Skip to main content
Log in

Affirming the Existence and Legitimacy of Secular Bioethical Consensus, and Rejecting Engelhardt’s Alternative: A Reply to Nick Colgrove and Kelly Kate Evans

  • Published:
HEC Forum Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

One of the most significant and persistent debates in secular clinical ethics is the question of ethics expertise, which asks whether ethicists can make justified moral recommendations in active patient cases. A critical point of contention in the ethics expertise debate is whether there is, in fact, a bioethical consensus upon which secular ethicists can ground their recommendations and whether there is, in principle, a way of justifying such a consensus in a morally pluralistic context. In a series of recent articles in this journal, Janet Malek defends a positive view of ethics expertise, claiming that secular ethicists should comport their recommendations with bioethical consensus. In response, Nick Colgrove and Kelly Kate Evans deny the existence of a secular bioethical consensus; question why, even if it did exist, consensus should be considered a reliable way of resolving bioethical questions; and recommend a friendlier approach to clinical ethics based on the thought of H. Tristram Engelhardt Jr. In this article, I respond to Colgrove and Evans on all three points. In part one, I show there is a secular bioethical consensus but note it could be better consolidated and created through a more systematic and inclusive process. In part two, I argue that bioethical consensus is morally justified but note that this justification cannot be plausibly based upon claims that it only invokes moral principles available to or shared by all. In part three, I argue Engelhardt’s approach cannot be described as “friendlier” to clinical ethics because it is incompatible with many current healthcare laws and policies.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Malek acknowledges that there are areas of clinical practice where there is no settled bioethical consensus and argues that, in those situations, ethicists should think through problems in a clear and systematic way, arriving at conclusions using accepted moral principles (Malek 2019, p. 95).

  2. The Core Competencies Report admits that ethicists may not always circumscribe a range of ethically permissible options, but instead may occasionally make a singular recommendation that describes only one option as morally justified (American Society for Bioethics and Humanities 2011, p. 8).

  3. See: (American Society for Bioethics and Humanities 2011, 2015 , 2017; Appelbaum 2007; Beauchamp and Childress 2013; Berlinger, Jennings, & Wolf 2013; Diekema, Mercurio, & Adam 2011; Dubler and Liebman 2011; Fletcher, Spencer, & Lombardo 2005; Ford and Dudzinski 2008; Hester and Schonfeld 2012; Jonsen, Siegler, & Winslade 2006; Kon et al. 2016; Lo 2009). Information about the core references and the commission tasked with selecting these references can be found here: https://heccertification.org/.

  4. A perceptive reviewer raised the point that talk of moral epistemology is likely to run bioethicists into interminable philosophical disputes, for example, the internalist vs externalist debate. However, it is precisely these sorts of philosophical arguments that are bracketed by the middle-level approaches to moral theory described by John Arras. On middle-level approaches, it is only necessary that certain principles can acquire widespread agreement that they are morally weighty, not agreement over deeper philosophical issues about why they are morally weighty.

  5. See Kostick et al. for a concise taxonomy of nudging types (Kostick et al., 2020).

  6. For similar articulations of secular bioethical consensus, see Jonathan Moreno, Christopher Meyers, and Stephen Wear (Meyers, 2018; Moreno, 1995; Wear, 2015).

  7. I have several articles that argue against the increasing divide between religious and non-religious voices in bioethics (see, e.g., Brummett forthcoming). Part of what motivates this project is my sincere belief in the value of dissenting views in professional bioethics discourse.

  8. One objection that Engelhardt has made to reflective equilibrium (one Colgrove and Evans may share) is that reflective equilibrium does not produce a single unique moral theory, but that many moral theories can be made to satisfy the criteria of reflective equilibrium (Engelhardt, 2009, p. 301). Engelhardt’s point results from his broader argument that all moral theories must ultimately rely upon foundational premises that are presumed, not proven. While I accept Engelhardt’s point that foundational premises are ultimately presumed, I give a three-part response arguing that reason still plays a significant role in the development and authority of bioethical consensus. First, the moral commitments of bioethical consensus must be made to satisfy the criteria of reflective equilibrium as outlined above. Second, bioethical consensus does not aim at a mere reflective equilibrium, but a wide reflective equilibrium, which requires secular bioethical consensus to also consider relevant non-moral (read scientific, social, metaphysical) commitments (Nichols, 2012). Wide reflective equilibrium opens additional rational standards for bioethical consensus to satisfy (blinded, 2021). Finally, I argue that Engelhardt’s own account faces several internal challenges because it cannot survive the application of the radical critique he levels against other moral approaches to clinical ethics (Brummett, forthcoming, 2021).

  9. Engelhardt’s approach would have more implications than simply overturning current health law and policy that uses coercive force, but I focus on these laws and policies here because they help demonstrate the radical nature of his view for secular clinical ethics.

  10. I am not arguing that all existing law and policy are ethically justified. I am arguing that some laws and policies are ethically justified and that bioethicists have had some influence in the creation of these laws and policies. It is those ethically justified laws and policies (laws and policies that derive their justification, in part, from bioethical consensus) that an Engelhardtean approach would seek to overturn. Describing some of these laws and policies that are incompatible with the principle of permission is the purpose of this third section.

  11. I place the quotations here because many critiques of Engelhardt’s view show the principle contains substantive content (Hanson, 2005; Khushf, 2015).

  12. Engelhardt is not a moral skeptic, he believes we can know moral truths but that we cannot demonstrate them to others using discursive reason (Engelhardt, 2000b).

  13. Engelhardt places one caveat for pediatrics when he writes, “Choosing for [a child] does not violate the principle of permission, unless it is clear that [her] permission would not be given…[T]he most one can say with surety is that one should not directly act to affect [future] persons in ways that are very likely to be against their wishes.” As Hanson notes, this caveat should motivate parents to be so efficient in their abuse of a child that they either “kill it, or leave it with a mental handicap such that it never develops into a full person” (Hanson 2005, p. 197, footnote 1). I would add that brainwashing the child into accepting an unethical intervention (such as conversion therapy) as ultimately good for them is a third way for parents to avoid violating the principle of permission.

  14. For example, Clint Parker argues secular ethicists should draw upon the full range of their comprehensive doctrines when making recommendations (Parker, 2019).

References

  • American Society for Bioethics and Humanities. (2011). Core competencies for healthcare ethics consultation. Glenview: American Society for Bioethics and Humanities.

  • American Society for Bioethics and Humanities. (2015). Improving competencies in clinical ethics consultation: An education guide (2nd ed.). Glenview: American Society for Bioethics and Humanities.

  • American Society for Bioethics and Humanities. (2017). Addressing patient-centered ethical issues in health care: A case-based study guide. Glenview: American Society for Bioethics and Humanities.

  • Appelbaum, P. S. (2007). Assessment of patients’ competence to consent to treatment. New England Journal of Medicine, 357(18), 1834–1840.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arras, J. (2016). Theory and bioethics. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.) Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. [Online] Available: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/theory-bioethics/.

  • Beauchamp, T., & Childress, J. (2013). Principles of biomedical ethics (7th ed.). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berlinger, N., Jennings, B., & Wolf, S. M. (2013). The Hastings Center Guidelines for decisions on life-sustaining treatment and care near the end of life: Revised and expanded second edition. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bishop, J. P., Fanning, J., & Bliton, M. (2009). Of goals and goods and floundering about: A discensus report on clinical ethics consultation. HCE Forum. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10730-009-9109-6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brummett, A. & Salter, E. (2019). Taxonomizing views of clinical ethics expertise. The American Journal of Bioethics 19(11), 50−61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brummett, A. (forthcoming). Defending secular clinical ethics expertise from an Engelhardt-inspired sense of theoretical crisis. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics.

  • Buchanan, A. E., & Brock, D. W. (1989). Deciding for others: The ethics of surrogate decision making. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colgrove, N., & Evans, K. K. (2019). The place for religious content in clinical ethics consultations: A reply to Janet Malek. HEC Forum, 31(4), 305–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diekema, D., Mercurio, M., & Adam, M. (2011). Clinical ethics in pediatrics: A case-based textbook. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dubler, N. N., & Liebman, C. B. (2011). Bioethics mediation: A guide to shaping shared solutions. Vanderbilt University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Engelhardt, H. T., Jr. (1991). Bioethics and secular humanism. SCM Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engelhardt, H. T., Jr. (1996). The foundations of bioethics (2nd ed.). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engelhardt, H. T., Jr. (2000a). Autonomy: The cardinal principle of contemporary bioethics. Rhodos International.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engelhardt, H. T., Jr. (2000b). The foundations of Christian bioethics. Taylor & Francis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engelhardt, H. T., Jr. (2009). Credentialing strategically ambiguous and heterogeneous social skills: The emperor without clothes. HEC Forum, 21(3), 293–306. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10730-009-9106-9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Engelhardt, H. T., Jr. (2011a). Bioethics critically reconsidered: Having second thoughts (Vol. 100). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engelhardt, H. T., Jr. (2011b). The search for global morality: Bioethics, moral diversity, & the collapse of consensus. In 28th annual interdisciplinary faculty seminar series: Global health and medical ethics, Baylor University.

  • Engelhardt, H. T., Jr. (2012). Why clinical bioethics so rarely gives morally normative guidance. In H. T. Engelhardt (Ed.), Bioethics critically reconsidered: Having second thoughts (pp. 151–174). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Engelhardt, H. T., Jr. (2017). After God: Morality and bioethics in a secular age. St Vladimir’s Seminary Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fletcher, J. C., Spencer, E. M., & Lombardo, P. A. (2005). Fletcher’s introduction to clinical ethics. University Publishing Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ford, P. J., & Dudzinski, D. M. (2008). Complex ethics consultations: Cases that haunt us. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Garrett, J. R. (2015). Cracks in the foundations of Engelhardt’s bioethics. In L. Rasmussen, A. Iltis, & M. J. Cherry (Eds.), At the foundations of bioethics and biopolitics: Critical essays on the thought of H. Tristram Engelhardt, Jr. (pp. 215–230). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hanson, S. (2005). Engelhardt and children: The failure of libertarian bioethics in pediatric interactions. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 15(2), 179–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hanson, S. S. (2009). Moral acquaintances and moral decisions: Resolving moral conflicts in medical ethics (Vol. 103). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hester, D. M., & Schonfeld, T. (2012). Guidance for healthcare ethics committees. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jonsen, A. R. (2005). On the origins and future of the Belmont Report. Georgetown University Press.

  • Jonsen, A. R., Siegler, M., & Winslade, W. J. (2006). Clinical ethics: A practical approach to ethical decisions in clinical medicine. McGraw Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khushf, G. (2015). A transcendental argument for agreement as the sole sufficient basis of a philosophical ethic. In At the foundations of bioethics & biopolitics: Critical essays on the thought of H. Tristram Engelhardt, Jr. (pp. 87–144). Springer.

  • Kon, A. A., Shepard, E. K., Sederstrom, N. O., Swoboda, S. M., Marshall, M. F., Birriel, B., & Rincon, F. (2016). Defining futile and potentially inappropriate interventions: A policy statement from the Society of Critical Care Medicine Ethics Committee. Critical Care Medicine, 44(9), 1769–1774.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kostick, K. M., Trejo, M., Volk, R. J., Estep, J. D., & Blumenthal-Barby, J. S. (2020). Using nudges to enhance clinicians’ implementation of shared decision making with patient decision aids. MDM Policy & Practice, 5(1), 2381468320915906.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lo, B. (2009). Resolving ethical dilemmas: A guide for clinicians (4th ed.). Wolters Kluwer Health.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malek, J. (2019). The appropriate role of a clinical ethics consultant’s religious worldview in consultative work: Nearly none. HEC Forum, 31, 91–102.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCullough, L. B. (2015). A critical appraisal of Engelhardt on the “Enlightenment Project.” In L. M. Rasmussen, A. Iltis, & M. J. Cherry (Eds.), At the foundations of bioethics and biopolitics: Critical essays on the thought of H. Tristram Engelhardt, Jr. (pp. 3–12). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meyers, C. (2018). Ethics expertise: What it is, how to get it, and what to do with it. In J. C. Watson, & L. K. Guidry-Grimes (Eds.), Moral Expertise (pp. 53–70). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moreno, J. (1995). Deciding together: Bioethics and moral consensus. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, P. (2012). Wide reflective equilibrium as a method of justification in bioethics. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, 33(5), 325–341.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Rourke, K. D., Kopfen-Steiner, T., & Hamel, R. (2001). A brief history: A summary of the development of the Ethical and Religious Directives for Catholic Health Care Services. Health Progress, 82(6), 18–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parker, J. C. (2019). Religion, authenticity, and clinical ethics consultation. HEC Forum, 31(2), 103–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rasmussen, L. M. (2015). Non-certain foundations: Clinical ethics consultation for the rest of us. In L. M. Rasmussen, A. Iltis, & M. J. Cherry (Eds.), At the foundations of bioethics and biopolitics: Critical essays on the thought of H. Tristram Engelhardt, Jr. (pp. 187–199). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rothman, D. J. (1991). Strangers at the bedside: A history of how law and bioethics transformed medical decision making. BasicBooks.

    Google Scholar 

  • Truog, R. D., & Miller, F. G. (2008). The dead donor rule and organ transplantation. New England Journal of Medicine, 359(7), 674–675.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • United States Conference of Catholic Bishops. (2018). Ethical and Religious Directives for Catholic Health Care Services.

  • Veatch, R. M. (2019). Controversies in defining death: A case for choice. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, 40(5), 381–401.

    Google Scholar 

  • Veatch, R. M., & Guidry-Grimes, L. K. (2019). The basics of bioethics. Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wasserman, J. A., & Navin, M. C. (2018). Capacity for preferences: Respecting patients with compromised decision-making. Hastings Center Report, 48(3), 31–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Watson, J. C., & Guidry-Grimes, L. K. (2018). Moral expertise: New essays from theoretical and clinical bioethics. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wear, S. (2015). The foundations of secular bioethics. In L. M. Rasmussen, A. Iltis, & M. J. Cherry (Eds.), At the foundations of bioethics and biopolitics: Critical essays on the thought of H. Tristram Engelhardt, Jr. (pp. 45–56). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Abram Brummett.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author declares to have no conflicts of interest.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Brummett, A. Affirming the Existence and Legitimacy of Secular Bioethical Consensus, and Rejecting Engelhardt’s Alternative: A Reply to Nick Colgrove and Kelly Kate Evans. HEC Forum 35, 95–109 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10730-021-09452-w

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10730-021-09452-w

Keywords

Navigation