Skip to main content
Log in

Why pretense poses a problem for 4E cognition (and how to move forward)

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Whether a person is pretending, or not, is a function of their beliefs and intentions. This poses a challenge to 4E accounts of pretense, which typically seek to exclude such cognitive states from their explanations of psychological phenomena. Resulting tensions are explored within three recent accounts of imagination and pretense offered by theorists working in the 4E tradition. A path forward is then charted, through considering ways in which explanations can invoke beliefs and intentions while remaining true to 4E precepts. To make real progress in explaining pretense, 4E theorists will need to grow comfortable with the idea that two agents whose outward behaviors and environments are, in the short term, the same, may be guided by quite different beliefs and intentions, in virtue of which only one is pretending. In this way, the scientific project of explaining pretense remains inseparable from the more general project of determining which beliefs and intentions are appropriate to ascribe to which kinds of entities, given which kinds of behaviors.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. An important addendum to this thumbnail definition of pretense is that we can nevertheless pretend that x is a y while believing that x is a y. Engaged in a game of charades, for instance, I can pretend that I am a philosophy professor, while believing that I am one. However, such cases of pretending what is believed can only occur in the context of a broader pretense where something is pretended (e.g. “I am now giving an important lecture”) that is not believed by the person doing the pretending. We cannot, then, pretend the world is exactly as we believe it to be. These details are sorted out in Langland-Hassan (2014a, b). For the purposes of this paper, I set aside the matter of pretending what is believed.

  2. Austin has it that “to be pretending . . . I must be trying to make others believe, or to give them the impression, by means of a current personal performance in their presence, that I am (really, only, &c.) abc, in order to disguise the fact that I am really xyz (1958, p. 275). One of his main examples involves a thief who pretends to be a window-washer in order to see what valuables lay inside a home. In conversation, Zuzanna Rucińska (a co-editor of this special issue) has emphasized that she does not view intentionally deceptive behaviors as cases of pretense—at least, not in the same sense in which childhood games of pretense are pretense. Perhaps some other 4E theorists will share that view. I think it comes with a high theoretical cost to assume no important connection between deceptive pretense and childhood pretense. Granted, if, after long theorizing, we can find no important psychological similarity between the two, skepticism about a deep link would be warranted. However, if we can find an elucidating analysis of pretense that captures both forms in its net—as I’ve aimed to provide (Langland-Hassan, 2014a, b)—such an account serves to vindicate their prima facie connection, and, in its generality, will be explanatorily preferable to an account that insists on a deep distinction between childhood and deceptive pretense.

References

  • Austin, J. L. (1958). Pretending. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 32, 261–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bermúdez, J. L. (2014). Cognitive science: An introduction to the science of the mind. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2006). Why pretend? In S. Nichols (Ed.), The architecture of imagination. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chemero, A. (2011). Radical embodied cognitive science. MIT press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2000). Mindware: An introduction to the philosophy of cognitive science. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Currie, G., & Ravenscroft, I. (2002). Recreative minds: Imagination in philosophy and psychology. Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1981). True believers : The intentional strategy and why it works. In A. F. Heath (Ed.), Scientific Explanation: Papers Based on Herbert Spencer Lectures Given in the University of Oxford (pp. 150–167). Clarendon Press.

  • Dennett, D. C. (1991). Real patterns. Journal of Philosophy, 88(1), 27–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Egan, F. (1995). Folk psychology and cognitive architecture. Philosophy of Science, 62(2), 179–196. https://doi.org/10.1086/289851.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1987). Psychosemantics: The problem of meaning in the philosophy of mind. The MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, O., & Leslie, A. (2007). The conceptual underpinnings of pretense: Pretending is not 'behaving-as-if'. Cognition, 105, 103–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2017). Enactivist interventions: Rethinking the mind. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D. (2015). Overly enactive imagination? Radically re-imagining imagining. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 53, 68–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D., & Myin, E. (2012). Radicalizing enactivism: Basic minds without content. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D., & Peeters, A. (2018). The roots of remembering: Radically enactive recollecting. In K. Michaelian, D. Debus, & D. Perrin (Eds.), New Directions in the Philosophy of Memory (pp. 97–118). Routledge.

  • Langland-Hassan, P. (2012). Pretense, imagination, and belief: The single attitude theory. Philosophical Studies, 159, 155–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Langland-Hassan, P. (2014). What it is to pretend. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 95(3), 397–420.

  • Langland-Hassan, P. (2015). Imaginative Attitudes. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 90(3), 664–686. https://doi.org/10.1111/phpr.12115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Langland-Hassan, P. (2020). Explaining Imagination. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, A. M. (1987). Pretense and representation: The origins of "theory of mind". Psychological Review, 94, 412–426.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, A. M. (1994). Pretending and believing: Issues in the theory of ToMM. Cognition, 50, 211–238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1972). Psychophysical and theoretical identifications. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 50, 249–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liao, S.-Y., & Gendler, T. (2011). Pretense and imagination. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science, 2(1), 79–94. https://doi.org/10.1002/wcs.91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liao, S.-Y., & Gendler, T. (2020). Imagination. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2020 ed.).

  • Lillard, A. (1993). Young Children's conceptualization of pretense: Action or mental representation state? Child Development, 64(2), 372–386.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lillard, A. (1998). Wanting to be it: Children's understanding of intentions underlying pretense. Child Development, 69(4), 981–993. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-8624.1998.tb06155.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lillard, A., & Witherington, D. C. (2004). Mothers' behavior modifications during pretense and their possible signal value for toddlers. Developmental Psychology, 40(1), 95–113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malafouris, M. (2013). How things shape the mind: A theory of material engagement. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Murphy, D. (2017). Brains and beliefs: On the scientific integration of folk psychology. In D. Kaplan (Ed.), Explanation and integration in mind and brain science (pp. 119–145). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newen, A., De Bruin, L., & Gallagher, S. (2018). 4E cognition: Historical roots, key concepts, and central issues. In A. Newen, L. De Bruin, & S. Gallagher (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of 4E cognition. Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2000). A cognitive theory of pretense. Cognition, 74, 115–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Picciuto, E., & Carruthers, P. (2016). Imagination and pretense. The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Imagination (pp. 334–345). Routledge.

  • Quilty-Dunn, J., & Mandelbaum, E. (2018). Against dispositionalism: Belief in cognitive science. Philosophical Studies, 175(9), 2353–2372. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-017-0962-x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rucińska, Z. (2014). Basic pretending as sensorimotor engagement? In J. M. Bishop & A. O. Martin (Eds.), Contemporary sensorimotor theory (pp. 175–187). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rucińska, Z. (2016). What guides pretence? Towards the interactive and the narrative approaches. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 15(1), 117–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1949/2009). The concept of mind. Routledge.

  • Schwitzgebel, E. (2002). A phenomenal, dispositional account of belief. Nous, 36(2), 249–275. https://doi.org/10.1111/1468-0068.00370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searcy, W. A., & Nowicki, S. (2005). The evolution of animal communication: Reliability and deception in signaling systems. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S., & Tarzia, J. (2015). The pretense debate. Cognition, 143, 1–12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Leeuwen, N. (2011). Imagination is where the action is. Journal of Philosophy, 108(2), 55–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, B. C. (2009). Monkeys crying wolf? Tufted capuchin monkeys use anti-predator calls to usurp resources from conspecifics. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 276(1669), 3013–3018.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Many thanks to Zuzanna Rucińksa and Tony Chemero for thoughtful comments that improved this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Peter Langland-Hassan.

Additional information

Publisher’s note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Langland-Hassan, P. Why pretense poses a problem for 4E cognition (and how to move forward). Phenom Cogn Sci 21, 1003–1021 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-021-09745-y

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-021-09745-y

Keywords

Navigation