1 Introduction

On 20 December 2019, the Dutch Supreme Court decided on a landmark climate change case: the Urgenda case.Footnote 1 In its judgement, the Court declared that the European Convention on Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms (ECHR)Footnote 2 imposes a positive obligation on the Netherlands. This obligation entails that the state needs to take appropriate measures for the prevention of climate change. In this context, the Court referred to the United Nations climate change regimeFootnote 3 and the commitment of Annex I state parties to the aim of reducing greenhouse gas emissions by 25–40% by 2020.Footnote 4 Such obligations, as further developed in the Paris Agreement under the United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change (Paris Agreement), are known as due diligence obligations. Remarkably, the Dutch Supreme Court considered that positive obligations under Articles 2 (the right to life) and 8 (the right to respect for one’s private life, family life and home) ECHR were the basis for taking all appropriate measures to implement reduction commitments to prevent climate change.Footnote 5 The Court, however, did not elaborate on the question whether the concept of due diligence in international environmental law and the concept of positive obligation in international human rights law are the same or different. More in general, recent studies point out that much is still to be explored when it comes to the normative content of due diligence and its systemic relation to various norms in international law.Footnote 6

This article aims to contribute to the understanding of due diligence in international law. Most academics examine this notion as a technique to allocate accountability in the context of risk managementFootnote 7 or in the context of primary and secondary rules in international law.Footnote 8 However, such perspectives relate to only one side of the coin. In international law, due diligence obligations are also used as a regulatory technique where the norm addressee enjoys a broad discretion so as to attain regulatory goals. Due diligence obligations, after all, do not prescribe a particular measure that has to be taken. The norm addressee only has to undertake its best efforts, leading to further law-making and decision-making by the norm addressee. Such regulatory understanding of due diligence obligations, remarkably, remains unexplored in legal literature.Footnote 9 This being said, due diligence obligations arguably operate in two paradigms: an accountability paradigm and a regulation paradigm. Since such a distinction has not yet been examined in greater detail, this article will explore these two paradigms to construct a working model of due diligence in international law. This working model will then form the basis for a comparative legal study of the operation of due diligence obligations under the Paris Agreement and positive obligations under the ECHR. In the end, the findings of this study can be used to further clarify the meaning of this familiar stranger in international lawFootnote 10 and to explain corresponding legal rights of subjects of international law.Footnote 11

The structure of this article is as follows. Section 2 will first discuss a particular due diligence obligation that is vital for contemporary climate change mitigation, namely the obligation to take precautionary measures to prevent environmental harm or the risk thereof. This is also known as the precautionary principle. Section 3, subsequently, will analyse the two paradigms of due diligence obligations. This will be illustrated with the help of the precautionary principle. By doing so, a working model of due diligence obligations can be constructed, forming the theoretical framework for the comparative legal study in this article. Section 4 will compare the operation of due diligence obligations related to the nationally determined contributions (NDCs) under the Paris Agreement with the operation of positive obligations under Article 8 ECHR. It will use the theoretical framework as constructed in Sect. 3 to identify similarities and differences. Finally, Sect. 5 will reflect on these findings: due diligence remains a familiar stranger in international law, while at the same time its rise is of systemic importance to many areas of international law.

2 The Precautionary Principle: A Due Diligence Obligation

Due diligence is a frequently employed concept in international law.Footnote 12 However, it has been interpreted and applied differently in international law.Footnote 13 For example, the second report on due diligence by the International Law Association (ILA) refers to due diligence as a broad principle of international law, but also as specific obligations in several branches of international law.Footnote 14 Barnidge, however, refers to due diligence as a ‘well-established principle of international law’ of which its interpretation depends on the responsibility of a state for non-state actors within its territory.Footnote 15 In contrast, Schmitt asserts that due diligence has a broader scope as it is not limited to only non-state actors, but concerns the obligation of a state to ensure acts within the territory under its control are not used to the detriment of other states.Footnote 16 Others, like Pisillo-Mazzeschi and Kulesza, rather refer to due diligence in the context of general accountability.Footnote 17

Although the notion of due diligence has been given different meanings, it has evolved most notably in international environmental law since the second half of the twentieth century.Footnote 18 With that in mind, due diligence concerns a key element in this branch of international law, especially when it comes to preventing transboundary environmental harm to other states and protecting the environment in general. States, in that way, have duties of care. Legal doctrineFootnote 19 and case lawFootnote 20 predominantly refer to such duties as ‘obligations of conduct’. An example is the obligation of states to take precautionary measures that can reasonably be expected from the state to prevent environmental harm. This is also known as the precautionary principle.Footnote 21

This Section will briefly outline the precautionary principle as the remainder of this study will rely on and refer to this fundamental principle of international environmental law. Discussing the precautionary principle, however, cannot be done without first addressing the notion of prevention.Footnote 22 In contemporary international environmental law, the aspect of prevention plays an important role as the activities on the territory of one state can have an impact on the territory of another.Footnote 23 In the end, damage to the environment is commonly irreversible, restoration of the situation is frequently impossible and hazardous activities can lead to high costs.Footnote 24 With that in mind, Sect. 2.1. will address the principle of prevention and Sect. 2.2 will discuss the precautionary principle.

2.1 The Principle of Prevention

The idea that ‘prevention is rather better than the cure’ has been widely admitted in international environmental law.Footnote 25 This has been affirmed in arbitral awards and the case law of the International Court of Justice (ICJ), stating that the principle of prevention is now a ‘principle of general international law’, respectively a ‘customary rule’.Footnote 26 In international environmental law, the notion of prevention was famously addressed in the Trail Smelter caseFootnote 27:

under the principles of international law […] no state has the right to use or permit the use of its territory in such a manner as to cause injury by fumes in or to the territory of another or the properties or persons therein, when the case is of serious consequence and the injury is established by clear and convincing evidence.Footnote 28

A state needs to ensure that in its jurisdiction other states’ rights and interests are not violated (the ‘no harm’ principle).Footnote 29 The breach of such obligation would occur if a state fails to take measures so as to prevent activities that have a ‘serious consequence’ and lead to injuries based on ‘clear and convincing evidence’. According to Barnidge, the terms ‘serious consequence’ and ‘clear and convincing evidence’ show the importance of the significant nature of the injury in question. The Trail Smelter judgement, in that way, excludes de minimis injuries.Footnote 30 That is to say, only materialised damage is included and not a mere risk thereof.Footnote 31 As such, a state cannot be assumed to be responsible for all activities on its territory.Footnote 32 What is expected from the state is that it takes reasonable measures that are available to it to prevent materialised harm. In that regard, a state is presumed to act in ‘good faith’ when it comes to the prevention of the harm.Footnote 33

2.2 The Precautionary Principle

As the principle of prevention requires a state to take action to prevent environmental harm, such actions need to be taken—if possible—before damage actually has occurred.Footnote 34 Following the Trail Smelter dictum, a state would only breach this duty of care if the case has a ‘serious consequence’ and the injury is established on ‘clear and convincing evidence’. Such high thresholds suggest that action shall only be taken where there is scientific evidence that serious environmental harm will occur.Footnote 35 Obtaining sufficient scientific evidence, however, is often difficult. This limitation of the principle of prevention has been widely recognised in several international legal instrumentsFootnote 36 and in case lawFootnote 37 in the form of the precautionary principle. The rationale for this principle is that where environmental damage will be irreversible and damage cannot be repaired or only at very high expense,Footnote 38 the lack of scientific proof shall not be used as a justification to postpone the taking of preventive measures.Footnote 39 That is to say, even in a situation where there is only the risk of harm but it has not yet materialised, a state is required to take precautions.

Nonetheless, the legal status and exact meaning of the precautionary principle remain unclear.Footnote 40 During the negotiations of the United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change (1992 UNFCCC), reference to the precautionary principle was controversial. As a result, the eventual text adopted includes limitations on the application of the principle. Article 3(3) of the 1992 UNFCCC, for instance, requires the damage to be ‘serious or irreversible’. On top of that, the provision only requires state parties to take those measures that are ‘cost effective’.Footnote 41 However, Article 3(3) of the 1992 UNFCCC does not contain the high threshold of ‘clear and convincing evidence’ as articulated in the Trail Smelter case. As such, the precautionary principle justifies a lower standard of proof. Other international legal instruments also use a lower threshold. For instance, Article 2(2)(a) of the Convention for the Protection of the Marine Environment of the North-East Atlantic (OSPAR Convention) requires its parties to take preventive action when there are reasonable grounds for concern that environmental hazards will occur, even when the harm cannot be fully scientifically proven.Footnote 42

The general idea of the precautionary principle is that states need to act carefully and with foresight when it comes to activities in their jurisdiction which may have negative consequences for the environment, even when there is a lack of scientific evidence.Footnote 43 However, when environmental harm can actually be proved based on ‘clear and convincing evidence’ the prevention principle takes over, requiring a higher degree of diligence from the state.Footnote 44 This leads to the question of how due diligence is to be understood in the context of environmental pollution. To answer this question, it is useful to examine the notion of due diligence in international law.

3 Due Diligence in International Law: One obligation, Two Paradigms

As the precautionary principle is a due diligence obligation, the state needs to act diligently and with foresight when it comes to activities in their jurisdiction that may cause significant harm to the environment or the risk thereof. Risk management lies at the heart of due diligence obligations. At the same time, due diligence obligations are also used as a regulatory technique to outsource law-making and decision-making to the norm addressees of these obligations. This Section will address these two perspectives. To illustrate these, the precautionary principle will be used as an example for each perspective. First, Sect. 3.1 will examine due diligence obligations in the context of risk management. Fundamental to such an examination is the dichotomy of obligations of conduct and result known in civil law to hold the norm addressee accountable. Section 3.2, subsequently, will analyse due diligence obligations through a completely different lens, namely one of regulation. In this regard, a different dichotomy is used which confusingly uses the same terms as the civil law dichotomy. The terms ‘obligation of conduct’ and ‘obligation of result’ are given a totally different meaning when analysing due diligence obligations in a regulatory context. Finally, Sect. 3.3 will put together the threads and construct a working model, forming the theoretical foundation to compare due diligence obligations for the remainder of the present study.

3.1 Obligations of Conduct and Result: An Accountability Perspective

The distinction between obligations of conduct and of result has a long history in civil law traditions.Footnote 45 Its origins can be traced back to the Roman law concept of bonus pater familias, which has systematically further developed in French law as the concept of bon père de famille.Footnote 46 This entails that a person is obliged to exercise a certain degree of reasonable care when he affects other persons or their property. Such an obligation de moyens (obligation of means or conduct) needs to be distinguished from what can be called an obligation de résultat (obligation of result).Footnote 47

The classic example is one of a medical doctor. If a doctor is obliged to cure his patient, he would have an obligation of result. However, a doctor would most certainly not want to commit himself to achieving such results as he cannot guarantee the patient’s health at all times. On the contrary, a doctor rather assumes the obligation to do everything possible to cure his patient, which is an obligation of conduct: he needs to do everything that a ‘reasonable person’ and ‘competent physician’ placed in the same circumstances can do to look after his patient. If he fails to do so, he will be held responsible for a failure to demonstrate his ‘best efforts’, regardless of whether he would have healed his patient or not. Consequently, he is not accountable for the final outcome, but only for his conduct.Footnote 48

The distinction between obligations of conduct and obligations of result is particularly meaningful for two reasons. First of all, the distinction leads to a change in the parties’ burden of proof. In the case of an obligation of result, the debtor who agreed to achieve a certain result is presumed to be responsible ipso facto, unless he is able to exonerate himself by force majeure. In that way, a patient would only have to show that his doctor failed to achieve the desired result, namely healing him. The burden of proof then lies on the doctor, since he has to free himself by proving that it was impossible for him to perform his obligation.Footnote 49 However, the burden of proof is different in the case of an obligation of conduct as this type of obligation does not entail responsibility ipso facto. This is favourable to the debtor since his conduct is closely related to risk management.Footnote 50 If his obligation is an obligation of conduct rather than of result, he does not have to prove anything. Instead, it is the creditor that needs to prove that the debtor did not demonstrate his best efforts. In other words, the burden of proof lies not on the doctor, but on the patient.Footnote 51 On top of that, the patient needs to prove the damage that was caused by the doctor’s lack of care. Accordingly, proving the breach of an obligation of conduct is more difficult.Footnote 52

Another practical interest for using the distinction between obligations of conduct and result is that it enables the determination of the exact moment of a violation. In the case of obligations of result, the moment of a violation occurs when the given result is not achieved. For an obligation of conduct, however, the moment of violating the norm concerns the occurrence of the situation prohibited by the norm and not the result that could have occurred because of it.Footnote 53

For the above-mentioned reasons, and especially from the perspective of risk management, the civil law dichotomy has proven to be useful in the context of international environmental law and transboundary damage.Footnote 54 One of the first pioneers to have introduced the civil law dichotomy in international law was Paul Reuter.Footnote 55 According to him, obligations of result require a state to specifically perform a certain action, whereas an obligation of conduct requires a state to present its best efforts.Footnote 56 For example, the obligation of a state to take all necessary measures to prevent environmental harm (the principle of prevention) would be an obligation of conduct and not an obligation of result. In that context, a state may be held accountable if it did not demonstrate its best efforts—even if environmental harm has not (yet) occurred. The failure of having showed sufficient care and the existence of significant (risk of) environmental harm needs to be proven by the injured party. The rationale of the obligation of conduct is to release the burden of proof from the norm addressee of the obligation. In that regard, the state is presumed to act in ‘good faith’, thereby placing the burden of proof upon the party claiming the violation. As in civil law, it is difficult for this party to prove that the state has failed to take reasonable measures, especially when there is a lack of scientific evidence.Footnote 57 In the case of a lack of scientific evidence, the precautionary principle would be applicable.

The precautionary principle can also be qualified as an obligation of conduct. As the rationale of an obligation of conduct is to place the burden of proof upon the party claiming the violation, the state is assumed to have acted in good faith. In principle, the state would not have to prove anything, yet in the case of the precautionary principle a lower ‘standard of proof’ is used for the party claiming the violation. The latter does not have to rely on ‘clear and convincing evidence’ when it comes to the existence of the risk of environmental harm. Instead, it has to prove that the state has not taken precautionary actions to become aware of the risk of environmental harm. An example is proof that the state has failed to establish a legislative or other regulatory framework which should have made it possible for it to become aware of the risk of environmental harm.Footnote 58 It would then be up to the state to prove the non-existence of the risk.Footnote 59

3.2 Obligations of Conduct and Result: A Regulatory Perspective

As illustrated, due diligence obligations are useful in international law as regards holding a state accountable in the context of risk management. However, due diligence obligations are also used as a regulatory technique. Remarkably, the dichotomy between ‘obligations of conduct’ and ‘obligations of result’ is then used, yet the underlying idea is not the same as the civil law dichotomy. As the meaning of the terms ‘result’ and ‘conduct’ change in the context of regulation, a different dichotomy is in fact followed. This can be best explained with the work of the legal philosopher Pauline Westerman.Footnote 60 According to her, in a regulatory context an ‘obligation of result’ merely prescribes the ends to be pursued by regulation. This implies that the norm addressee needs to realise certain regulatory ends, but leaves it up to the norm addressee to determine how these ends are realised. Put differently, how regulation is done is up to the norm addressee to decide, as long as the norm addressee takes measures to achieve the end result of regulation.Footnote 61 The precautionary principle is a perfect example.Footnote 62 This obligation requires a state to take precautionary measures and leaves a great amount of discretion as to which measures are taken to meet the regulatory end result. The required end result is that the state takes regulatory measures that it regards as necessary and appropriate to realise the required precautions to prevent environmental degradation. If, according to Westerman, the obligation concerns an ‘obligation of conduct’, the norm addressee is required to take specified regulatory action. The norm addressee must simply perform the specific action required by the norm to realise the end result of regulation. This leaves no regulatory discretion for the norm addressee. For example, if a treaty provision requires a state ‘to create an administrative body as a precautionary measure to reach the regulatory end-goal of preventing environmental harm’, the norm is very concrete and provides a clear direction: the state must establish that administrative body. This is the end result and it is not up to the state to decide whether this is the best way to implement the precautionary principle.Footnote 63 Arguably, this idea of ‘obligations of result’ was already introduced in international law by Roberto Ago in his Sixth Report on State Responsibility in 1997.Footnote 64 Although Ago’s understanding of obligations of conduct and result received major criticism in the context of state responsibility, his dichotomy in fact is not useless when it comes to a regulatory perspective on due diligence obligations.Footnote 65

The reason for qualifying due diligence obligations as obligations of result from a regulatory perspective is that the employment of such obligations leads to a particular mode of regulation, also known as ‘outcome-based’ or ‘result-driven’ regulation.Footnote 66 This mode of regulation has the function to, what Westerman qualifies as, ‘outsourced rule-making’.Footnote 67 By outsourcing, Westerman neither refers to the practice of hiring external experts in order to draft rules nor to consulting online or offline practices in which the public or experts are invited to provide their input in the law-making. She rather refers to ‘a much more radical practice’ in which the outsourcer formulates the desired outcomes or goals with the use of ‘duties of care’.Footnote 68 Such norms do not indicate how the goal needs to be reached, but only require the norm-addressee to demonstrate his maximum efforts. It is then within the competence of the norm addressee to decide how to attain the given goal.Footnote 69

With such a mode of regulation, law-making is decentralised in many branches of international law. The reason for this is that a network of regional, national and local actors becomes more involved. In that way, expertise can be fully utilised and aspirational goals set out by the norm can effectively be reached. Regulating behaviour on the international level, after all, is a challenging task. Much depends on expertise and implementation by individual states, and the social field that is to be regulated by a branch of international law is diverse as states have their own norms, values, laws, cultures, practices and customs. In the end, specific rule-making might be in conflict with entrenched domestic rules of a state and ‘cut against the grain’ of state sovereignty.Footnote 70 Moreover, the implementation of international norms might differ for each state. As states themselves have the best expertise to regulate further, the means to realising a regulatory end-goal are rather outsourced to the state.Footnote 71 Such mode of regulation avoids the parity of obligations in favour of a flexible approach to performance. As a result, broader participation in treaty and customary regimes can be encouraged, which in the end can lead to strengthening branches of international law and the creation of customary international law in the long term.Footnote 72

Clearly, there are advantages of using due diligence obligations in international law, yet the question remains what precisely happens when such obligations are used as a mode of regulation. To explain this, one can take the precautionary principle as an example: a state needs to take precautionary measures that can be reasonably expected to prevent environmental degradation.Footnote 73 This obligation includes two important elements when it comes to regulation, namely an aspirational norm and an implementation norm.

The ‘aspirational norm’ is inherent in a due diligence obligation and describes the aim of the regulation that needs to be realised. In the case of the precautionary principle, the regulatory aim concerns the prevention of environmental degradation. The ‘implementation norm’—also inherent in a due diligence obligation—refers to how this goal is to be achieved.Footnote 74 In the case of due diligence obligations, precise measures are commonly not prescribed by the obligation. For example, the precautionary principle does not refer to any concrete and specific measures that need to be taken, so in that regard the state has discretion when it comes to implementation. What is clear from the due diligence obligation is that a state needs to take precautionary measures which can reasonably be expected from the state. In other words, the state needs to create more concrete and specific rules and policies to reach the regulatory end-goal because the precautionary principle itself does not prescribe what these rules and policies should look like.

According to Westerman, the ‘aspirational norm’ and ‘implementation norm’ usually operate with another norm to realise outsourced law, namely a ‘reporting norm’.Footnote 75 This norm requires the norm addressee to deliver reports on the measures that have been taken and policies that have been pursued. In that way, the reporting norm pushes the norm addressee to take measures, holding the norm addressee accountable if the reports illustrate a failure to take measures to realise the regulatory end-goal.Footnote 76 However, reporting norms cannot always be found in international law—especially if the norm is not implemented in a concrete regulatory regime. In the case that no such regime is applicable, the due diligence obligation needs to be read in light of the principle of good faith. This general principle of law, after all, requires a state to perform an obligation with the genuine intention to achieve a positive result.Footnote 77 In that way, the principle of good faith supplements due diligence obligations and deploys a constitutional quality in international law, persuading states to take measures and realise a regulatory aim.Footnote 78

All in all, the employment of due diligence obligations leads to outsourced law. That is to say, further law-making and policy-making is outsourced to states and the latter need to concretise and specify the rather vague due diligence obligation. Therewith, aspects of due diligence obligations are outsourced as well. For example, the precautionary principle requires the state to take appropriate measures.Footnote 79 The term ‘appropriate’ gives the state discretion as to decide how to reach the regulatory end-goal. Put differently, the state has to conduct a balancing exercise and determine which measures are reasonable to take depending on the circumstances of a given case.Footnote 80 That way, the due diligence obligation requires a state to give further meaning to the abstract notion of reasonableness and, henceforth, an element of due diligence is outsourced to the state.Footnote 81

3.3 Accountability and Regulation: Two Different Paradigms

Clearly, due diligence obligations can be qualified as both ‘obligations of conduct’ and ‘obligations of result’, depending on the lens through which one analyses the obligation. If due diligence obligations are analysed to hold a state accountable, the obligation would be understood as an ‘obligation of conduct’. However, if the obligation is to be analysed as a mode of regulation, the term ‘obligation of result’ is used. Important is that this does not refer to an obligation of result as known in civil law to hold the norm addressee accountable. Instead, a completely different meaning is given to the term from a regulatory perspective. Due diligence obligations therefore operate in two paradigms at the same time. First, a due diligence obligation operates in an ‘accountability paradigm’. In this paradigm, the civil law dichotomy is used as an axiom in the context of risk management. At the same time, a due diligence obligation operates in a ‘regulation paradigm’, where Westerman’s dichotomy is used in the context of outsourced law. As the terms ‘obligation of conduct’ and ‘obligation of result’ are given an entirely different meaning in this paradigm, there is in fact no construction of due diligence obligations opposite to the civil law dichotomy. Instead, a completely different axiom is used in this paradigm. To explain this, one can compare a due diligence obligation with the phenomenon of ambiguous images.

An ambiguous image contains multiple figures, creating an ambiguity that leads to the phenomenon of multistability in perception.Footnote 82 As such, a competition between interpretations of one single image arises. A classic example is the duck-rabbit illusion.Footnote 83 While the image contains both a duck and a rabbit, one cannot observe both a duck and a rabbit at the same time. One perceives either a duck or a rabbit, depending on the construction made by the viewer. Exactly the same applies to the understanding of due diligence obligations. On the one hand, one can analyse a due diligence obligation in the accountability paradigm using the civil law dichotomy to determine the performance of a state’s due diligence obligation. On the other hand, one can analyse a due diligence obligation in the regulation paradigm using Westerman’s dichotomy with the rationale of outsourcing law-making. Having said that, one can speak of two paradigms that exist at the same time, yet one shifts from one paradigm to the other.Footnote 84

Altogether, the accountability paradigm and regulation paradigm form a working model of due diligence obligations in this study. In this model, due diligence obligations operate in the two paradigms at the same time, yet the elements of due diligence function differently in each of these paradigms.Footnote 85 Important is that the civil law dichotomy functions as an axiom in the accountability paradigm, while Westerman’s dichotomy serves as an axiom in the regulation paradigm (see Table 1). Using such a working model, then, makes it possible to categorise and clarify the elements of due diligence much better, which ultimately contributes to a better understanding of due diligence in international law. As for now, this article will give no further meaning to this model nor will it expand upon this model. Instead, it will use the working model as a theoretical foundation for the comparison of due diligence obligations in international environmental law and international human rights law, in particular the Paris Agreement and the ECHR.Footnote 86

Table 1 Accountability paradigm and regulation paradigm of due diligence obligations

4 Due Diligence Under the Paris Agreement and the ECHR

Contemporary climate change mitigation is primarily regulated by the UN climate change regime. Central to this regime are its three key international legal instruments: the 1992 UNFCCC,Footnote 87 the Kyoto Protocol to the United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change (Kyoto Protocol)Footnote 88 and the Paris Agreement.Footnote 89 Collectively, these treaties form the core instruments for regulating the management of climate change. Whereas the 1992 UNFCCC forms the foundation for action and establishes an institutional framework, the Kyoto Protocol and the Paris Agreement are attempts to provide further substance to the obligations of the states parties.Footnote 90

The Paris Agreement aims to enhance the implementation of the 1992 UNFCCC and to reach the underlying end-goal of the latter, namely responding to the threat of climate change.Footnote 91 The Paris Agreement does this by setting out its aims and the ‘long-term temperature goal’ in Article 2(1).Footnote 92 This provision needs to be read in conjunction with Article 4(1) Paris Agreement, which operationalises the long-term temperature goal.Footnote 93 Central to achieving the objectives of the Paris Agreement are NDCs under Article 4(2) Paris Agreement. These entail efforts by each party to the Agreement to reduce national emissions and to adapt to the consequences of climate change.Footnote 94 After every five years, states need to communicate an NDC, which is subsequently registered by the Secretariat.Footnote 95 The underlying idea is that the parties to the Paris Agreement determine the goals related to climate change mitigation themselves and, at the same time, are obliged to undertake their best efforts to reach these goals. Such efforts are expected to reflect the highest ambitions to mitigate climate change and to illustrate a progression over time.Footnote 96 As Bodansky, Brunnée, Rajamani and Voigt note, the duty to undertake such efforts can be best qualified as a due diligence obligation. Each party, after all, is individually required to pursue domestic measures, such as the development of domestic laws, to achieve the objective of their own mitigation NDC.Footnote 97

In the context of environmental pollution, obligations of a similar type can be found under the ECHR—albeit that these are commonly known as positive obligations.Footnote 98 As Stoyanova observes, the European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR) does not generally use the standard of due diligence to hold the norm addressee of a positive obligation accountable. This is especially the case when it comes to more concretised obligations, such as the obligation to criminalise and the obligation to investigate.Footnote 99 With that in mind, it would not be appropriate to qualify all positive obligations under the ECHR as due diligence obligations. Strasbourg case law related to Article 8 ECHR, however, supports the idea that the general duty to protect human rights in the context of environmental pollution can be best qualified as a due diligence obligation.Footnote 100 A state, for example, can be held responsible for having failed to regulate a private industry as it has an obligation to take reasonable and appropriate measures to secure the rights protected by Article 8 ECHR.Footnote 101 Put differently, ‘a state must take due diligence into account in its policy’.Footnote 102 In the end, authorities cannot ensure that absolutely no human rights violations occur or that such human rights violations will always be prevented. At the same time, a state cannot stand by idly while a person’s private life, family life and/or home is negatively affected due to environmental pollution. Accordingly, the duty to protect these rights under Article 8 ECHR puts emphasis on the measures to be taken by the state and not the achievement of the complete protection of human rights. This obligation, therefore, can be best described as a due diligence obligation as well.Footnote 103 As noted by Shelton and Gould, such a classification is most appropriate as the notion of due diligence lies somewhere between the extremes of always guaranteeing absolute protection and doing nothing.Footnote 104

As international environmental law and international human rights law provide rich sources for comparative experiences, this Section will compare the operation of due diligence obligations under Article 4(2) Paris Agreement with the operation of positive obligations related to the right to respect for private life, family life and the home under Article 8 ECHR. In this regard, a number of units of comparison will be discussed. At first sight, appropriate units of comparison would be the parameters that influence a state’s performance of its due diligence obligations. Early judicial practice has identified numerous legal benchmarks capable of influencing the application of the notion of due diligence in international law.Footnote 105 These include the foreseeability of harm or the risk thereof,Footnote 106 the interest at stake,Footnote 107 the capacity of the stateFootnote 108 and effective control by the state.Footnote 109 Nevertheless, this article will not analyse these parameters as much has already been written about these elements of due diligence.Footnote 110 Instead, three core elements of due diligence obligations will be compared in this study, namely the ‘character of the obligation’, ‘reasonableness’ and ‘good faith’.

Section 4.1 will first discuss the character of the obligations. This is important as the nature of human rights obligations under international human rights law is somewhat different from the nature of obligations under general international law. A comparison of the character of the obligations makes it also possible to compare due diligence obligations under the Paris Agreement with positive obligations under the ECHR through the lens of the accountability paradigm and regulation paradigm. Section 4.2 will compare the elements of reasonableness and good faith under the Paris Agreement and the ECHR in the accountability paradigm. These two elements have been selected for this study as they operate not only in the accountability paradigm, but also in the regulation paradigm. Finally, Sect. 4.3 will compare the operation of these two core elements of due diligence obligations under the Paris Agreement and the ECHR in the regulation paradigm.

4.1 Character of the Obligation: Reciprocity and Special Character

Due diligence obligations can be found in various branches of international law, yet their character can be qualified differently. Historically, due diligence obligations were created by consent between sovereign equals. Examples are the obligation to provide protection to foreigners and their properties, and the obligation to protect the interests and rights of other states.Footnote 111 These obligations were based on reciprocity, meaning that a legal relationship between two or more states exists under international law. As a result, particular behaviour by one party is dependent upon that of another party.Footnote 112 Obligations under general international law are mutual and one obligation constitutes an exchange for another.Footnote 113

The reciprocal character of international obligations has a particular impact on treaties. The main idea is that treaties are freely concluded based on the sovereign equality of states and, hence, embody a mutual exchange of benefits or lay down uniformity for future behaviour.Footnote 114 For example, the 1992 UNFCCC, the Kyoto Protocol and the Paris Agreement establish reciprocal rights and obligations among the state parties. In this respect, due diligence obligations related to the NDCs under the Paris Agreement operate vis-à-vis other parties to the treaty. If the obligation is breached, other states can hold the breaching state internationally responsible for violating international law.Footnote 115

Positive obligations related to Article 8 ECHR, however, do not fit this model. The idea is that obligations under international human rights law deal with obligations of states towards individuals and collective groups as human rights holders, rather than obligations of states towards other states.Footnote 116 According to Craven, the elements of the ‘form’ and ‘function’ of a human rights obligation seem to be in conflict with each other.Footnote 117 Human rights obligations are not based on the idea of reciprocity per se. States rather express their consent to be bound by these obligations, while at the same time rights for individuals within their jurisdiction are created with which these obligations operate. This has led to conceptual and practical challenges as regards the qualification of the nature of human rights obligations under international law. As noted by Mégret, the answer to this problem lies in the ‘special character’ of the obligations under international human rights law.Footnote 118

The idea of this ‘special character’ of human rights obligations was accurately addressed by the Inter-American Court of Human Rights (IACtHR) in the Effect of Reservations Opinion. In this Advisory Opinion it was stated that

[m]odern human rights treaties in general, and the American Convention in particular, are not multilateral treaties of the traditional type concluded to accomplish the reciprocal exchange of rights for the mutual benefit of the contracting States. Their object and purpose is the protection of the basic rights of individual human beings irrespective of their nationality, both against the State of their nationality and all other contracting States. In concluding these human rights treaties, the States can be deemed to submit themselves to a legal order within which they, for the common good, assume various obligations, not in relation to other States, but towards all individuals within their jurisdiction.Footnote 119

In other words, human rights treaties regulate inter-state behaviour while at the same time they function as a framework enabling states to unilaterally commit themselves not to violate human rights within their jurisdiction.Footnote 120 As such, states commit themselves to a certain supranational standard of behaviour.Footnote 121 Human rights obligations are not to be understood as being dependent on human rights obligations of other states. In contrast, states pledge themselves to a legal order within which they assume human rights obligations towards all individuals within their jurisdiction, and where the obligations are exercised for the common good and not in relation to other states.Footnote 122 Such ‘pledges’ are legally binding and limit governmental power.Footnote 123

Related to this is another aspect of the special character of human rights obligations. Human rights obligations operate, as some suggest, in a similar way as legislative or even constitutional norms. The ECtHR, for instance, has referred to the ECHR as a ‘constitutional instrument of European public order’.Footnote 124 Reference to such a constitutional character illustrates that human rights treaty regimes operate closely in relation to regional and domestic governance structures. In Mégret’s view, international human rights attach all parties to a human rights system to a collective project that is both domestic and supranational in character.Footnote 125 Such an understanding is relevant to note as it confirms that both the Paris Agreement and the ECHR provide an institutional framework where due diligence obligations operate.Footnote 126 With that in mind, it is possible to compare the core elements of due diligence obligations through two lenses: risk management (accountability paradigm) and outsourced law (regulation paradigm).

4.2 Accountability Paradigm

As explained in Sect. 3, a due diligence obligation needs to be understood against the background of risk management in the accountability paradigm. The question remains how due diligence obligations operate in this paradigm. How is a state’s performance of a due diligence obligation determined? Numerous arbitral awards have identified factors influencing the application of due diligence in international law.Footnote 127 These parameters have to be read both individually and collectively in light of the standard of reasonableness. At the same time, the matter of good faith plays a role when it comes to the expectations of taking reasonable action. The following subsections will address these two core elements of due diligence in the accountability paradigm and compare its operation under Article 4(2) Paris Agreement with its operation under Article 8 ECHR.

4.2.1 Reasonableness and the Degree of Care

The concept of reasonableness derives from the principle of bonus pater familias, entailing that a person is obliged to exercise a particular degree of reasonable care when he affects other persons or their property.Footnote 128 International legal practice and early legal scholars used this principle to determine the degree of care that is expected from a state.Footnote 129 Generally speaking, the notion of reasonableness is the standard that is used to assess the relevant parameters influencing a state’s performance of its due diligence obligation.Footnote 130 For each individual factor, the standard of reasonableness is used to determine whether a state’s behaviour is in accordance therewith. On top of that, the notion of reasonableness is used as an overarching standard to fairly balance these parameters with each other. The parameters that influence a state’s performance of its due diligence obligation, consequently, interact with each other in one balancing exercise.Footnote 131

Consider, for instance, a developing state that has committed itself to absolute limitation targets through its NDC under Article 4(2) Paris Agreement. If this state were to undergo an unexpected decade of economic crisis and, as a result, would not able to take those measures that it initially planned, the state is likely to have less means at its disposal to reach its targets. In such a context, it would be unreasonable to expect from the state that it still has to pursue the original efforts that it originally planned; the parameter of the ‘capacity of the state’ limits the level of efforts it can pursue. Consequently, a state would likely not breach its due diligence obligation as long as it has still taken those reasonable measures at its disposal.Footnote 132 Otherwise an impossible or disproportionate burden would be imposed on the state.Footnote 133

In the context of human rights protection, the ECtHR takes a similar approach by referring to a fair balance test.Footnote 134 ECtHR case law on environmental pollution related to Article 8 ECHR, furthermore, shows that the element of reasonableness is used to fairly balance all relevant interests. An example is one of the earliest environmental cases related to Article 8 ECHR: Powell and Rayner.Footnote 135 In this case, the applicants lived under the flight path of aircraft departing from and arriving at Heathrow Airport, and claimed that the excessive levels of aircraft noise affected their lives. As such, they argued that the United Kingdom (UK) had violated Article 8 ECHR. The ECtHR agreed with the applicants as their quality of private life was affected by the noise caused by the aircraft.Footnote 136 However, the ECtHR explained that a fair balance had to be struck between the competing interests of the individual (a violation of Article 8 ECHR) and the community as a whole (economic well-being) and, with that in mind, the Court rejected the applicants’ argument. According to the Court, the balance had not been upset due to the airport being necessary for the economic well-being of the UK. The government, moreover, had taken significant regulatory measures to reduce, control and compensate for aircraft noise.Footnote 137

Another example can be found in Hatton and Others, in which the matters of Powell and Rayner were revisited.Footnote 138 For the fair balance test, the Grand Chamber eventually took several factors into consideration. These were the difficulties in establishing a policy to decline noise disturbance throughout the night,Footnote 139 the contribution of the night flights to the general economy,Footnote 140 the measures that were in place at Heathrow Airport to mitigate the effects of the noise disturbance,Footnote 141 the fact that the few people affected could move from the area without financial lossFootnote 142 and the fact that the authorities consistently monitored the situation.Footnote 143 In that regard, the Grand Chamber found that a fair balance was struck by the UK and, thus, no violation of Article 8 ECHR had taken place.Footnote 144

4.2.2 Good Faith, Precaution and the Burden of Proof

Equally important to a due diligence obligation is the notion of ‘good faith’. In the accountability paradigm, the element of good faith is inherent in the nature of a due diligence obligation. Since due diligence obligations are qualified as obligations of conduct in this paradigm, the norm addressee is expected to undertake his efforts in good faith: a state cannot act diligently when it has acted in bad faith or has knowingly refused to take any action.Footnote 145 For instance, parties to the Paris Agreement are expected to take action in good faith to the extent that their resources and capacities permit in achieving their NDCs.Footnote 146 As explained in Sect. 3, this has consequences for the burden of proof. In the case of a breach of a due diligence obligation, the burden of proof lies upon the party claiming a violation.Footnote 147 It is expected that the state undertakes efforts in good faith and, with that in mind, the party claiming a violation of the due diligence obligation must prove that the state has acted in bad faith and demonstrated negligence. However, in cases of severe environmental damage that can occur without taking measures, a state can be required to take precautionary actions even if harm has not yet materialised.Footnote 148 In that case, a state cannot hide behind the high threshold of the principle of prevention (significant and clear evidence that has to be proved by the potential injured party).Footnote 149 Instead, the precautionary principle makes it possible to lower the standard of proof for the injured party when there is a risk of severe environmental harm. As a result, the burden of proof practically shifts to the state as justified by the precautionary principle.Footnote 150

In the case of Article 4(2) Paris Agreement, such understanding is not explicitly referred to in the text of the treaty. The text itself only refers to the obligation to ‘pursue domestic mitigation measures, with the aim of achieving the objectives of such contributions’.Footnote 151 Although the Paris Agreement does not expressly refer to the precautionary principle, the provision needs to be read in the context of the UNFCCC regime as a whole.Footnote 152 With that in mind, the Paris Agreement is to be understood against the backdrop of the principles laid out in the 1992 UNFCCC, one of which is the precautionary principle.Footnote 153 The efforts that have to be taken to mitigate climate change under Article 4(2) Paris Agreement can thus be viewed as precautionary measures due to the application of Article 3(3) 1992 UNFCCC. As such, states are required to take precautionary measures at the bear minimum. The precautionary principle then lowers the standard of proof for an injured party if it holds a state party internationally responsible for breaching Article 4(2) Paris Agreement. In that way, the burden of proof practically shifts to the state, which then has to show that the risk of environmental damage will not be severe in nature.

In the context of positive obligations under Article 8 ECHR, the ECtHR has made explicit reference to the precautionary principle.Footnote 154 Accordingly, it becomes possible to consider the precautionary principle as a legal basis for lowering the standard of proof for the injured party. The Court, however, has never explicitly referred to the principle as a justification for lowering the standard of proof for the injured party in relation to positive obligations under Article 8 ECHR. What it could have done in its case law on environmental pollution was to refer to Article 31(3)(c) of the Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties (VCLT).Footnote 155 The precautionary principle as expressed in Article 3(3) 1992 UNFCCC, after all, is a relevant norm of international law that is to be interpreted ‘together with’ the context. The context is clearly that of significant environmental harm.Footnote 156

As the precautionary principle makes it possible for the ECtHR to lower the standard of proof for an injured party, the ECtHR remarkably lowers the standard of proof for the party claiming a violation to the point that the latter does not have to prove anything. The Court then acts proprio motu and directly assesses positive obligations—even if the party claiming a violation has not even referred to it. For this, an effet utile interpretation is used as the basis for the Court acting proprio motu and lowering the standard of proof for the claiming party to such an extent.Footnote 157 The state will thus have the burden to show that it had acted in good faith, implying that it is assumed that the state has acted in bad faith. Noticeably, this is rather a characteristic of an obligation of result in the accountability paradigm.Footnote 158 A due diligence obligation, in contrast, is based on the expectation that the state acts in good faith, but since the Court lowers the standard of proof for the injured party to such an extent, it is rather expected that the state has acted in bad faith. This is completely the opposite of the rationale of due diligence obligations under which it is expected that the state performs its obligations in good faith when it comes to risk management.

4.3 Regulation Paradigm

In the regulation paradigm, the notions of ‘reasonableness’ and ‘good faith’ operate in a rather different way than in the accountability paradigm. The reason for this is that these elements of due diligence have to be read in light of the level of discretion given to the state, leading to outsourced law as a mode of regulation.Footnote 159 The following subsections will explore these matters in relation to the NDCs under the Paris Agreement and the positive obligations under Article 8 ECHR.

4.3.1 Reasonableness, Discretion and Margin of Appreciation

As the Seabed Mining Advisory Opinion noted, a due diligence obligation requires its norm addressee to take measures which are ‘reasonably appropriate’.Footnote 160 Nonetheless, such an open-ended and vague formulation requires an evaluation of what can be expected from a state. Such an assessment is affected by the flexibility of due diligence obligations. States have choices of means that they can employ when they are expected to take reasonable measures. Due diligence obligations, accordingly, provide a certain amount of discretion to a state in deciding which precise measure can be taken in order to fulfil its obligation.Footnote 161 In the end, the obligation does not provide a predefined list of measures that need to be taken. This would cut against the grain of state sovereignty and the decentralised nature of international law.Footnote 162 Instead, due diligence obligations are flexible, and their content may change over time in light of new developments and changes to the risk involved.Footnote 163 This being said, the assessment of what entails a reasonable measure, in fact, is outsourced to the states, leaving to them to decide what is reasonable.Footnote 164

A perfect example illustrating this is the matter of the NDCs under the Paris Agreement. According to Article 4(2) Paris Agreement, states have a duty to pursue domestic mitigation measures with the aim of achieving the objectives of such contributions. Accordingly, it is expected that the efforts by a state will represent a progression over time. The state, however, has discretion as regards the nature of these efforts and how these will represent progression over time.Footnote 165 In that way, states have to determine the most appropriate measures to be taken in conformity with their due diligence obligation. In other words, the element of reasonableness is outsourced to the states. The Paris Agreement takes it even one step further. States do not only have significant discretion in light of the measures they can take. They also have discretion when it comes to setting the targets that need to be reached with the measures taken. In that way, the NDCs are self-selected.Footnote 166 Although states are clearly left with a great amount of discretion, this is not ultimately what determines which measures are reasonable. The Paris Agreement includes normative expectations (‘progression’, ‘highest possible ambition’ and ‘leadership’) which provide a minimum direction to states performing their due diligence obligations related to their NDCs. As such, an assessment of the degree of care required by states is guided by an ‘elaborate tapestry of normative expectations placed on states’.Footnote 167

Under the ECHR, the discretion that states have in choosing the necessary means has also been acknowledged. In an attempt to balance national views of human rights with a uniform application of the ECHR, the ECtHR has developed what is known as the margin of appreciation.Footnote 168 The margin of appreciation lays down a minimum standard that is to be achieved, whilst particular specificities of a particular state need to be taken into account.Footnote 169 The implementation of human rights obligations, after all, requires an adaptation to several aspects, such as the history, political, social and cultural specificities of a state.Footnote 170 Accordingly, the margin of appreciation is to be understood against the backdrop of the lack of an absolute uniform implementation in the European context. As the parties to the ECHR are the ones closest to the social field that needs to be regulated, the rationale for the margin of appreciation is that states are better suited to make assessments of which measures need to be taken.Footnote 171 In that way, it has been argued that the margin of appreciation is rooted in the principle of subsidiarity.Footnote 172

In the context of environmental pollution and positive obligations under Article 8 ECHR, the margin of appreciation operates closely with the fair balance test. In that regard, it is possible to consider the notion of reasonableness as the other side of the margin of appreciation: the more intense the fair balance test is exercised by the Court, the narrower the margin of appreciation of the state becomes.Footnote 173 For instance, in Guerra and Others the ECtHR examined whether necessary steps had been taken by Italy to ensure the effective protection of the applicants’ right to respect for their private and family life due to environmental pollution from a nearby waste treatment plant.Footnote 174 In this respect, the essential information that would have been necessary was not given to the applicants.Footnote 175 The Court clearly applied the standard of reasonableness to these procedural matters and gradually narrowed down the abstract positive obligation so that in the end only one measure would have been sufficiently effective.Footnote 176 As there would be no room for any ‘middle-ground’, no reference to the margin of appreciation was even made by the Court.Footnote 177 In the end, the state had failed to take this measure and thus the ECtHR concluded that there had been a violation of Article 8 ECHR.Footnote 178

Nevertheless, a state might have a wide margin of appreciation depending on the process of balancing the individual rights involved as protected by Article 8 ECHR and countervailing interests, like economic well-being.Footnote 179 For example, Powell and Rayner and Hatton and Others demonstrate that the Court acknowledges a wide margin of appreciation.Footnote 180 However, where nuisance exceeds reasonable levels, the Strasbourg Court instead intensifies the standard of reasonableness to override a state’s margin of appreciation.Footnote 181 In view of this, the Court still engages in its own review of the merits and occasionally determines what would be reasonable without restraining itself from rigorous judicial scrutiny. If the matter of discretion were to be given sincere meaning, the fair balance test would actually be outsourced to the state as is done under the Paris Agreement. Since this does not seem to be the case in some situations for the ECHR, the margin of appreciation might be considered as a gesture to balance deference to state sovereignty with the Court’s supervision of effective human rights protection.Footnote 182

4.3.2 Good Faith and Reporting

As the ILA Study Group on Due Diligence in International Law has noted, ‘[a] state cannot be considered to have acted diligently when the state has acted in bad faith or has knowingly refused to take any measures whatsoever’.Footnote 183 From a regulatory perspective this is relevant, especially with respect to pushing and realising states to take action. As explained in Sect. 3, a due diligence obligation contains two regulatory elements, namely an aspirational norm and an implementation norm.Footnote 184 However, without a third aspect that pushes the norm addressee to take actual action, the due diligence obligation would only refer to an aspiration and nothing more than a minimum of ‘try and do something’ would be expressed in that way.Footnote 185 The actual realisation of the aspiration of the obligation cannot be guaranteed due to the great amount of discretion given to states. In this respect, the notion of good faith fills this gap and pushes states to realise the regulatory aim of a due diligence obligation.Footnote 186 That way, good faith ‘deploys a certain kind of constitutional quality within the international law scheme and beyond that is conceived to be the very foundation of all law’.Footnote 187

According to Rajamani, the notion of good faith influences the nature and extent of due diligence obligations under the Paris Agreement.Footnote 188 The good faith expectation related to the NDCs, however, is further supplemented by more concrete procedural obligations that can be qualified as reporting norms. As explained in Sect. 3, these norms require the state to deliver reports on the measures that have been taken and policies that have been pursued, but can even require the states to account for future plans that they have developed.Footnote 189 For instance, the ambition cycle of the NDCs requires states to communicate their NDC in which they are expected to show progression every five years.Footnote 190 Such a concrete procedural obligation supplements the open-ended due diligence obligation under Article 4(2) Paris Agreement and ensures that the Conference of Parties (COP) can supervise whether states have made serious efforts to reach their self-determined goals. As a result, a compliance relationship between the COP and the Parties to the Paris Agreement is created, meaning that the state is propelled to reach its self-determined regulatory goal within five years. If it fails to do so, it can be held accountable. With that in mind, compliance and further progression is to be realised.

While the due diligence obligation under Article 4(2) Paris Agreement is supplemented by concrete procedural obligations, such is not the case for positive obligations related to Article 8 ECHR. In the human rights context, the idea of state sovereignty and diverse cultural, social and legal traditions of each state party lead to difficulties related to supervision by the ECtHR and the identification of a unified standard of human rights. Arai-Takahashi accordingly considers that ‘the enforcement of the Strasbourg organs’ undertaking ultimately depends on the good faith and continuing cooperation of the contracting states’ since ‘[t]he Convention’s enforcement system depends on the mandate and consent of member states’.Footnote 191 Considering this, the ECtHR has arguably developed the margin of appreciation out of necessity to balance the devotion to both state sovereignty and the supervision of human rights.Footnote 192 This implies that the ECHR provides a minimum standard of human rights protection.Footnote 193 Insofar as national authorities comply with this standard of protection, they have discretion when choosing the necessary means and assessing the impact that a measure can have on their citizens.Footnote 194 This discretion, however, is not supplemented by more procedural obligations which push the state towards realising the aspiration set out by positive obligations under the ECHR. To that extent, the due diligence obligations under the Paris Agreement operate in a stronger regulatory framework than the positive obligations under the ECHR (Table 2).

Table 2 Comparing the NDCs under the Paris Agreement with positive obligations under the ECHR

5 Conclusions, Reflection and Further Research

From the present study, it can be concluded that the core elements of due diligence obligations concern ‘reasonableness’ and ‘good faith’. These notions operate in both the accountability paradigm and regulation paradigm (see Fig. 1). Moreover, a reflection on the present comparative study illustrates that due diligence in the context of climate change mitigation is a qualifier of behaviour attached to obligations that can be found in two separate legal frameworks: the Paris Agreement and the ECHR. With that in mind, the due diligence that has to be exercised by a state needs to be understood in a systemic way. Attaching due diligence to only one obligation under one legal framework would result in due diligence not being truly effective. The operation of the obligations under both the Paris Agreement and the ECHR, after all, has its strengths and weaknesses. However, when reading due diligence in a holistic manner the weaknesses of an obligation in one regime are rectified by the strengths of an obligation in the other.

Fig. 1
figure 1

A working model for due diligence and its ‘core elements’

For instance, under the ECHR the margin of appreciation of a state can be overridden by the employment of a strict standard of reasonableness by the Court, while at the same time the aspiration element of a positive obligation under the ECHR significantly depends on good faith instead of concrete reporting norms. In that way, states are less pushed towards the realisation of the regulatory end-goal and the implementation thereof. At the same time, states are given a great amount of discretion under the Paris Agreement, contributing to more treaty participation and universal action against climate change. This does not mean that states have unlimited discretion as regards taking ‘any action’ or acting in the name of ‘just doing something’. A strong institutional framework of the UNFCCC regime and several procedural obligations, after all, push towards the implementation of the due diligence obligations under the Paris Agreement.Footnote 195 As such, the lack of procedural obligations under the ECHR to realise the degree of care that needs to be exercised by a state is covered by the regulatory operation of due diligence obligations under the Paris Agreement, which includes more concrete procedural obligations. To that extent, the Paris Agreement provides significant meaning to the regulatory component of due diligence in climate change mitigation.Footnote 196

In contrast, the component of risk management is much more developed under the ECHR, especially when it comes to the assessment of reasonableness. Case law by the ECtHR points out that the Strasbourg Court employs the standard of reasonableness. As such, more guidance for the determination of what an ‘appropriate measure’ means has been provided by the Court. However, under the Paris Agreement the balancing exercise determining an appropriate measure is completely outsourced to the states. With that in mind, further concretisation and specification of an ‘appropriate’ measure depends on state practice that must be developed. Currently, it is difficult to assert whether a uniform standard for assessing ‘reasonableness’ has developed in relation to the NDCs under the Paris Agreement. However, against the backdrop of the ECHR a clearer picture of what an ‘appropriate measure’ entails is provided. Therefore, it can be said that the accountability paradigm of due diligence is further operationalised by the ECtHR.Footnote 197

In conclusion, the operation of due diligence obligations in international environmental law and international human rights law have implications for systemic issues in international law.Footnote 198 In the end, a state is required to exercise due diligence and take appropriate measure to mitigate climate change. The obligations to which this qualifier of behaviour is attached can be found in multiple branches of international law, interacting with each other. Furthermore, the working model of due diligence obligations as constructed in this study illustrates that these types of obligations have two functions: one related to risk management and the other related to a mode of regulation.Footnote 199 There are good prospects for using such a working model in international law as it makes it possible to shed light on new perspectives regarding the legal entitlements of subjects of international law.Footnote 200 Moreover, this working model can further clarify the operation and impact of due diligence in numerous branches of international law.Footnote 201 For instance, elements of a due diligence obligation other than ‘reasonableness’ and ‘good faith’ might operate in both the accountability paradigm and the regulation paradigm or only in one.Footnote 202 All in all, the rise of due diligence cannot be denied and, on that note, it is crucial to conduct further studies on this familiar stranger in international law.