The first prior: From co-embodiment to co-homeostasis in early life

https://doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2021.103117Get rights and content

Highlights

  • The paper is a predictive processing investigation of perceptual experiences in utero.

  • Primitive experiences are co-embodied in a strong ontological sense.

  • Homeostatic self-regulation first emerges within and through another human body.

  • The concepts of co-embodiment and co-homeostasis are introduced.

  • The ‘first prior’ is strongly dependent on co-embodiment and co-homeostasis.

Abstract

The idea that our perceptions in the here and now are influenced by prior events and experiences has recently received substantial support and attention from the proponents of the Predictive Processing (PP) and Active Inference framework in philosophy and computational neuroscience. In this paper we look at how perceptual experiences get off the ground from the outset, in utero. One basic yet overlooked aspect of current PP approaches is that human organisms first develop within another human body. Crucially, while not all humans will have the experience of being pregnant or carrying a baby, the experience of being carried and growing within another person’s body is universal. Specifically, we focus on the development of minimal selfhood in utero as a process co-embodiment and co-homeostasis, and highlight their close relationship. We conclude with some implications on several critical questions fuelling current debates on the nature of conscious experiences, minimal self and social cognition.

Introduction

Recent years have witnessed an ‘embodied turn’ in examining perception, cognition and action from a situated and embodied viewpoint (Varela et al., 1991, Gallagher, 2000, Thompson, 2007, De Jaegher and Di Paolo, 2007, Chemero, 2009). The idea basic idea is that our bodies’ survival within a wider and potentially threatening physical and social environment lies at the core of our perceptual experiences and cognitive processes. The embodied cognition approach outlines the idea that perception and cognition are first and foremost embodied activities (Noë, 2004, Sheets-Johnstone, 2011). In this view, cognition is “the enactment of a world and a mind on the basis of a history of the variety of actions that a being in the world performs” (Varela et al., 1991:9, our italics).

The idea that our ongoing perceptions, cognitive processes and actions are influenced by prior events and experiences has recently received substantial support and attention from the proponents of the Predictive Processing (PP henceforth) and Active Inferences framework1 (AIF henceforth) in philosophy and computational neuroscience (Friston, 2005, Clark, 2013, Hohwy, 2013, Fotopoulou, 2015). The basic starting point is the idea that humans are biological agents that “emerge as proactive survival-enabled prediction machines” (Clark, 2013:1).

In order to keep track of the survival- and reproduction-relevant bodily and worldly information, the human brain generates self- and world models, by extracting statistical patterns of information from its embodied and worldly interactions (Conant & Ross Ashby, 1970). These generative models of the cause of incoming sensory inputs are based on Bayesian ‘prior’ beliefs2 about the likely ‘hidden’ causes of the sensory information. These models form the basis of the so-called ‘expectations’ of the agent about the causal structure of its internal and external world (Rao and Ballard, 1999, Friston, 2005).

In a nutshell, our ongoing perceptions, cognition and actions are processed through the lens of prior self- and world-related information processing. If this is so, then it becomes crucial to look at how these perceptual inputs get off the ground from the outset.

In this paper we lay the theoretical basis for understanding how humans self-regulate their homeostatic bodily states and build their most basic self- and world-model, literally through others’ bodies, in utero. Specifically, we define in utero development as a process co-embodiment and co-homeostasis, and highlight their close relationship.

Indeed, one basic yet overlooked aspect of current PP and AIF approaches in both philosophy and cognitive neuroscience is that brains (and minds), and human bodies, first develop within another human body. The most basic perceptions and actions emerge already in utero (Young, 2005, Zoia et al., 2007, Castiello et al., 2010, Piontelli, 2010, Lymer, 2011, Ciaunica and Crucianelli, 2019, Quintero and De Jaegher, 2020). Crucially for our discussion here, while not all humans will have the experience of being pregnant or carrying a baby, the experience of being carried and growing within another person’s body is universal.3

Previous work looked at sensorimotor, homeostatic and bodily mechanisms operating already in early stages of development (Delafield-Butt and Gangopadhyay, 2013, Ciaunica, 2016, Ciaunica and Fotopoulou, 2017, Fotopoulou and Tsakiris, 2017, Atzil and Barrett, 2017). Here we focus on pregnancy, a case where two individuating organisms literally grasp/ grip one into each other. Specifically, we stress the idea that if we endorse a developmental bottom-up perspective, then embodiment should be examined through the lens of co-embodiment in humans. Contrary to the common view of the foetus being passively ‘contained’4 and solipsistically ‘trapped’ in the solitude of the womb, we will present evidence speaking in favour of an active and bidirectional co-regulation and constant negotiation between the two living bodies (Quintero & de Jaegher, 2020), what we will call ‘co-homeostasis’.

This paper proceeds as follows. We start in Section 2 by providing a minimal working definition of ‘embodiment’, before introducing the key notion of co-embodiment. The co-embodiment thesis will allow us to lay the preliminary ground for introducing the notion of homeostasis, allostasis and ‘co-homeostasis’, in Section 3, where we will propose an active inference reading of in utero development of perceptual experiences. We then show that the case of pregnancy offers a clear and fundamental example of co-embodiment, in Section 4, building upon theoretical and empirical work tackling the emergence of perceptual experiences in utero. Section 5 briefly discusses potential implications of endorsing a developmental perspective on current discussions regarding the nature of the human selfhood and conscious experiences. We conclude that when it comes to understanding the nature of our perceptual experiences and embodiment, the ‘infant is father to the human’ - to paraphrase Wordsworth.

Section snippets

Introducing co-embodiment

A growing body of work in philosophy, psychology and neuroscience proposed that the body plays a key role in constituting and structuring our most basic sense of self (Gallagher, 2000, Damasio and Damasio, 2006, Legrand, 2006, Seth et al., 2011; Limanowski & Blankenburg, 2013; Apps and Tsakiris, 2013, Blanke et al., 2015, Seth and Tsakiris, 2018, Allen and Tsakiris, 2019). The embodied aspects of self-related experiences have been extensively investigated in the literature (Berlucchi & Aglioti,

Modelling the self through an other: Homeostasis and allostasis under active inference

As we mentioned in the Introduction, one core aspect of the PP/AIF’s6

Back to square one: The emerging self within an other’s body

If we go back to its earliest manifestation, a successfully emerging self-organising system such as a human body needs to meet numerous constraints in order to stay alive and successfully grow. It would be too long to provide here a comprehensive description of the fascinating journey of the human life within a womb (see Piontelli, 2010, Quintero and De Jaegher, 2020 for a more detailed discussion). Yet, it is important to draw the backbone of the emergence of the human organism as a key step

From co-embodiment to co-homeostasis

As we saw earlier, both embodied and PP/AIF approaches rightly point out to the role of the organism’s physical and social environment and cognitive niche in understanding the constitutive relationship between self-organising systems (such as human bodies) and their physical and social environment (Varela et al., 1991, Fotopoulou and Tsakiris, 2017, Seth and Tsakiris, 2018). However, less attention has been paid to the idea that human bodies necessarily emerge within another human body

Future directions

The co-embodiment and co-homeostasis theses that we have outlined here may have important implications on several critical questions fuelling current debates on the nature of perceptual experiences, consciousness and minimal self-awareness. While a detailed discussion of these implications lies beyond the scope of this paper and is to be addressed in dedicated paper (**Ciaunica, Petreca, et al., submitted), it is important however to outline what we take to be the most seminal ones.

First, as we

Conclusion

In this paper we looked at the basic yet overlooked idea that the human body is a self-organising organism that emerges and develops within another human body. This is what we called the co-embodiment thesis.

We argued that the state of co-embodiment leads necessarily to co-homeostasis defined as the bi-directional process of co-regulation between the two (or more) co-embodied organisms. Co-homeostasis in human primitive bodies relies upon self-regulatory processes achieved through others’

CRediT authorship contribution statement

Anna Ciaunica: Conceptualization, Writing - original draft, Writing - review & editing. Axel Constant: Writing - review & editing. Hubert Preissl: Writing - review & editing, Supervision. Katerina Fotopoulou: Writing - review & editing, Supervision

Funding information

This work was supported by was supported by a FCT grant SFRH/BPD/94566/2013 / and PTDC/FER-FIL/4802/2020 to Anna Ciaunica.

Axel Constant was supported by an Australian Laureate Fellowship project A Philosophy of Medicine for the 21st Century (Ref: FL170100160); and by a Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council (SSHRC) doctoral fellowship (Ref: 752-2019-0065).

Hubert Preissl was supported by the FET Open Luminous project (H2020 FETOPEN-2014-2015-RIA under agreement No. 686764) as part of

References (120)

  • G. Pezzulo et al.

    Active Inference, homeostatic regulation and adaptive behavioural control

    Progress in Neurobiology

    (2015)
  • A.K. Seth

    Interoceptive inference, emotion, and the embodied self

    Trends in Cognitive Sciences

    (2013)
  • A.K. Seth et al.

    Being a beast machine: the somatic basis of selfhood

    Trends in Cognitive Sciences

    (2018)
  • R.A. Adams et al.

    The computational anatomy of psychosis

    Frontiers in Psychiatry

    (2013)
  • K.M. Adams Waldorf et al.

    Autoimmune disease during pregnancy and the microchimerism legacy of pregnancy

    Immunological Investigations

    (2008)
  • M.S. Ainsworth et al.

    Patterns of attachment: A psychological study of the strange situation

    (1978)
  • M. Allen et al.

    The body as first prior: Interoceptive predictive processing and the primacy

  • A.H. Anderson et al.

    Placental transport of threonine and its utilization in the normal and growth restricted fetus

    American Journal of Physiology

    (1997)
  • M.A. Apps et al.

    The free-energy self: a predictive coding account of self-recognition

    Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews Apr.

    (2013)
  • S. Atzil et al.

    Social regulation of allostasis: Commentary on “Mentalizing homeostasis: The social origins of interoceptive inference” by Fotopoulou and Tsakiris

    Neuropsychoanalysis

    (2017)
  • I. Bauer et al.

    Spotlight on the fetus: how physical activity during pregnancy influences fetal health: a narrative review

    BMJ Open Sport & Exercise Medicine

    (2020)
  • M. Bekoff et al.

    Prenatal motility and postnatal play: Functional continuity?

    Developmental Psychobiology

    (1980)
  • D.W. Bianchi et al.

    Male fetal progenitor cells persist in maternal blood for as long as 27 years postpartum

    Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America

    (1996)
  • L. Birch

    Development of food preferences

    Annual Review of Nutrition

    (1999)
  • O. Blanke

    Multisensory brain mechanisms of bodily self-consciousness

    Nature Reviews Neuroscience

    (2012)
  • G.J. Burton et al.

    What is the placenta?

    American Journal of Obstetrics & Gynecology

    (2015)
  • Cannon, W.B. (1929) Organisation for Physiological Homeostasis. Physiological Reviews 9(3),...
  • U. Castiello et al.

    Wired to Be Social: The Ontogeny of Human Interaction

    PLoS One

    (2010)
  • A. Ciaunica

    Basic Forms of Pre-reflective Self-Consciousness: a Developmental Perspective

  • A. Ciaunica

    The ‘Meeting of Bodies’: Empathy and Basic Forms of Shared Experiences

    Topoi

    (2017)
  • A. Ciaunica et al.

    Minimal self-awareness: From within a developmental perspective

    Journal of Consciousness Studies

    (2019)
  • A. Ciaunica et al.

    The Touched Self: Psychological and Philosophical Perspectives on Proximal Intersubjectivity and the Self

  • Ciaunica, A., Petreca, B., Fotopoulou, A., & Roepstorff, A. (2021, January 5). Whatever Next and Close to my Self – The...
  • Ciaunica, A., Safron, A., & Delafield-Butt, J. (2021, March 1). Back to Square One: from Embodied Experiences in Utero...
  • J. Cha et al.

    Mechanisms of implantation: Strategies for successful pregnancy

    Nature Medicine

    (2012)
  • A. Chemero

    Radical Embodied Cognition

    (2009)
  • A. Clark

    Whatever next? Predictive brains, situated agents, and the future of cognitive science

    Behavioral and Brain Sciences

    (2013)
  • R.C. Conant et al.

    Every good regulator of a system must be a model of that system

    International Journal of Systems Science

    (1970)
  • A. Constant et al.

    A variational approach to niche construction

    Journal of the Royal Society, Interface/The Royal Society

    (2018)
  • A. Constant et al.

    Extended active inference: constructing predictive cognition beyond skulls

    Mind and Language

    (2020)
  • A. Damasio

    The Feeling of What Happens. Body, Emotion and the Making of Consciousness

    (2000)
  • A. Damasio et al.

    Minding the body

    Daedalus

    (2006)
  • H. De Jaegher et al.

    Participatory sense-making: an enactive approach to social cognition

    Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences

    (2007)
  • F. de Vignemont

    Embodiment, ownership and disownership

    Consciousness and Cognition

    (2010)
  • J.A. Eyre et al.

    Functional corticospinal projections are established prenatally in the human foetus permitting involvement in the development of spinal motor centres

    Brain

    (2000)
  • C. Einspieler et al.

    Fetal behaviour: A neurodevelopmental approach

    (2012)
  • N. Faivre et al.

    Consciousness is more than meets the eye: a call for a multisensory study of subjective experience

    Neuroscience of Consciousness

    (2017)
  • T. Field

    Touch

    (2001)
  • A. Fotopoulou et al.

    Mentalizing homeostasis: The social origins of interoceptive inference

    Neuropsychoanalysis

    (2017)
  • K. Friston

    A theory of cortical responses

    Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London

    (2005)
  • Cited by (32)

    • “Conflict to collage”: A perceptual control architecture to underpin human consciousness

      2023, The Interdisciplinary Handbook of Perceptual Control Theory, Volume II: Living in the Loop
    • An integrative perspective on the role of touch in the development of intersubjectivity

      2022, Brain and Cognition
      Citation Excerpt :

      As it is described, for example, by the French philosopher Maurice Merleau-Ponty (1962): “we are in the world through our body and in so far as we perceive the world with our body […] perceiving as we do with our body, the body is a natural self and, as it were, the subject of perception” (p. 239). Thus, a sense of embeddedness of our body in the environment is to be considered among the crucial features of basic forms of self-awareness (e.g., Clark, 1998; De Jaegher and Di Paolo, 2008; Ciaunica et al., 2021). A fundamental aspect here is that our environment also includes other individuals with similar subjective experiences as ourselves.

    • I overthink—Therefore I am not: An active inference account of altered sense of self and agency in depersonalisation disorder

      2022, Consciousness and Cognition
      Citation Excerpt :

      While further work is needed to disentangle these aspects, one may speculate that these approaches are compatible insofar as different experimental designs tackle distinct levels of the hierarchical processing. For example, if one endorses a developmental perspective in understanding the “first priors” (Ciaunica, Constant, Preissl, & Fotopoulou, 2021b), then one may argue that different senses (e.g., tactile versus visual inputs) may have preferential access to higher levels of the hierarchy. For example, affiliative touch may be afforded more precision than visual afferents, and this may trigger distinct precision weighting at further levels of hierarchical processing.

    • Affective regulation through touch: homeostatic and allostatic mechanisms

      2022, Current Opinion in Behavioral Sciences
      Citation Excerpt :

      We envision that such processes converge in affective regulation but we emphasise both embodied cognition and higher-order concepts of cognition in this paper to ensure coverage of the whole spectrum of functions. This model is embedded in wider perspectives on the central role of homeostasis, rather than rationality, in cognition, and particularly the theoretical framework ‘Mentalising Homeostasis’ that we have proposed to characterise the interdependence between interoception, cognition and socialisation [12,14–16,17•]. According to this widely discussed framework (see commentaries on [12,18,19•]), affect is not the result of ascending ‘sensory’ signals and descending ‘modulatory’ cognitive influences, but rather the result of a single hierarchical system of recurring processes including predictive feedforward and feedback loops (e.g. [20]), as understood particularly in hierarchical Bayesian brain accounts [21].

    View all citing articles on Scopus
    View full text