Skip to main content
Log in

The irrelevance of intentions to refer: demonstratives and demonstrations

  • Book Review
  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

According to Mario Gómez-Torrente in Roads to Reference, the reference of a demonstrative is fixed in an object by the speaker’s referential intentions (IRH). I argue that this is a mistake. First, I draw attention to a venerable alternative theory that Gómez-Torrente surprisingly overlooks: the reference is fixed in an object directly by a relation established in perceiving the object. Next I criticize IRH, arguing that it is implausible, redundant, and misleading. Finally, I present a theory of demonstrations that is like the alternative theory for demonstratives. For, though demonstrations do not determine the reference of demonstratives, they play an independent referential role which is important in explaining David Kaplan’s famous Carnap-Agnew example and many others including some of Gómez-Torrente’s.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Notes

  1. All citations of Gómez-Torrente are to this work.

  2. Hanna (1993) is a helpful discussion of Husserl, relating his views to contemporary discussions.

  3. Almog attributes the view to Donnellan without evidence; for discussion, see Devitt (2015, 111 n. 4.)

  4. Devitt (2014) is a response to Hawthorne and Manley’s critique of “acquaintance”. Gómez-Torrente discusses (82–85) the updated presentation of my grounding theory of proper names in Devitt (2015). The update cites (114, n. 14) the earlier presentations of the grounding theory of demonstratives.

  5. Some may be tempted to clutch at the popular weasel word ‘tacit’ at this point. But, absent an account of what it is to tacitly intend to refer, this move yields no explanation.

  6. Developmental evidence (Hakes, 1980) suggests that the capacity to have metalinguistic thoughts comes later, in middle childhood.

  7. There is a theoretical need to distinguish much of the behavior of these organisms, including their referring behavior, from mere bodily movements; we need to distinguish what an organism does, in some sense, from what just happens to it. It is natural to say that the former behavior is intentional. But, according to what Michael Bratman calls “the Simple View” (1984), a behavior is intentional in virtue of having a certain intention as its immediate cause. I follow Bratman in presuming that this view is wrong. If it is not wrong, then we would need some less cognitive notion than this intentional to distinguish these behaviors from mere bodily movements.

  8. Similarly, of analogously parasitic causal-descriptive theories of proper names (Devitt and Sterelny, 1999, 61).

References

  • Almog, J. (2012). Referential uses and the foundations of direct reference. In J. Almog & P. Leonardi (Eds.), Having in mind: The philosophy of Keith Donnellan (pp. 176–184). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bratman, M. (1984). Two faces of intention. Philosophical Review, 93, 375–405.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davies, M. (1981). Meaning, quantification, necessity. Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (1974). Singular terms. Journal of Philosophy LXXI, 183–205.

  • Devitt, M. (1981a). Designation. Columbia University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (1981b). Donnellan’s distinction. In P. A. French, T. E. Uehling, & H. K. Wettstein (Eds.), Midwest studies in philosophy. The foundations of analytic philosophy (Vol. VI, pp. 511–524). University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (2004). The case for referential descriptions. In M. Reimer & A. Bezuidenhout (Eds.), Descriptions and beyond (pp. 280–305). Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (2006). Ignorance of language. Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (2013). Three methodological flaws of linguistic pragmatism. In C. Penco & F. Domaneschi (Eds.), What is said and what is not: The semantics/pragmatics interface (pp. 285–300). CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (2014). Lest auld acquaintance be forgot. Mind and Language, 29, 475–484.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (2015). Should proper names still seem so problematic? In A. Bianchi (Ed.), On reference (pp. 108–143). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (2020). Three mistakes about semantic intentions. In F. Macagno & A. Capone (Eds.), Inquiries in philosophical pragmatics (pp. 9–20). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. and Sterelny, K.. (1999). Language and reality: An introduction to the philosophy of language (2nd edn. 1st edn 1987). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Evans, G. 1982 The varieties of reference. J. McDowell (Ed.). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • Gómez-Torrente, M. (2019). Roads to reference: An essay on reference fixing in natural language. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hakes, D. T. (1980). The development of metalinguistic abilities in children. Springer-Verlag.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hanna, R. (1993). Direct ref, direct perception, and the cognitive theory of demonstratives. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 74, 96–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne, J., & Manley, D. (2012). The reference book. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jeshion, R. (2010). Singular thought: Acquaintance, semantic instrumentalism, and cognitivism. In R. Jeshion (Ed.), New essays on singular thought (pp. 105–140). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. (1979). Dthat. In P. A. French, T. E. Uehling, & H. K. Wettstein (Eds.), Contemporary perspectives in the philosophy of language (pp. 383–400). University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. (1989a). Demonstratives: An essay on the semantics, logic, metaphysics, and epistemology of demonstratives and other indexicals. In J. Almog, J. Perry, & H. Wettstein (Eds.), Themes from Kaplan (pp. 510–563). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. (1989b). Afterthoughts. In J. Almog, J. Perry, & H. Wettstein (Eds.), Themes from Kaplan (pp. 565–614). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • King, J. C. (2001). Complex demonstratives: A quantificational account. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McGinn, C. (1981). The mechanisms of reference. Synthese, 49, 157–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neale, S. (1990). Descriptions. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pendlebury, M. (1984). How demonstratives denote. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 22, 91–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reimer, M. (1991). Demonstratives, demonstrations, and demonstrata. Philosophical Studies, 63, 187–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schiffer, S. (1978). The basis of reference. Erkenntnis, 13, 171–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Speaks, J. (2017). A puzzle about demonstratives and semantic competence. Philosophical Studies, 174, 709–734.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to Andrea Bianchi and Dunja Jutronić for comments on a draft.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michael Devitt.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Devitt, M. The irrelevance of intentions to refer: demonstratives and demonstrations. Philos Stud 179, 995–1004 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-021-01682-5

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-021-01682-5

Navigation