Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Criminal Law Guilt and Ontological Guilt: A Heideggerian Perspective

  • Published:
Law and Critique Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The paper deals with the notion of guilt according to Heidegger’s philosophy and its repercussions for the understanding of guilt according to criminal law doctrine and theory. Heidegger’s notion on guilt is tantamount to Dasein’s incapacity to exhaust all its existential possibilities, whereas legal guilt has to do only with man’s legal indebtedness, which is an aspect of inauthenticity, a deficient mode of ontological responsibility. This does not mean, though, sheer amoralism or apologetics to violence. In late Heidegger one may discern traces of an ontological ethics, which refers to Dasein’s attunement to Being and especially to the sparing and healing of the Fourfold as these are coming to presence through poetic dwelling; through, that is, an authentic contact with the Uncanny, meaning a radical exposure to Being’s enigmatic hiddenness, the endurance in front of the abyss of Nothingness. In this framework there remains no space for assuming any moral-juridical responsibility, because Dasein is predestined to err constantly due to the ruptures and turnings of Being’s history. Legal blameworthiness is thus obsolete because, injustice being according to Heidegger the dis-jointure of Being’s order, there is ontologically no imputable ‘legal’ crime; there is only Dasein’s eventful projecting-opening within errancy. Whether though this notion of ‘Being’ is a new ‘arche’ to be superseded emerges then as the crucial question. To regain any non-metaphysical notion of guilt is after Heidegger only possible through a theoretical move which cannot ignore his legacy but also has to go beyond the Master.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. With ‘Turn’ one denotes the change of viewpoint under which Heidegger deals with the very question of his philosophy, i.e. the question of Being; whereas within a first stage of development of his thought (expressed mainly in ‘Being and Time’) this question is worked out through the lenses of existential analytic, meaning the understanding of Being via Dasein, late Heidegger is supposed to understand Being from out of Being itself and especially via its history (‘being-historical thinking’); such a Being has Dasein now to be attuned to. Analysis is now replaced through responding to the immediate call of Being. Therefore poetics become crucial for the philosopher.

  2. One cannot repress the feeling that the refutation of deontology runs the risk of ushering in power apologetics. The risky exposure to totalitarian political manipulation of such an attitude is again present here, as long as deontology is not enriched through substantial ethics but rejected in favour of some kind of militant existentialism, which forecloses critique.

  3. See respectively (Critchley 1999, pp. 224–225); on Levinas’ negation of a personal death, see also Wall (1999, pp. 59–62).

  4. Cf. a thorough analysis of the law as irresponsibility imposing mechanism, Veitch (2007), passim and especially at pp. 7–73.

  5. For further details on these topics, which cannot be presented here, see: Heidegger (2003, Parts II, IV, V, VII, VIII).

  6. Steiner (2009, pp. 190–196), Fried (2000, pp. 191–192); on Heidegger’s ethical–political ambivalence, see the excellent analyses of De Beistegui (1998, passim and especially at pp. 146–157); cf. in favour of the view that Heidegger came progressively into conflict with the bestial Nazi regime, Tietjen (2001, pp. 303–305).

  7. See on the private nature of Heideggerian Nazism also Fried (2000, p. 174).

References

  • Alexander, Larry. 2011. Culpability. In The Oxford handbook of philosophy of criminal law, ed. J. Deigh and D. Dolinko, 218–238. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexander, Larry, and Kimberly Kessler Ferzan. 2011. Beyond the special part. In Philosophical foundations of criminal law, eds. R.A. Duff and St. Green, 253–78. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Ben-Dor, Oren. 2007. Thinking about law. In silence with Heidegger. Oxford and Portland, Oregon: Hart.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blok, Vincent. 2011. Establishing the truth: Heidegger’s reflections on gestalt. Heidegger Studies/Heidegger Studien/Etudes Heideggeriennes 27 (Enowning-thinking, the onefold of hermeneutic phenomenology, interpreting gestalt und history): 101–118.

  • Bochenski, I.M. 1975. Europäische Philosophie der Gegenwart, trans. into Greek, Chr. Malevitsis. Athens: Dodoni Publ.

  • De Beistegui, Miguel. 1998. Heidegger & the political. Dystopias. Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Beistegui, Miguel. 2003. Thinking with Heidegger. Displacements. Bloomington & Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caputo, John. 2006. Heidegger and theology. In The Cambridge companion to Heidegger, ed. Ch. Guignon, 326–344. Cambridge University Press.

  • Critchley, Simon. 1999. The ethics of deconstruction. Derrida and Levinas: Edinburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dastur, Françoise. 2008. Heidegger et la question du temps, trans. into Greek, Μ. Pangalos. Athens: Patakis Publ.

  • Derrida, Jacques. 1986. Schibboleth. Für Paul Celan. Vienna: Passagen Verlag Ges.M.B.H.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diamond, John. 1996. The myth of morality and fault in criminal law doctrine. American Criminal Law Review 34: 111–131.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elgat, Guy. 2020. Heidegger on guilt: Reconstructing the transcendental argument in being and time. European Journal of Philosophy 28 (4): 911–925.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Figal, Günter. 1998. For a philosophy of freedom and strife. Politics, aesthetics, metaphysics. New York: SUNY.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fräntzki, Ekkehard. 1987. Die Kehre. Heideggers Schrift ‘Vom Wesen der Wahrheit‘. Pffafenweiler: Centaurus.

    Google Scholar 

  • France-Lanord, Hadrien. 2011. Martin Heidegger et la question de l’autre. III. Être soi ensemble. IV. Le souci mutuel. Heidegger Studies/Heidegger Studien/Etudes Heideggeriennes 27 (Enowning-Thinking, the Onefold of Hermeneutic Phenomenology, Interpreting Gestalt und History): 75–99.

  • Fried, Gregory. 2000. Heidegger’s Polemos. From being to politics. New Haven & London: Yale University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gemenetzis, Kostas. 1991a. Reintroduction to psychoanalysis (in Greek). Athens: Hestia Publ.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gemenetzis, Kostas. 1991b. Comment (in Greek). In M. Heidegger, Aus einem Gespräch von der Sprache. Zwischen einem Japaner und einem Fragenden, trans. into Greek, K. Gemenetzis, 109–252. Athens: Roptron Publ.

  • Grosser, Florian. 2011. Revolution denken. Heidegger und das Politische 1919 bis 1969. München: C.H. Beck.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Guzzoni, Ute. 2008. ‘Were speculation about the state of reconciliation permissible…’: Reflections on the relation between human beings and things in Adorno and Heidegger. In Adorno and Heidegger. Philosophical questions, ed. I. Macdonald and Kr. Ziarek, 124–37. Stanford, California: Stanford University Press.

  • Han, Byung-Chul. 1996. Heideggers Herz. Zum Begriff der Stimmung bei Martin Heidegger. München: Wilhelm Fink.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Harries, Karsten. 2012. The antinomy of being: Heidegger’s critique of humanism. In The Cambridge companion to existentialism, ed. St. Crowell, 178–198. Cambridge University Press.

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1973. Einführung in die Metaphysik, trans. into Greek, Chr. Malevitsis. Athens: Dodoni Publ.

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1978. Sein und Zeit (Α’ Volume), trans. into Greek, G. Tzavaras. Athens: Dodoni Publ.

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1983. Schöpferische Landschaft: Warum bleiben wir in der Provinz? In Aus der Erfahrung des Denkens 1910–1976, 9–13. Frankfurt a.M.: Vittorio Klostermann.

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1991. Aus einem Gespräch von der Sprache. Zwischen einem Japaner und einem Fragenden, trans. into Greek, K. Gemenetzis. Athens: Roptron Publ.

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1985. Sein und Zeit (B’ Volume), trans. into Greek, G. Tzavaras. Athens: Dodoni Publ.

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1994. Wozu Dichter? In Holzwege, 269–320. Frankfurt a.M.: Vittorio Klostermann.

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1996. Die Technik und die Kehre. Stuttgart: Neske.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1997. Besinnung, GA Band 66. Frankfurt a.M. 1997: Vittorio Klostermann.

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1998a. Was ist Metaphysik? Frankfurt a.M.: Vittorio Klostermann.

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1998b. Die Geschichte des Seyns, GA Band 69. Frankfurt a.M.: Vittorio Klostermann.

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1998c. Aufenthalte. The Journey to Greece, trans. into Greek, G. Faraklas. Athens: Kritiki Publ.

  • Heidegger, Martin. 2000. Brief über denHumanismus’, bilingual edition, trans. into Greek, G. Xiropaidis. Athens: Roes Publ.

  • Heidegger, Martin. 2001a. Die Grundfrage der Philosophie, SS 1933. In Sein und Wahrheit, GA Band 36/37, 1–80. Frankfurt a.M.: Vittorio Klostermann.

  • Heidegger, Martin. 2001b. Vom Wesen der Wahrheit, WS 1933/34. In Sein und Wahrheit, GA Band 36/37, 83–264. Frankfurt a.M.: Vittorio Klostermann.

  • Heidegger, Martin. 2003. Beiträge zur Philosophie (Vom Ereignis), GA Band 65, Frankfurt a.M.: Vittorio Klostermann.

  • Heidegger, Martin. 2005a. Einblick in das was ist. Bremer Vorträge 1949. Das Ge-stell. In Bremer und Freiburger Vorträge, GA Band 79, 24–45. Frankfurt a.M.: Vittorio Klostermann.

  • Heidegger, Martin. 2005b. Einblick in das was ist. Bremer Vorträge 1949. Die Gefahr. In Bremer und Freiburger Vorträge, GA Band 79, 46–67. Frankfurt a.M.: Vittorio Klostermann.

  • Heidegger, Martin. 2007. The positivity of theology and its relation to phenomenology, trans. into Greek, G. Tzavaras. In Theology & philosophy in the early Heidegger, ed. G. Tzavaras, 91–117. Athens: Indiktos.

  • Heidegger, Martin. 2011. The Spiegel interview, trans. into Greek, K. Gemenetzis. Athens: Hestia Publ.

  • Heinemann, Walter. 1970. Die Relevanz der Philosophie Martin Heideggers für das Rechtsdenken, Inaugural-Dissertation, Freiburg i. B.

  • Hillis Miller, Joseph. 2006. Derrida’s destinerrance. Modern Language Notes 121 (4): 893–910.

    Google Scholar 

  • Janicaud, Dominique. 1992. The shadow of this thinking. In: Martin Heidegger. Critical assessments, Volume IV: Reverberations, ed. Chr. Macann, 104–34. London and New York: Routledge.

  • Jaspers, Karl. 2000. The question of the German guilt. New York: Fordham University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kalary, Thomas, and Frank Schalow. 2011. Attunement, discourse, and the onefold of hermeneutic phenomenology: Recent Heidegger-literature and a new translation of his work in critical perspective. Heidegger Studies/Heidegger Studien/Etudes Heideggeriennes 27 (Enowning-Thinking, the Onefold of Hermeneutic Phenomenology, Interpreting Gestalt und History): 199–219.

  • Kaufmann, Arthur. 1976. Das Schuldprinzip. Eine strafrechtlich-rechtsphilosophische Untersuchung. Heidelberg: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lacoue-Labarthe, Philippe. 1990. Heidegger, art and politics. The fiction of the political. Hoboken: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lukács, Georg. 2016. The destruction of reason. Delhi: Aakar Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macann, Christopher. 1992. Who is Dasein? Towards an ethics of authenticity. In Martin Heidegger. Critical assessments. Volume IV: Reverberations, ed. Chr. Macann, 214–246. London and NewYork: Routledge.

  • Malevitsis, Christos. 1973. Martin Heidegger. The philosopher of the meaning of being (in Greek). In M. Heidegger, Einführung in die Metaphysik, trans. into Greek, Chr. Malevitsis, 255–275. Athens: Dodoni Publ.

  • Moore, Michael. 1987. The moral worth of retribution. In Responsibility, character and the emotions, new essays in moral psychology, ed. Ferd. Schoeman, 179–219. Cambridge University Press.

  • Murphy, Jeffrie G. 2000. Forgiveness, reconciliation and responding to evil: A philosophical overview. Fordham Urban Law Journal 27: 1353–1366.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nancy, Jean-Luc. 2017. The banality of Heidegger. New York: Fordham University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Norrie, Alan. 2000. Punishment, responsibility and justice. A relational critique. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Norrie, Alan. 2008. Justice on the slaughter bench: The problem of war guilt in Arendt and Jaspers. New Criminal Law Review 11 (2): 187–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Papacharalambous, Charis. 2019. Criminal law’s normative aspirations in a post-positivist frame. Jurisprudence 10 (1): 77–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Papagiorgis, Kostis. 1983. The ontology of Martin Heidegger (in Greek). Athens: Nefeli Publ.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peperzak, Adriaan Theodoor. 1999. Beyond. The philosophy of Emmanuel Levinas. Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, James. 2005. Heidegger’s Volk. Between national socialism and poetry. Stanford, California: Stanford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pöggeler, Otto. 1992. Being as appropriation. In Martin Heidegger. Critical assessments. Volume I: Philosophy, ed. Chr. Macann, 279–309. London and New York: Routledge.

  • Ramsay, Peter. 2018. Book Review. Alan Norrie, justice and the slaughter bench: Essays on law’s broken dialectic [2016]. Modern Law Review 81 (3): 543–547.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rentsch, Thomas. 2003. Heidegger und Wittgenstein. Existential- und Sprachanalysen zu den Grundlagen philosophischer Anthropologie. Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schäfer, Martin Jörg. 2003. Schmerz zum Mitsein. Zur Lektüre Celans und Heideggers durch Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe und Jean-Luc Nancy. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schröder, Wolfgang M. 2004. Politik des Schonens. Heideggers Geviert-Konzept, politisch ausgelegt. Tübingen: Attempto Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steiner, George. 2009. Heidegger, trans. into Greek, Α. Karavanda. Athens: Patakis Publ.

  • van Stokkom, Bas. 2013. Book Review. Jeffrie G. Murphy, Punishment and the moral emotions: Essays in law, morality, and religion [2012]. Restorative Justice 1 (1): 150–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomä, Dieter. 2000. Verantwortung: Heidegger und Arendt. In Intellektuelle im Nationalsozialismus, eds. W. Bialas/M. Gangl, 176–209. Frankfurt a.M., Berlin etc.: Peter Lang.

  • Tietjen, Hartmut. 2001. Nachwort des Herausgebers. In Sein und Wahrheit, M. Heidegger, GA Band 36/37, 299–305. Frankfurt a.M.: Vittorio Klostermann.

  • Tzavaras, Giannis. 2007. Theology & philosophy in the early Heidegger (in Greek). Athens: Indiktos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vallega-Neu, Daniela. 2018. Heidegger’s poietic writings. From contributions to philosophy to the event. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Veitch, Scott. 2007. Law and irresponsibility. On the legitimation of human suffering. Abingdon: Routledge, Cavendish.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wahl, Jean. 1970. Les philosophies de l’existence, trans. into Greek, Chr. Malevitsis. Athens: Dodoni Publ.

  • Wall, Thomas Carl. 1999. Radical passivity. Levinas, Blanchot, and Agamben. New York: SUNY.

    Google Scholar 

  • Webb, Julian. 2009. Review of Oren Ben-Dor, Thinking about law: In A relational critique. Silence with Heidegger Legal Studies 29 (2): 341–345.

    Google Scholar 

  • West, David. 2010. Continental philosophy. An introduction. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wood, David. 1999. The experience of the ethical. In Questioning ethics. Contemporary debates in philosophy, eds. R. Kearney and M. Dooley, 105–119. London and New York: Routledge.

  • Wulff, Agnes. 2008. Die Existenziale Schuld. Der fundamentalontologische Schuldbegriff Martin Heideggers und seine Bedeutung für das Strafrecht. Münster: LIT.

  • Xiropaidis, Georgios. 1995. Heidegger and the problem of ontology (in Greek). Athens: Kritiki Publ.

    Google Scholar 

  • Xiropaidis, Georgios. 2000. Introduction (in Greek). In M. Heidegger, Brief über denHumanismus’, bilingual edition, trans. into Greek, G. Xiropaidis, 11–35. Athens: Roes Publ.

Download references

Acknowledgements

This is an elaborated version of my Birkbeck College lecture on 27 November 2019. I would like to express my best thanks to Elena Loizidou for her kind invitation, as well as to her and Marinos Diamantides, Craig Reeves, Stewart Motha and Patrick Hanafin for their valuable comments during the discussion following the presentation. As to the author’s responsibility for the text, the usual caveats apply.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Charis N. Papacharalambous.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Papacharalambous, C.N. Criminal Law Guilt and Ontological Guilt: A Heideggerian Perspective. Law Critique 33, 149–173 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10978-021-09289-9

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10978-021-09289-9

Keywords

Navigation