Skip to main content
Log in

Basic Quasi-Boolean Expansions of Relevance Logics

  • Published:
Journal of Philosophical Logic Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The basic quasi-Boolean negation (QB-negation) expansions of relevance logics included in Anderson and Belnap’s relevance logic R are defined. We consider two types of QB-negation: H-negation and D-negation. The former one is of paraintuitionistic or superintuitionistic character, the latter one, of dual intuitionistic nature in some sense. Logics endowed with H-negation are paracomplete; logics with D-negation are paraconsistent. All logics defined in the paper are given a Routley-Meyer ternary relational semantics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  1. Anderson, A.R., & Belnap, N. D. Jr. (1975). Entailment. The logic of relevance and necessity Vol. II. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Anderson, A.R., Belnap, N.D. Jr., & Dunn, J.M. (1992). Entailment, The logic of relevance and necessity Vol. I. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Avron, A. (1991). Natural 3-valued logics –characterization and proof theory. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 56(1), 276–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Białynicki-Birula, H. A., & Rasiowa, H. (1957). On the representation of quasi-Boolean algebras. Bulletin de l’Académie Polonaise des Sciences, Classe III, Bd., 5, 259–261.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Bimbó, K., & Dunn, J.M. (2008). Generalized Galois logics Vol. 188. Stanford: CSLI.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Bimbó, K., & Dunn, J.M. (2017). The emergence of set-theoretical semantics for relevance logics around 1970. In Bimbó, K., & Dunn, J. M. (Eds.) Proceedings of the Third Workshop, 16-17, May 2016, Edmonton, Canada. IfCoLog Journal of Logics and their Applications, 4(3), 357–389.

  7. Brady, R.T. (1992). Hierarchical semantics for relevant logics. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 21(4), 357–374. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00260741.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Brady, R.T. (Ed.). (2003). Relevant logics and their rivals, Vol. II. Aldershot: Ashgate.

  9. Brady, R.T. (2006). Universal logic. Stanford: CSLI.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Cattaneo, G., Ciucci, D., & Dubois, D. (2011). Algebraic models of deviant modal operators based on de Morgan and Kleene lattices. Information Sciences, 181(19), 4075–4100. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.ins.2011.05.008.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Dunn, J.M. (1982). A relational representation of quasi-Boolean algebras. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 23(4), 353–357.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Dunn, J.M. (1991). Gaggle theory: An abstraction of Galois connections and residuation, with applications to negation, implication, and various logical operators. In van Eijck, J. (Ed.) Logics in AI. https://doi.org/10.1007/BFb0018431 (pp. 31–51): Springer.

  13. Dunn, J.M., & Hardegree, G. (2001). Algebraic methods in philosophical logic. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Dunn, J., & Restall, G. (2002). Relevance logic. In Gabbay, D., & Guenthner, F. (Eds.) Handbook of Philosophical Logic: Kluwer.

  15. González, C. (2011). MaTest. https://sites.google.com/site/sefusmendez/matest (last Accessed May 12 2020).

  16. Hacking, I. (1963). What is Strict Implication? Journal of Symbolic Logic, 28(1), 51–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Meyer, R.K., & Routley, R. (1973). Classical relevant logics. I. Studia Logica, 32(1), 51–66. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02123812.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Meyer, R.K., & Routley, R. (1974). Classical relevant logics II. Studia Logica, 33(2), 183–194. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02120493.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. Meyer, R.K., Giambrone, S., & Brady, R.T. (1984). Where gamma fails. Studia Logica, 43, 247–256. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02429841.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Rasiowa, H. (1974). An algebraic approach to non-classical logics Vol. 78. Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Robles, G. (2013). Admissibility of Ackermann’s rule δ in relevant logics. Logic and Logical Philosophy, 22(4). https://doi.org/10.12775/LLP.2013.018.

  22. Robles, G. (2016). The quasi-relevant 3-valued logic RM3 and some of its sublogics lacking the variable-sharing property. Reports on Mathematical Logic, 51. https://doi.org/10.4467/20842589RM.16.008.5285.

  23. Robles, G., & Méndez, J.M. (2018). Routley-Meyer ternary relational semantics for intuitionistic-type negations. New York: Elsevier. ISBN: 9780081007518.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Robles, G., & Méndez, J.M. (2019). Belnap-Dunn semantics for natural implicative expansions of Kleene’s strong three-valued matrix with two designated values. Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics, 29(1), 37–63. https://doi.org/10.1080/11663081.2018.1534487.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. Routley, R., Meyer, R.K., Plumwood, V., & Brady R.T. (1982). Relevant logics and their rivals Vol. 1. Atascadero: Ridgeview Publishing Co.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Slaney, J.K. (1995). MaGIC, Matrix Generator for Implication Connectives: Version 2.1, Notes and Guide. Canberra: Australian National University. http://users.cecs.anu.edu.au/jks/magic.html.

  27. Sylvan, R. (1990). Variations on da Costa C systems and dual-intuitionistic logics I. Analyses of Cω and CCω. Studia Logica, 49(1), 47–65. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00401553.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  28. Sylvan, R., & Plumwood, V. (2003). Non-normal relevant logics. In R. Brady (Ed.) Relevant logics and their rivals. Ashgate, Aldershot and Burlington: Western Philosophy Series, (Vol. II pp. 10–16).

Download references

Acknowledgements

This work is supported by the Spanish Ministry of Economy, Industry and Competitiveness under Grant [FFI2017-82878-P]. - We sincerely thank two anonymous referees of the Journal of Philosophical Logic for their comments and suggestions on a previous draft of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gemma Robles.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Appendices

Appendix: A

The following sets of truth-tables t1-t13 are used to prove some claims made throughout the paper (designated values are starred). Let L be a logic defined upon the language \({\mathscr{L}}\) (cf. Definitions 2.1 and 2.2), Γ a set of wffs and A a wff of \({\mathscr{L}}\). On the other hand, let t be a set of truth-tables and v an assignment to the propositional variables of \({\mathscr{L}}\) built upon t. v verifies A if it assigns a designated value to A; and v verifies the rule ΓA if it assigns a designated value to A, provided it assigns a designated value to each BΓ. Then, t verifes L if every assignment v verifies all axioms and rules of L. The sets t1-t13 have been found by using MaGIC (cf. [26]; each set of tables is the simpler one justifying the respective claim). (In case a tester is needed, the reader can use that in [15].) In what follows, p,q and r are distinct propositional variables.

figure a

This set verifies all axioms and rules of RM3+ (i.e., B+ plus b2, b4, b6, b7 and b8. Cf. Definitions 2.4 and 2.7) plus A7-A10 and Con\(\sim \), but falsifies A11: \(v[(p\rightarrow q)\rightarrow (\sim q\rightarrow \sim p)]=0\) for any assignment v such that v(p) = v(q) = 2.

figure b

t2 verifies RM3+ plus A7, A8 and Con\(\sim \) but falsifies A10: \(v(\sim \sim p\rightarrow p)=0\) for any assignment v such that v(p) = 0.

figure c

t3 verifies classical propositional logic C and A12, A13, A15, A16, A18, A19-A21, A23 and A24 but falsifies A14 and A22: \(v[p\rightarrow \lbrack q\rightarrow \lnot (r\wedge \lnot r)]]=0\) for any assignment v such that v(p) = v(q) = v(r) = 1; and \(v[p\rightarrow \lbrack \overset {\bullet }{\lnot } (r\wedge \overset {\bullet }{\lnot }r)\rightarrow q]]=0\) for any assignment such that v(p) = 1 and v(q) = v(r) = 0.

figure d

t4 verifies the logic G (i.e., B plus the PEM axiom \(A\vee \sim A\)) plus A12, A13, A15, A17-A20, A22, A24, Con\(\lnot \) and Con\(\overset {\bullet }{ \lnot }\) but falsifies A14 and A21: \(v[p\rightarrow \lbrack q\rightarrow \lnot (r\wedge \lnot r)]]=v[p\rightarrow \lbrack q\rightarrow (r\vee \overset { \bullet }{\lnot }r)]]=0\) for any assignment v such that v(p) = v(q) = v(r) = 3.

figure e

The tables for \(\wedge ,\vee ,\sim ,\lnot \) and \(\overset {\bullet }{\lnot }\) are the same as in t4.

t5 verifies the logic G plus A12-A14, A17-A21, A24, Con\(\lnot \) and Con\( \overset {\bullet }{\lnot }\) but falsifies A15 and A22: \(v[p\rightarrow \lbrack (q\wedge \lnot q)\rightarrow r]]=v[p\rightarrow \lbrack \overset { \bullet }{\lnot }(r\vee \overset {\bullet }{\lnot }r)\rightarrow r]]=0\) for any assignment v such that v(p) = v(q) = v(r) = 1.

figure f

The tables for ∧,∨ and \(\sim \) are the same as in t4.

t6 verifies the logic ticket entailment T (cf. Section 2) plus A12, A13, A15-A18, but falsifies A14: \(v[p\rightarrow \lbrack q\rightarrow \lnot (r\wedge \lnot r)]]=0\) for any assignment v such that v(p) = v(q) = v(r) = 1.

figure g

The tables for \(\wedge ,\vee ,\sim ,\lnot \) and \(\overset {\bullet }{\lnot }\) are as in t4.

t7 verifies the logic E (cf. Section 2) plus T5, T8 (cf. Proposition 3.4), A12, A13, A16-A20, A23, A24, the ECQ axiom, \((A\wedge \lnot A)\rightarrow B\), and the CPEM axiom, \(B\rightarrow (A\vee \overset {\bullet }{\lnot }A)\), but falsifies A14, A15, A21 and A22: \( v[p\rightarrow \lbrack q\rightarrow \lnot (r\wedge \lnot r)]]=v[p\rightarrow \lbrack (r\wedge \lnot r)\rightarrow q]]=v[p\rightarrow \lbrack q\rightarrow (r\vee \overset {\bullet }{\lnot }r)]]=v[p\rightarrow \lbrack \overset { \bullet }{\lnot }(r\vee \overset {\bullet }{\lnot }r)\rightarrow q]]=0\) for any assignment v such that v(p) = v(q) = v(r) = 1.

figure h

t8 verifies RB, that is, the logic R plus \(A\leftrightarrow --A\), \( B\rightarrow (A\vee -A)\), \((A\wedge -A)\rightarrow B\) and Con− (i.e., \( A\rightarrow B\Rightarrow -B\rightarrow -A\)) but falsifies \((A\rightarrow B)\rightarrow (-B\rightarrow -A)\): \(v[(p\rightarrow q)\rightarrow (-q\rightarrow -p)]=0\) for any assignment v such that v(p) = 5 and v(q) = 1.

figure i

t9 verifies RM3 (cf. Section 2) plus A12-A24 but falsifies \(q\rightarrow (p\vee \lnot p)\) (for any assignment v such that v(p) = 1 and v(q) = 2) and \( (p\wedge \overset {\bullet }{\lnot }p)\rightarrow q\) (for any assignment v such that v(p) = 1 and v(q) = 0).

Also notice that \(v(\sim p\rightarrow \lnot p)=v(\overset {\bullet }{\lnot } p\rightarrow \sim p)=0\) for any assignment v such that v(p) = 1.

figure j

Tables for \(\sim ,\wedge ,\vee \) are as in t1.

t10 verifies R plus A12-A16 and A18, but falsifies A17: \(v(p\vee \lnot p)=0\) for any assignment v such that v(p) = 1.

figure k

t11 verifies R plus A12-A15, A17-A22 and A24, but falsifies A16 and A23: \( v[(p\rightarrow q)\rightarrow (\lnot q\rightarrow \lnot p)]=0\) for any assignment v such that v(p) = 2 and v(q) = 4; \(v[(p\rightarrow q)\rightarrow (\overset {\bullet }{\lnot }q\rightarrow \overset {\bullet }{ \lnot }p)]=0\) for any assignment v such that v(p) = 1 and v(q) = 3.

figure l

The tables for \(\wedge ,\vee ,\sim ,\lnot \) and \(\overset {\bullet }{\lnot }\) are as in t9.

t12 verifies the 3-valued expansion of the negationless fragment of Lewis’ modal logic S5 (cf. [16, 24] and references in the last item) plus A12-A24 but falsifies \((p\wedge \sim p)\rightarrow q\) and \((p\wedge \overset {\bullet }{\lnot }p)\rightarrow q\) (for any assignment v such that v(p) = 1 and v(q) = 0) and \(q\rightarrow (p\vee \sim p)\) and \(q\rightarrow (p\vee \lnot p)\) (for any assignment v such that v(q) = 2 and v(p) = 1).

figure m

The tables for \(\wedge ,\vee ,\sim ,\lnot \) and \(\overset {\bullet }{\lnot }\) are as in t4.

t13 verifies the logic RW (cf. Section 2) plus A12-A24 but falsifies \((\sim p\rightarrow p)\rightarrow p\), \((\lnot p\rightarrow p)\rightarrow p\) and \((\overset {\bullet }{\lnot }p\rightarrow p)\rightarrow p\) (for any assignment v such that v(p) = 2), and \((p\rightarrow \sim p)\rightarrow \sim p\), \( (p\rightarrow \lnot p)\rightarrow \lnot p\) and \((p\rightarrow \overset { \bullet }{\lnot }p)\rightarrow \overset {\bullet }{\lnot }p\) (for any assignment v such that v(p) = 1).

Appendix: B

Proposition B.1 (Ant, DNE are deriv. in FDE+ plus ECQ & CPEM)

The axiom DNE, \(--A\rightarrow A\), and the rule Ant, \((A\wedge B)\rightarrow -C\Rightarrow (A\wedge C)\rightarrow -B\) are derivable in FDE+ plus the axioms ECQ, \((A\wedge -A)\rightarrow B\), and CPEM, \(B\rightarrow (A\vee -A)\).

Proof

(Sketch)

  1. (a)

    \((A\wedge B)\rightarrow -C\Rightarrow (A\wedge C)\rightarrow -B\):

    Suppose (1) \((A\wedge B)\rightarrow -C\) (Hyp) and (2) \((C\wedge -C)\rightarrow -B\) (ECQ). By 1, 2 and FDE+, we have (3) \([(A\wedge C)\wedge B]\rightarrow -B\). On the other hand, we obviously have (4) \( [(A\wedge C)\wedge -B]\rightarrow -B\). By 3, 4 and FDE+, we get (5) \( [(A\wedge C)\wedge (B\vee -B)]\rightarrow -B\). Now, we use (6) \(C\rightarrow (B\vee -B)\) (CPEM), whence we obtain (7) \([(A\wedge C)\wedge (A\wedge C)]\rightarrow \lbrack (A\wedge C)\wedge (B\vee -B)]\). Finally, by 5, 7 and FDE+, we get (8) \((A\wedge C)\rightarrow -B\), as was to be proved.

  2. (b)

    \(--A\rightarrow A\):

    We have (1) \(--A\rightarrow (A\vee -A)\) (CPEM). By 1 and FDE+, we have (2) \((--A\wedge --A)\rightarrow \lbrack (--A\wedge A)\vee (--A\wedge -A]\). We use now (3) \((--A\wedge -A)\rightarrow A\) (ECQ). By 3 and FDE+, we get (4) \([(--A\wedge A)\vee (--A\wedge -A)]\rightarrow A\). Finally, by 2, 4 and FDE+, we have (5) \(--A\rightarrow A\), as was to be proved.

Proposition B.2 (Non-independence of A15 and A21)

A15 (resp., A21) is derivable from DW plus A12-A14, A18 and Con\(\lnot \) (resp., A19, A20, A22, A24 and Con\(\overset {\bullet }{\lnot }\)) (cf. Section 2 on the logic DW).

Proof

(a) A15: By A18, we have (1) \(\lnot (C\wedge \lnot C)\rightarrow \sim (C\wedge \lnot C)\), whence by A14, we get (2) \(A\rightarrow \lbrack \sim B\rightarrow \sim (C\wedge \lnot C)]\). Then, by A11, (3) \(A\rightarrow \lbrack \sim \sim (C\wedge \lnot C)\rightarrow \sim \sim B]\) follows. Finally, (4) \(A\rightarrow \lbrack (C\wedge \lnot C)\rightarrow B]\) is derivable by A9 and A10. (b) The proof of A21 is similar. □

Proposition B.3 (Non-independence of A14)

A14 is derivable from the logic E (cf. Section 2) plus A12, A13 and A15-A18.

Proof

Firstly, the derivability of \(B\rightarrow \lnot (A\wedge \lnot A)\) is proved. We use the rule assertion, \(A\Rightarrow (A\rightarrow B)\rightarrow B\), admissible in E (cf. [21]).

We have (1) \(B\rightarrow \lbrack \lnot C\rightarrow \lnot (A\wedge \lnot A)] \) and (2) \(B\rightarrow \lbrack \lnot \lnot C\rightarrow \lnot (A\wedge \lnot A)]\) by A15 and A16. Then, (3) \(B\rightarrow \lbrack (\lnot C\vee \lnot \lnot C)\rightarrow \lnot (A\wedge \lnot A)]\) is provable by the E∨ axiom (A5 of B+ —cf. Definition 2.4). Next, (4) \([(\lnot C\vee \lnot \lnot C)\rightarrow \lnot (A\wedge \lnot A)]\rightarrow \lnot (A\wedge \lnot A)\) follows by the rule assertion and A17. Finally, we get (5) \( B\rightarrow \lnot (A\wedge \lnot A)\) from (3) and (4).

Once \(B\rightarrow \lnot (A\wedge \lnot A)\) is proved, \(A\rightarrow \lnot \lnot A\) is derivable from this thesis and \((A\wedge \lnot A)\rightarrow \lnot \lnot A\), similarly as \(--A\rightarrow A\) is demonstrated with \( --A\rightarrow (A\vee -A)\) and \((--A\wedge -A)\rightarrow A\) in Proposition Appendix.1. Finally, A14 follows from \(C\rightarrow \lbrack (\lnot \lnot B\rightarrow \lnot (A\wedge \lnot A)]\) (cf. (2) above) and \(B\rightarrow \lnot \lnot B\). □

Paraconsistency and paracompleteness

Let L be a logic, the negation operator \(\overset {\square }{\lnot }\) being one of its connectives; and let a be an L-theory. a is \(\overset {\square }{\lnot }\)-inconsistent if \(A\wedge \overset {\square }{\lnot }A\in a\), for some wff A; and a is \(\overset {\square }{\lnot }\)-complete if Aa or \(\overset {\square }{\lnot }A\in a\) for every wff A. Then, L is \(\overset {\square }{\lnot }\)-paraconsistent if there is at least one \(\overset { \square }{\lnot }\)-inconsistent regular L-theory which is not trivial; and L is \(\overset {\square }{\lnot }\)-paracomplete if there is at least one (non-trivial) prime and regular L-theory which is not complete (notice that if a is a non-trivial regular and \(\overset {\square }{\lnot }\) -inconsistent L-theory, in general, it is not difficult to extend a to a prime theory with the same properties).

We prove Propositions Appendix.4 and Appendix.5.

Proposition B.4 (RD s is \(\protect \overset {\bullet }{\lnot }\) -paraconsistent)

The logic RDs is R (cf. Section 2) plus A19-A24. Then, any logic L included in RDs is \(\overset {\bullet }{\lnot }\)-paraconsistent.

Proof

Let p,q be different propositional variables. Consider the set z = {B∣ ⊩LA & \(\vdash _{\text {L}}[A\wedge (p\wedge \overset { \bullet }{\lnot }p)]\rightarrow B\}\). It is easy to show that z is a regular L-theory and that it is \(\overset {\bullet }{\lnot }\)-inconsistent. Anyway, z is not trivial. Consider t9 (in Appendix Appendix) and any assignment v defined on the set {0, 1, 2} such that v(p) = 1 and v(q) = 0. Clearly, \(v[A\wedge (p\wedge \overset {\bullet }{\lnot }p)]=1\) but \(v[[A\wedge (p\wedge \overset {\bullet }{\lnot }p)]\rightarrow q]=0\), whence by the soundness theorem of RDs (cf. Theorem 5.12) we get \(\nvdash _{\text {RD}_{\text {s}}}[A\wedge (p\wedge \overset {\bullet }{\lnot } p)]\rightarrow q\). Consequently, qz. Then, we apply Lemma 6.16 and there is a prime, regular and non-trivial L-theory x such that \(z\subseteq x\) but qx. Therefore, x is \(\overset {\bullet }{\lnot }\) -inconsistent, but not trivial. □

Proposition B.5 (RHs is \(\lnot \)-paracomplete)

The logic RHs is R (cf. Section 2) plus A12-A16 and A18. Then, any logic L included in RHs is \(\lnot \)-paracomplete.

Proof

Similar to (but simpler than) that of Proposition Appendix.4, now using t10 in Appendix Appendix. □

On strong completeness (see [25] and [8])

In Theorem 6.19, a weak completeness theorem is proved for all the QB-logics defined in the paper. Regarding strong completeness, in the context of RM-semantics, we need prime theories closed under all primitive rules of the logic in question. Unfortunately, in general, it is not possible to build up prime L-theories closed under all primitive rules of inference of a QB-logic L if it lacks the MP axiom, \([A\wedge (A\rightarrow B)]\rightarrow B\), or has other primitive rules of inference in addition to MP and Adj. Nevertheless, the required prime L-theories are definable, provided the disjunctive version or the thesis corresponding to each primitive rule of inference of L is added. For instance, suppose Modus Tollens (MT), \( A\rightarrow B\And \lnot B\Rightarrow \lnot A\), is a primitive rule of inference of L. Then, the disjunctive version of MT is \(C\vee (A\rightarrow B)\And C\vee \lnot B\Rightarrow C\vee \lnot A\); and, of course, the corresponding thesis to MT is \([(A\rightarrow B)\wedge \lnot B]\rightarrow \lnot A\). Consequently, a strong completeness theorem for a QB-logic L is available if (a) L has no primitive rules of inference other than Adj and MP and the MP axiom is an L-theorem, or (b) L has the disjunctive version or the corresponding thesis to each one of its primitive rules of inference.

In addition, it has to be noted that if the required prime theories are available, then a reduced RM1-semantics, preferable when possible to the unreduced version, can be defined.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Robles, G., Méndez, J.M. Basic Quasi-Boolean Expansions of Relevance Logics. J Philos Logic 50, 727–754 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-020-09583-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-020-09583-4

Keywords

Navigation