Skip to main content
Log in

From Externalism to Internalism: The Historiographical Development of Thomas Kuhn

  • Published:
Foundations of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I will present a comparative analysis between Thomas Kuhn's The Copernican Revolution (CR) published in 1957 and The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (SSR) published in 1962, ir order to identify divergences in the views contained in each work. I shall set forth a comparative analysis of the historiographical assumptions employed by Kuhn in each of his books. I will explore some proposals which have pointed out several discontinuities between both books, as I introduce some tools to widen this interpretative trend. I will argue that although Kuhn’s work in 1957 contains some concerns and problems which anticipate his later stances, these anticipations coexist with historiographical formulations and premises which are incompatible with the core of SSR. Therefore, I will assert that Kuhn adopts different historiographical frameworks in CR and in SSR. Finally, I will conclude that these differences are expressions of Kuhn's adoption of a more externalist view in the former, and a more internalist frame in the latter.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Availability of Data and Material

Not applicable.

Code Availability

Not applicable.

Notes

  1. Strictly speaking, 'paradigm' (p. 222) and 'incommensurable' (p. 47) appear once, but Kuhn uses the terms colloquially, without the theoretical content they have in SSR.

  2. Director of the Center for Advanced Study in the Behavioral Sciences at Stanford University, where Kuhn spent a year between 1958 and 1959.

  3. Kuhn to Tyler, July 31, 1959. Archives, Center for Advanced Study in the Behavioral Sciences, Stanford, California, quoted in Hufbauer (2012: 451).

  4. Westman points out that CR does not offer an account of why some astronomers converted to Copernicanism and others did not, so that ‘Kuhn produces no conversion stories for any of these figures. Instead, he circumnavigates the difficulty by falling back on a more general, less controversial, claim: Copernicus's work changed ‘the field’; it helped to open up new problems and cast doubt on the Ptolemaic alternative, even if it failed to win over most technically proficient conservative astronomers.’ (1994: 95).

  5. In CR Kuhn claims: ‘many of those who took the observations seriously did make the full translation. These new converts may also have been impelled by another consideration: the Copernicans… had anticipated the sort of universe that the telescope was disclosing.’ (1957: 224).

  6. See Hacking (1993), Hoyningen-Huene (1993), Fuller (2000: Ch. 4) and Bird (2015).

  7. ‘The combination of science and intellectual history is, however, essential in approaching the plural structure of the Copernican Revolution… Astronomers were trained in other sciences as well, and they were committed to various philosophical and religious systems. Many of their non-astronomical beliefs were fundamental first in postponing and then in shaping the Copernican Revolution. These non-astronomical beliefs compose my ‘intellectual history’ component…’ (1957: viii).

  8. ‘An extended treatment would also discuss the social pressure for calendar reform, a pressure that made the puzzle of precession particularly urgent. In addition, a fuller account would consider medieval criticism of Aristotle, the rise of Renaissance Neoplatonism, and other significant historical elements besides. But technical breakdown would still remain the core of the crisis.’ (1962: 69). Also in CR, ‘The resulting demand for calendar reform provided one important motive for the reform of astronomy itself, and the reform that gave the Western world its modern calendar followed the publication of De Revolutionibus by only thirty-nine years.’ (1957: 11).

  9. ‘When 60 years after his (Copernicus) death the telescope suddenly displayed mountains on the moon, the phases of Venus, and an immense number of previously unsuspected stars, those observations brought the new theory a great many converts, particularly among non-astronomers.’ (1962: 154–155).

  10. About the first process, Kuhn claims ‘By the early sixteenth century an increasing number of Europe’s best astronomers were recognizing that the astronomical paradigm was failing in application to its own traditional problems. That recognition was prerequisite to Copernicus’ rejection of the Ptolemaic paradigm and his search for a new one.’ (1962: 67). Regarding the second: ‘The quantitative superiority of Kepler’s Rudolphine tables to all those computed from the Ptolemaic theory was a major factor in the conversion of astronomers to Copernicanism.’ (1962: 153).

References

  • Barker, P. (2001). Incommensurability and conceptual change during the Copernican revolution. In P. Hoyningen-Huene & H. Sankey (Eds.), Incommensurability and related matters (pp. 241–273). Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. (2015). Kuhn and the historiography of science. In W. Devlin & A. Bokulich (Eds.), Kuhn’s structure of scientific revolutions—50 years on (pp. 23–38). Dordrecht.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fuller, S. (2000). Thomas Kuhn. A philosophical history for our times. The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1993). Working in a new world: The taxonomic solution. In P. Horwich (Ed.), World changes. Thomas Kuhn and the nature of science (pp. 275–310). MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heilbron, J. L. (1998). Thomas Samuel Kuhn. Isis, 89(3), 505–515. Retrieved March 23, 2021, from http://www.jstor.org/stable/237146

  • Hoyningen-Huene, P. (1993). Reconstructing scientific revolutions. The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoyningen-Huene, P. (1995). Two letters of Paul Feyerabend to Thomas S. Kuhn on a draft of The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 26(3), 353–387. https://doi.org/10.1016/0039-3681(95)00005-8

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoyningen-Huene, P. (2006). More letters by Paul Feyerabend to Thomas S. Kuhn on proto-structure. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 37(4), 610–632. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2006.09.007

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoyningen-Huene, P. (2012). Philosophical elements in Thomas Kuhn’s historiography of science. Theoria, 75, 281–292. https://doi.org/10.1387/theoria.6160

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoyningen-Huene, P. (2015). Kuhn’s development before and after structure Paul Hoyningen-Huene. In Alisa Bokulich & William J. Devlin (eds.), Kuhn’s Structure of Scientific Revolutions - 50 Years On. Springer

  • Hufbauer, K. (2012). From student of physics to historian of science: T. S. Kuhn’s education and early career, 1940–1958. Physics in Perspective, 14, 421–470. https://doi.org/10.1007/s00016-012-0098-5

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Isaac, J. (2012). Working knowledge. Making the human sciences from Parsons to Kuhn. Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1957). The Copernican revolution. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1959). Energy conservation as an example of simultaneous discovery. In M. Clagett (Ed.), Critical problems in the history of science (pp. 321–356). Madison, University of Wisconsin Press. Repr. in The Essential Tension, 66–104.

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1960). Engineering precedent for the work of Sadi Carnot. Archives Internationales D’histoire Des Sciences, 13, 251–255.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1961). The function of measurement in modern physical science. Isis, 52, 161–193. Repr. in The Essential Tension, 178–224. Retrieved March 23, 2021, from http://www.jstor.org/stable/228678

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1962). The structure of scientific revolutions (2nd ed.). University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1977). Preface. In The essential tension. Selected studies in scientific tradition and change (pp. ix–xxiii). The University of Chicago Press.

  • Kuhn, T. S. (2000). A discussion with Thomas S. Kuhn. A Valtas, C. Gavroglu, V. Kindi. In The road since structure (pp. 255–323). Chicago University Press.

  • Kuhn, T. S. (2021). The quest for physical theory: Problems in the methodology of scientific research. Lowell lectures. Thomas S. Kuhn’s Lowell lectures of 1951 edited with an introduction by George A. Reisch.

  • Marcum, J. (2005). Thomas Kuhn’s revolution: An historical philosophy of science. Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayoral, J. (2012). Five decades of Structure. A retrospective view. Theoria, 75, 261–280. Retrieved March 23, 2021, from http://www.jstor.org/stable/23926395

  • Mayoral, J. (2017). Thomas S. Kuhn. La búsqueda de La Estructura. Prensas de la Universidad de Zaragoza.

    Google Scholar 

  • Omodeo, P. (2016). Kuhn’s paradigm of paradigms: Historical and epistemological coordinates of The Copernican Revolution. In A. Blum, K. Gavroglu, C. Joas, & J. Renn (Eds.), Shifting paradigms. Thomas S. Kuhn and the history of science (pp. 71–104). Max Planck Institute for the History of Science.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinto de Oliveira, J. C. (2007). Carnap, Kuhn, and revisionism: On the publication of Structure in Encyclopedia. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 38, 147–157. Retrieved March 23, 2021, from http://www.jstor.org/stable/20722480

  • Pinto de Oliveira, J. C. (2017). Thomas Kuhn, the image of science and the image of art: The first manuscript of structure. Perspectives on Science, 25(6), 746–765. https://doi.org/10.1162/POSC_a_00264

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reisch, G. (2019). The politics of paradigms. The State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swerdlow, N. (2004). An essay on Thomas Kuhn’s first scientific revolution, the Copernican revolution. Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 148(1), 64–120. Retrieved March 23, 2021, from http://www.jstor.org/stable/1558245

  • Westman, R. (1994). Two cultures or one?: A second look at Kuhn’s the Copernican revolution. Isis, 85(1), 79–115. Retrieved March 23, 2021, from http://www.jstor.org/stable/235897

  • Wray, B. (2011). Kuhn’s evolutionary social epistemology. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wray, B. (2019). Kuhn, the history of chemistry and the philosophy of science. Hopos, 9, 75–92. https://doi.org/10.1086/700174

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Paul Hoyningen-Huene, K. Brad Wray, Juan V. Mayoral, Agustín Courtoisie and Hernán Miguel for the fruitful discussions given during the preparation of this paper, James Lumsden for careful reading of several versions of the manuscript, and two anonymous reviewers from Foundations of Science whose comments and criticisms contributed to substantially improve the final version.

Funding

University of the Republic (UdelaR), Uruguay/National Agency for Innovation and Research (ANII), Uruguay.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

Not applicable.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Pablo Melogno.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

Not applicable.

Ethics Approval

Not applicable.

Consent to Participate

Not applicable.

Consent for Publication

Not applicable.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Melogno, P. From Externalism to Internalism: The Historiographical Development of Thomas Kuhn. Found Sci 27, 371–385 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-021-09801-5

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-021-09801-5

Keywords

Navigation