dynamic model into the phenomenology of Nature that is considered as the foundation of phenomenology of body, Merleau-Ponty put forward a new concept of time. Time as Schema in this sense is integrated into symbiotic structure with Nature and flesh in the name of chiasme.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The “Central I” in Merleau-Ponty’s main texts, for example Phénoménologie de la perception (1945/2004: 478), mainly refers to the “consciousness-subject” with certain constructive effects in the intellectualism with the method of “reflective analysis” in Descartes-Kant tradition. Merleau-Ponty believes that Husserl has surpassed traditional intellectualism and philosophy of consciousness in a sense. Husserl’s analyses of perception and his theory of time-consciousness points out the direction of Merleau-Ponty’s phenomenology of body, but Merleau-Ponty implies that Husserl’s phenomenology still has some kinship with traditional idealism, and does not fully emphasize the unique statue of “body” in direct comparison with “consciousness”. Therefore, coupled with the influence from existential philosophy, in Merleau-Ponty’s view, the “consciousness-subject” referred by the “Central I” exists not only in Descartes-Kant, but also in Husserl’s philosophy. He thinks that Husserl’s philosophy is still a kind of phenomenology of consciousness, which is incompatible with Merleau-Ponty’s own “body-subject” concept in a certain sense.

  2. Merleau-Ponty put this sentence as an inscription at the beginning of the chapter “temporality” in Phenomenology of Perception, which shows that Merleau-Ponty basically accepts Heidegger’s interpretation of the relationship between “Dasein” and “temporality” to a certain extent. See Merleau-Ponty (1945/2004: 471), Heidegger (2010: 316).

References

  • Barbaras, R. (2004). The being of the phenomenon: Merleau-Ponty's ontology (T. Toadvine and L. Lawlor, Trans.). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

  • Bergson, H. (1959a). Matière et mémoire, in œuvres. PUF.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bergson, H. (1959b). La pensée et le mouvant, in œuvres. PUF.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dalissier, M. (2018). Endo-ontology and the later Merleau-Ponty’s thoughts on space-time. Studia Phaenomenologica, 18, 303–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dastur, F. (2004). La phénoménologie en questions. Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2005). How the body shapes the mind. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2013). Husserl and the phenomenology of temporality. In H. Dyke & A. Bardon (Eds.), A companion to the philosophy of time (pp. 135–150). Wiley-BlackWell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2016). Timing is not everything: The intrinsic temporality of action. In R. Altshuler & M. J. Sigrist (Eds.), Time and the philosophy of action (pp. 205–222). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geniusas, S. (2012). The origins of the horizon in Husserl’s phenomenology. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hamrick, W. S., & Veken, J. V. D. (2011). Nature and logos: A Whiteheadian key to Merleau-Ponty’s fundamental thought. State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (2010). Being and time (J. Stambaugh Trans.). Albany: State University of New York Press.

  • Howell, W. (2015). Learning and the development of meaning: Husserl and Merleau-Ponty on the temporality of perception and habit. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 53(3), 311–337.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1973). Experience and judgment: Investigations in a genealogy of logic (J. S. Churchill and K. Ameriks Trans.). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

  • Husserl, E. (1981a). Philosophy as rigorous science (Q. Lauer, Trans.). In P. Mccormick and F. A. Elliston (eds.), Husserl: Shorter works (pp.166–197). Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

  • Husserl, E. (1981b). Foundational investigations of the phenomenological origin of the spatiality of nature (F. Kersten, Trans.). In P. Mccormick and F. A. Elliston (eds.), Husserl: Shorter works (pp.222–233). Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

  • Husserl, E. (1991). On the phenomenology of the consciousness of internal time (1893–1917) (J. B. Brough, Trans.). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

  • Kelly, M. R. (2015). The subject as time: Merleau-Ponty’s transition from phenomenology to ontology. In D. Morris & K. Maclaren (Eds.), Time, memory, institution: Merleau-Ponty’s new ontology of self (pp. 199–215). Ohio University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mazis, G. A. (1992). Merleau-Ponty and the ‘backward flow’ of time: The reversibility of temporality and the temporality of reversibility. In T. W. Busch & S. Gallagher (Eds.), Merleau-Ponty, hermeneutics, and postmodernism (pp. 53–68). State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mazis, G. A. (2016). Merleau-Ponty and the face of the world: Silence, ethics, imagination, and poetic ontology. State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mensch, J. (2010). The temporality of Merleau-Ponty’s intertwining. Continental Philosophy Review, 42, 449–463.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1942/2013). La structure du comportement. Paris: PUF.

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1945/2004). Phénoménologie de la perception. Paris: Gallimard.

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1960). Signes. Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1964). Le visible et l’invisible. Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1968). Résumés de cours: Collège de France 1952–1960. Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1969). La prose du monde. Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1995). La nature: Notes cours du Collège de France. Seuil.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1996a). Le primat de la perception et ses conséquences philosophiques. Lagrasse: Verdier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1996b). Notes de cours: 1959–1961. Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2000). Parcours deux: 1951–1961. Lagrasse: Verdier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2002a). Causeries 1948. Seuil.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2002b). L’union de l’âme et du corps chez Malebranche, Biran et Bergson. Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2003a). L’institution, la passivité: Notes de cours au Collège de France (1954–1955). Belin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2003b). Nature: Course notes from the Collège de France (R. Vallier, Trans.). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2016). Entretiens avec Georges Charbonnier et autres dialogues 1946–1959. Lagrasse: Verdier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morris, D. (2017). Institution, expression, and the temporality of meaning in Merleau-Ponty. In K. Jacobson & J. Russon (Eds.), Perception and its development in Merleau-Ponty’s phenomenology (pp. 193–220). University of Toronto Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Morris, D. (2018). Merleau-Ponty’s developmental ontology. Northwestern University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Romdenh-Romluc, K. (2011). Merleau-Ponty and phenomenology of perception. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sallis, J. (1971). Time, subjectivity, and the phenomenology of perception. The Modern Schoolman, 48, 343–357.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Toadvine, T. (2002). Merleau-Ponty’s reading of Husserl: A chronological overview. In T. Toadvine & L. Embree (Eds.), Merleau-Ponty’s reading of Husserl (pp. 227–286). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Vanzago, L. (2017). The voice of no one: Merleau-Ponty on time and nature. Mimesis International.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J., et al. (1999). The specious present: A neurophenomenology of time consciousness. In J. Petitot & F. J. Varela (Eds.), Naturalizing phenomenology: Issues in contemporary phenomenology and cognitive science (pp. 266–314). Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This work was supported by the National Office for Philosophy and Social Sciences [The National Social Science Fund of China: 20CZX042]. I am also grateful to the anonymous reviewers at Human Studies for their helpful comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Yubin Shen.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Shen, Y. The Trio of Time: On Merleau-Ponty’s Phenomenology of Time. Hum Stud 44, 511–528 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-021-09589-0

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-021-09589-0

Keywords

Navigation