Skip to main content
Log in

Speciesism, Arbitrariness and Moral Illusions

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Just as one line appears to be longer than another in an optical illusion, we can have a spontaneous moral judgment that one individual is more important than another. Sometimes such judgments can lead to moral illusions like speciesism and other kinds of discrimination. Moral illusions are persistent spontaneous judgments that violate our deepest moral values and distract us away from a rational, authentic ethic. They generate pseudo-ethics, similar to pseudoscience. The antidote against moral illusions is the ethical principle to avoid unwanted arbitrariness. Speciesism involves unwanted arbitrariness, and psychological research as well as the problem of wild animal suffering demonstrate that moral illusions such as speciesism can be very persistent.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Although the unwantedness seems to give this principle a subjective flavor, the principle is objective in the sense of being completely independent from the beliefs of the ethicist who applies the principle. What counts as arbitrary is a matter of logic, and what counts as unwanted is determined by the person who does not want the consequences of the choice.

  2. This principle resembles a Kantian categorical imperative (“Act only according to that maxim whereby you can, at the same time, will that it should become a universal law.” Kant 1785) and a contractualist principle (“An act is wrong if and only if any principle that permitted it would be one that could reasonably be rejected by people moved to find principles for the general regulation of behaviour that others, similarly motivated, could not reasonably reject” Scanlon 1998). Parfit (2011) argued that such formulations can unify rule consequentialist, Kantian and contractualist ethics: “An act is wrong if and only if 1. such acts are disallowed by some principle that is one of the principles whose being universal laws would make things go best, 2. one of the only principles whose being universal laws everyone could rationally will, 3. a principle that no one could reasonably reject.”

    In practical ethics contexts, the anti-arbitrariness principle is also reminiscent of moral consistency reasoning (Campbell and Kumar 2012).

  3. Many defenses of speciesism reflect essentialism, by referring to personhood or humanity (the human species) as a ‘kind’, having a ‘substantial nature’. (See e.g. Chappell 2011; Cohen and Regan 2001; Lee and George 2008; Scanlon 1998, p.186; Scruton 2000. See McMahan 2005 and Tanner 2006, for an extensive critique of the ‘argument of kinds’.)

  4. This body ownership issue is complicated by body transfer illusions (Petkova and Ehrsson 2008) such as the rubber hand illusion (Botvinick and Cohen 1998). For the moment, I will assume that a person can autonomously decide what counts as his or her own body, e.g. using thought experiments where the person can decide which body parts and objects such as rubber hands cannot be tortured.

  5. Note that this right not to be used against one’s will differs from other rights, such as the right not to be killed against one’s will. Think of genocide: people who hate other people, prefer the absence of those other people. The end or goal is their absence, so their presence is not required to reach this end. Killing those other people does not violate their right not to be used, but does violate their right not to be killed.

  6. Experimental evidence of cognitive dissonance indicates that most meat eaters have moral values that conflict with their consumption of ‘factory farmed’ meat (Loughnan et al. 2010; Bastian et al. 2012; Bastian and Loughnan 2017). Such cognitive dissonance experiments could give indications about our hidden, deepest moral values.

  7. The animal rights advocates mentioned in this section, include attendees at animal rights conferences. Their presented arguments are based on personal communications.

  8. These are known as epistemic, instrumental and axiological rationality (Kolodny and Brunero 2016).

References

  • Ahluwalia, A. (1978). An intra-cultural investigation of susceptibility to ‘perspective’ and ‘non-perspective’ spatial illusions. British Journal of Psychology, 69(2), 233–241.

    Google Scholar 

  • Altman, A. (2016). Discrimination. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, winter 2016 edition, Edward N. Zalta (ed.).

  • Bach, M., & Poloschek, C. M. (2006). Optical illusions. Advances in Clinical Neurosciences Rehabilitation, 6(2), 20–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barker, M. (2010). Specious Intrinsicalism. Philosophy of Science, 77, 73–91.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bastian, B., & Loughnan, S. (2017). Resolving the meat-paradox: A motivational account of morally troublesome behavior and its maintenance. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 21(3), 278–299.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bastian, B., Loughnan, S., Haslam, N., & Radke, H. (2012). Don’t mind meat? The denial of mind to animals used for human consumption. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 38, 247–256.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloom, P. (2010). Why we like what we like. Observer, 23(8), 3.

    Google Scholar 

  • Botvinick, M., & Cohen, J. (1998). Rubber hands ‘feel’ touch that eyes see. Nature, 391(6669), 756–756.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruers, S. (2016). In search of moral illusions. The Journal of Value Inquiry, 50(2), 283–303.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, R., & Kumar, V. (2012). Moral reasoning on the ground. Ethics, 122(2), 273–312.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chappell, T. (2011). On the very idea of criteria for personhood. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 49(1), 1–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, C., & Regan, T. (2001). The animal rights debate. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cosmides, L., Tooby, J., & Kurzban, R. (2003). Perceptions of race. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7(4), 173–179.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R. (1993). Gaps in the mind. In P. Cavaliere & P. Singer (Eds.), The great ape project (pp. 81–87). New York: St. Martin’s Griffin.

    Google Scholar 

  • DiSilvestro, R. (2010). Human capacities and moral status. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefski, M. (2010). What’s wrong with the new biological essentialism. Philosophy of Science, 77, 674–685.

    Google Scholar 

  • Faria, C. (2016). Animal ethics Goes wild: The problem of wild animal suffering and intervention in nature (Ph.D.). Universitat Pompeu Fabra.

  • Francione, G. (2000). Your child or the dog? An introduction to animal rights. Philadephia: Temple University Press.

  • Gelman, S. (2003). The essential child: Origins of essentialism in everyday thought. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gil-White, F. J. (2001). Are ethnic groups biological “species” to the human brain? Essentialism in our cognition of some social categories. Current Anthropology, 42(4), 515–555.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godlovitch, R., Godlovitch, S., & Harris, J. (Eds.). (1971). Animals, men and morals: An inquiry into the maltreatment of non-humans. New York: Grove Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gunnarsson, L. (2008). The great apes and the severely disabled: Moral status and thick evaluative concepts. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 11(3), 305–326.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansson, S. O. (2008). Science and Pseudo-Science. In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of hilosophy (Summer 2017 Edition). Stanford: Stanford University.

  • Harris, S. (2004). The end of faith. New York: W.W. Norton.

  • Hoffman, D. D., & Singh, M. (2012). Computational evolutionary perception. Perception, 41(9), 1073–1091.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horta, O. (2010). Debunking the idyllic view of natural processes: Population dynamics and suffering in the wild. Télos, 17(1), 73–88.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hsiao, T. (2015). In defense of eating meat. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 28(2), 277–291.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. (1965). The effect of essentialism on taxonomy: Two thousand years of stasis. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 15, 314–326.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joy, M. (2003). Psychic numbing and meat consumption: The Psychology of carnism (doctoral dissertation).

  • Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, fast and slow. New York: Macmillan.

  • Kant, I. (1785), translated by J.W. Ellington (1993). Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals, 3rd ed. Indianapolis: Hackett.

  • Kolodny, N., & Brunero, J. (2016). Instrumental Rationality. In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2020 Edition). Stanford: Stanford University.

  • Kumar, R. (2008). Permissible killing and the irrelevance of being human. The Journal of Ethics, 12, 57–80.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kurzban, R., Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (2001). Can race be erased? Coalitional computation and social categorization. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 98(26), 15387–15393.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lee, P., & George, R. (2008). The nature and basis of human dignity. Ratio Juris, 21(2), 173–193.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leite, A. C., Dhont, K., & Hodson, G. (2019). Longitudinal effects of human supremacy beliefs and vegetarianism threat on moral exclusion (vs. inclusion) of animals. European Journal of Social Psychology, 49(1), 179–189.

  • Lewens, T. (2012). Species, Essence and Explanation. Studies in the History and Philosophy of the Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 43, 751–757.

    Google Scholar 

  • Liao, M. (2010). The basis of human moral status. Journal of Moral Philosophy, 7(2), 159–179.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loughnan, S., Haslam, N., & Bastian, B. (2010). The role of meat consumption in the denial of moral status and mind to meat animals. Appetite, 55, 156–159.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacLean, D. (2010). Is “human being” a moral concept? Philosophy & Public Policy Quarterly, 30(3/4), 16–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marino, L., & Colvin, C. (2015). Thinking pigs: A comparative review of cognition, emotion, and personality in sus domesticus. International Journal of Comparative Psychology, 28, 1–22.

  • McMahan, J. (2005). Our fellow creatures. The Journal of Ethics, 9, 353–380.

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller-Lyer, F, C. (1889). Optische Urteilstäuschungen. Archiv für Physiologie Suppl., p.263–270.

  • Ng, Y.-K. (1995). Towards welfare biology: Evolutionary economics of animal consciousness and suffering. Biology and Philosophy, 10(3), 255–285.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (2011). On what matters. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Petkova, V., & Ehrsson, H. (2008). If I were you: Perceptual illusion of body swapping. PLoS One, 3(12), e3832.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci, M., & Boudry, M. (Eds.). (2013). Philosophy of pseudoscience: Reconsidering the demarcation problem. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Plous, S. (2003). Is there such a thing as prejudice towards animals? In Understanding prejudice and discrimination, Plous (ed.), McGraw-hill, New York.

  • Pylyshyn, Z. (1999). Is vision continuous with cognition? The case for cognitive impenetrability of visual perception. Behavior and Brain Sciences, 22, 341–365.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quattrone, G. A., & Jones, E. E. (1980). The perception of variability within in-groups and out-groups: Implications for the law of small numbers. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 38(1), 141–152.

    Google Scholar 

  • Resnik, D. B. (2000). A pragmatic approach to the demarcation problem. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 31(2), 249–267.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryder, R. D. (1975). Victims of science: The use of animals in research. London: Davis-Poynter.

  • Scanlon, T. (1998). What we owe to each other. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

  • Scruton, R. (2000). Animal Rights and Wrongs, 3rd ed. London: Demos.

  • Segall, M. H., Campbell, D. T., & Herskovits, M. J. (1963). Cultural differences in the perception of geometric illusions. Science, New Series, 139(3556), 769–771.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (1975, 1990). Animal Liberation, a new ethics for our treatment of animals, (2nd ed.). New York: New York Review.

  • Sober, E. (1980). Evolution, Population Thinking and Essentialism. Philosophy of Science, 47, 350–383.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tajfel, H. (1981). Human groups and social categories. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tanner, J. (2006). Marginal humans, the argument from kinds and the similarity argument. Facta Universitas, 5(1), 47–63.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasik, B. (2015). The importance of wild-animal suffering. Relations. Beyond Anthropocentrism, 3(2), 133–152.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A. (1986). Cognitive illusions in judgment and choice. In The Kaleidoscope of Science (pp. 75–87). Springer, Dordrecht

  • Walen, A. (2014). Transcending the means principles. Law and Philosophy., 33(4), 427–464.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitley, B. E., & Kite, M. E. (2010). The psychology of prejudice and discrimination. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (2006). The human prejudice. Philosophy as a Humanistic Discipline. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Wu, J. E. A. (2017). Interspecies chimerism with mammalian pluripotent stem cells. Cell, 168(3), 473–486.e15.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Stijn Bruers.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bruers, S. Speciesism, Arbitrariness and Moral Illusions. Philosophia 49, 957–975 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-020-00282-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-020-00282-7

Keywords

Navigation