Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-vfjqv Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-25T19:55:34.123Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A Second-Personal Solution to the Paradox of Moral Complaint

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  19 November 2020

Adam Piovarchy*
Affiliation:
The University of Sydney

Abstract

Smilansky (2006) notes that wrongdoers seem to lack any entitlement to complain about being treated in the ways that they have treated others. However, it also seems impermissible to treat agents in certain ways, and this impermissibility would give wrongdoers who are themselves wronged grounds for complaint. This article solves this apparent paradox by arguing that what is at issue is not the right simply to make complaints, but the right to have one's demands respected. Agents must accept the authority of others to make second-personal demands on them before they can expect others to treat their own demands (or complaints) as legitimate. Wrongdoers’ previous wrongdoing shows they do not treat others’ demands as authoritative. However, as they are still beings with dignity, which acts as a source of moral reasons for others, wronging them remains impermissible.

Type
Reply
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2020. Published by Cambridge University Press

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Austin, John. 1962. How to Do Things with Words (Oxford: Clarendon Press).Google Scholar
Bell, Macalaster. 2013. The Standing to Blame: A Critique. In Blame: Its Nature and Norms ed. by Coates, Justin and Tognazzini, Neal (New York: Oxford University Press), pp. 141–61.Google Scholar
Darwall, Stephen. L. 2006. The Second-Person Standpoint: Morality, Respect, and Accountability (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).Google Scholar
Duff, Antony. 2010. Blame, Moral Standing and the Legitimacy of the Criminal Trial. Ratio, 23.2: 123–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friedman, Marilyn. 2013. How to Blame People Responsibly. Journal of Value Inquiry, 47.3: 271284.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fritz, Kyle, and Miller, Daniel. 2018. Hypocrisy and the Standing to Blame. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 99.1: 118–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fritz, Kyle, and Miller, Daniel. 2019. The Unique Badness of Hypocritical Blame. Ergo, 6.19: 545–69.Google Scholar
Herstein, Ori. 2017. Understanding Standing: Permission to Deflect Reasons. Philosophical Studies, 174.12: 3109–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Herstein, Ori. 2020. Justifying Standing to Give Reasons: Hypocrisy, Minding Your Own Business, and Knowing One's Place. Philosophers' Imprint, 20.7: 118.Google Scholar
Isserow, Jessica and Klein, Colin. 2017. Hypocrisy and Moral Authority. The Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, 12.2: 191222.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Piovarchy, Adam. Forthcoming. Hypocrisy, Standing to Blame and Second-Personal Authority. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly.Google Scholar
Shaham, Talia. 2011. Is There a Paradox of Moral Complaint? Utilitas, 23.3: 344–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smilansky, Saul. 2006. The Paradox of Moral Complaint. Utilitas, 18.3: 284290.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smilansky, Saul. 2013. The Paradox of Moral Complaint: A Reply to Shaham. Utilitas, 25.2: 277282.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smilansky, Saul. 2020. Should We Sacrifice the Utilitarians First? Philosophical Quarterly, 70.281: 850–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Todd, Patrick. 2019. A Unified Account of the Moral Standing to Blame. Noûs, 53.2: 347–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tognazzini, Neal. Unpublished Manuscript. On Losing One's Moral Voice.Google Scholar
Wallace, Richard. 2010. Hypocrisy, Moral Address, and the Equal Standing of Persons. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 38.4: 307–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar