Skip to main content
Log in

Scientific Modeling Versus Engineering Modeling: Similarities and Dissimilarities

  • Article
  • Published:
Journal for General Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article aims to answer what I call the “constitution question of engineering modeling”: in virtue of what does an engineering model model its target system? To do so, I will offer a category-theoretic, structuralist account of design, using the olog framework. Drawing on this account, I will conclude that engineering and scientific models are not only cognitively but also representationally indistinguishable. I will finally propose an axiological criterion for distinguishing scientific from engineering modeling.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The philosophical literature on scientific representation is so vast and growing that I can mention only the surveys. Frigg and Nguyen (2017) have examined almost all views. Chakravartty (2010) has categorized them into the two groups of informational and functional theories. Boesch (2019) has recently developed a unifying picture of functional or agent-based accounts. For a brief sketch, see Frigg and Nguyen (2018).

  2. Among them are the use plan analysis of Houkes and Vermaas (2010), the explanationist account of van Eck (2016) and Galle’s (1999) action-based account in which the conception of design representation has a key role. Besides philosophical accounts, design theorists also have suggested several design theories, e.g. the concept-knowledge (C-K) theory of Hatchuel and Weil (2009), the Functional-Behavior-Structure account of Gero and Kannengiesser (2004) and the Functional Basis method of Stone and Wood (2000).

  3. Many thinkers attack such a distinction. For more on this, see footnote 20.

  4. For instance, Ubbink argues that “[t]he essential thing is that a model represents an object or matters of fact in virtue of its structure; so an object is a model ... of matters of fact if, and only if, their structures are isomorphic” (Ubbink 1960, 302), or French holds that “[e]ach of these claims [i.e. isomorphsim is not necessary for representation, isomorphism is not sufficient for representation and models denote and do not resemble] will be questioned and I will conclude by suggesting that, through appropriate modifications, a form of isomorphism [i.e. partial isomorphism] can serve to underpin representation in both the arts and science” (French 2003, 1473).

  5. The theories deploying non-symmetric morphisms such as homomorphism would meet the first objection (Bartels 2006). For more details about structuralism on representation, see Frigg and Nguyen (2017).

  6. Suárez’s account is deflationary in the sense that it aims not to answer the constitution question, but just to provide necessary conditions.

  7. To avoid Newman’s objection, the set A is not unconstrained (Bueno 2017). Otherwise, we can always ascribe a structure, being morphic to the model, to the target. As such, the intentional acts merely would carry out the representational burden.

  8. For a detailed defense of a hybrid account, see Bueno and French (2011).

  9. Galle calls the communication of the designer with herself “self-communication” (Galle 1999, 63).

  10. For more details, see Awodey (2010).

  11. Since being aspect is a functional relation, we cannot simply denote the aspect by “has” (Spivak and Kent 2012, 4).

  12. The mathematical notions to be introduced hereafter are not present in the olog framework.

  13. The olog language has been used in materials design studies. For example, see Giesa et al. (2012), Wong et al. (2012), and Cranford and Buehler (2012).

  14. Of course, there are some minor differences between the two kinds of modeling as reconstructed above. For instance, while the structures involved in scientific modeling are set-theoretic, the structures employed in engineering modeling are category-theoretic. These slight differences, however, are not substantial enough to fundamentally differentiate the two kinds of modeling. For in both cases the source and target of modeling are structures, the relation between them is structural, and intentional aspects matter for such relation. More importantly, The Elementary Theory of the Category of Sets (ECST) provides us with a machinery to derive set-theoretic notions from category-theoretic ones (Lawvere 1964).

  15. Emphases added in the above quotation illustrate this point.

  16. The constructive nature of target systems in high energy physics has already been discussed in the science studies literature (Galison et al. 1997; Pickering 1999).

  17. For a very brief history, see Weinberg (2004).

  18. Modern books on quantum field theory usually discuss the standard model (Schwartz 2014; Peskin 2018). For a more introductory book, see Goldberg (2017). The detection of the Higgs at the LHC has been narrated by Gagnon (2016).

  19. This does not mean that pure and applied scientists produce just, respectively, science and design representation. These given productions are merely final ones.

  20. Here it is taken for granted that there is a (though not clear-cut) distinction between science and engineering modeling. But there are many science and technology studies practitioners who deny any distinction between science and engineering (or between basic and applied science), advancing hybrid concepts such as technoscience (for more on this, see Channell 2017). For them, contextual (e.g. social, historical and political) factors have a key role in determining the meaning of the terms associated with these concepts (Latour 1987; Nordmann et al. 2011; Pielke 2012). There have recently been some attempts to reconcile these two approaches (e.g. Kant and Kerr 2019). The question whether the account proposed here would also do such a thing is interesting, but is beyond the scope of this article.

  21. I thank two anonymous referees for pointing out this worry to me.

References

  • Anscombe, G. (1957). Intention. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ashammakhi, N., Elkhammas, E., & Hasan, A. (2019). Translating advances in organ-on-a-chip technology for supporting organs. Journal of Biomedical Materials Research Part B: Applied Biomaterials, 107(6), 2006–2018.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ATLAS Collaboration et al. (2012). Latest results from atlas higgs search. Press statement, ATLAS Updates.

  • Awodey, S. (2010). Category theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bale, B., & Sharp, D. (2013). Concorde: Supersonic speedbird. Horncastle: Mortons Media Group Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bartels, A. (2006). Defending the structural concept of representation. THEORIA. Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia, 21(1), 7–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boesch, B. (2019). Resolving and understanding differences between agent-based accounts of scientific representation. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 50, 195–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boon, M. (2006). How science is applied in technology. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 20(01), 27–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boon, M., & Knuuttila, T. (2009). Models as epistemic tools in engineering sciences. In A. Meijers (Ed.), Philosophy of technology and engineering sciences, handbook of the philosophy of science (pp. 693–726). Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bueno, O. (2017). Overcoming Newman’s objection. In EPSA15 selected papers (pp. 3–12). Springer.

  • Bueno, O., & Colyvan, M. (2011). An inferential conception of the application of mathematics. Noûs, 45(2), 345–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bueno, O., & French, S. (2011). How theories represent. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62(4), 857–894.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1966). Technology as applied science. Technology and Culture, 7(3), 329–347.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Callender, C., & Cohen, J. (2006). There is no special problem about scientific representation. Theoria. Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia, 21(1), 67–85.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1983). How the laws of physics lie., Clarendon paperbacks Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1999). The dappled world: A study of the boundaries of science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (2010). Informational versus functional theories of scientific representation. Synthese, 172(2), 197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Channell, D. F. (2017). A history of technoscience: Erasing the boundaries between science and technology. New York: Taylor & Francis.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cranford, S. W., & Buehler, M. J. (2012). Universality-diversity paradigm: Music, materiomics, and category theory. In Biomateriomics (pp. 109–169). Springer.

  • Drake, F., & Purvis, M. (2001). The effect of supersonic transports on the global environment: A debate revisited. Science, Technology, & Human Values, 26(4), 501–528.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fletcher, S. C. (2018). On representational capacities, with an application to general relativity. Foundations of Physics, 50, 228–249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franzen, N., van Harten, W. H., Retèl, V. P., Loskill, P., van den Eijnden-van Raaij, A., & Ijzerman, M. J. (2019). Impact of organ-on-a-chip technology on pharmaceutical R&D costs. Drug Discovery Today, 24, 1720–1724.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • French, S. (2003). A model-theoretic account of representation (or, i don’t know much about art but i know it involves isomorphism). Philosophy of Science, 70(5), 1472–1483.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R., & Nguyen, J. (2017). Models and representation. In L. Magnani & T. Bertolotti (Eds.), Springer handbook of model-based science (pp. 49–102). Cham: Springer International Publishing.

  • Frigg, R., & Nguyen, J. (2018). Scientific representation. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2018 ed.). Stanford: Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R., & Nguyen, J. (2019). Mirrors without warnings. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02222-9.

  • Gagnon, P. (2016). Who cares about particle physics? Making sense of the Higgs boson, the Large Hadron Collider and CERN. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Galison, P., et al. (1997). Image and logic: A material culture of microphysics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galle, P. (1999). Design as intentional action: A conceptual analysis. Design Studies, 20(1), 57–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gelfert, A. (2016). How to do science with models: A philosophical primer. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gero, J. S., & Kannengiesser, U. (2004). The situated function-behaviour-structure framework. Design Studies, 25(4), 373–391.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. N. (2004). How models are used to represent reality. Philosophy of Science, 71(5), 742–752.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. N. (2010a). An agent-based conception of models and scientific representation. Synthese, 172(2), 269.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. N. (2010b). Scientific perspectivism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giesa, T., Spivak, D. I., & Buehler, M. J. (2012). Category theory based solution for the building block replacement problem in materials design. Advanced Engineering Materials, 14(9), 810–817.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldberg, D. (2017). The standard model in a nutshell. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grunwald, A. (2009). Technology assessment: Concepts and methods. In A. Meijers (Ed.), Philosophy of technology and engineering sciences (pp. 1103–1146)., Handbook of the philosophy of science Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Grunwald, A. (2011). Responsible innovation: Bringing together technology assessment, applied ethics, and sts research. Enterprise and Work Innovation Studies, 31, 10–9.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grunwald, A. (2015). Technology assessment and design for values. In J. van den Hoven, P. E. Vermaas, & I. van de Poel (Eds.), Handbook of ethics, values, and technological design: Sources, theory, values and application domains (pp. 67–86). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Grunwald, A. (2018). Technology assessment in practice and theory. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1983). Representing and intervening: Introductory topics in the philosophy of natural science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hatchuel, A., & Weil, B. (2009). Ck design theory: An advanced formulation. Research in Engineering Design, 19(4), 181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Houkes, W., & Vermaas, P. E. (2010). Technical functions: On the use and design of artefacts (Vol. 1). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hughes, R. I. (1997). Models and representation. Philosophy of Science, 64, S325–S336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kagan, S. (1998). Rethinking intrinsic value. The Journal of Ethics, 2(4), 277–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, V., & Kerr, E. (2019). Taking stock of engineering epistemology: Multidisciplinary perspectives. Philosophy & Technology, 32(4), 685–726.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knuuttila, T. (2011). Modelling and representing: An artefactual approach to model-based representation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 42(2), 262–271.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. M. (1983). Two distinctions in goodness. The Philosophical Review, 92(2), 169–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kroes, P. (2002). Design methodology and the nature of technical artefacts. Design Studies, 23(3), 287–302.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B. (1987). Science in action: How to follow scientists and engineers through society. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawvere, F. W. (1964). An elementary theory of the category of sets. Proceedings of the National academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 52(6), 1506.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (1993). The aim and structure of applied research. Erkenntnis, 38(1), 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nordmann, A., Radder, H., & Schiemann, G. (2011). Science after the end of science? An introduction to the epochal break thesis. In A. Nordmann, H. Radder, & G. Schiemann (Eds.), Science transformed? (pp. 1–15). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, J. (1992). The varieties of intrinsic value. The Monist, 75(2), 119–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Otto, K., & Wood, K. (2001). Product design: Techniques in reverse engineering and new product development. Upper Saddle River: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Otto, K. N., & Wood, K. L. (1998). Product evolution: A reverse engineering and redesign methodology. Research in Engineering Design, 10(4), 226–243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peskin, M. E. (2018). An introduction to quantum field theory. Boca Raton: CRC Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pickering, A. (1999). Constructing quarks: A sociological history of particle physics., Physics, history and sociology of science Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pielke, R. (2012). Basic research as a political symbol. Minerva, 50(3), 339–361.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Poznic, M. (2016). Modeling organs with organs on chips: Scientific representation and engineering design as modeling relations. Philosophy & Technology, 29(4), 357–371.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ramsden, J. M. (1974, April 11). Up to date with Rolls-Royce Bristol. FLIGHT International, 463–466.

  • Roll-Hansen, N. (2017). A historical perspective on the distinction between basic and applied science. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 48(4), 535–551.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, M. D. (2014). Quantum field theory and the standard model. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. (1968). The sciences of the artificial. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smale, A. (1979, September 22). Fuel costs kill second generation of concordes. Sarasota Herald-Tribune, 13A. https://news.google.com/newspapers?id=Q-0cAAAAIBAJ&pg=6914,3256355.

  • Sontheimer-Phelps, A., Hassell, B. A., & Ingber, D. E. (2019). Modelling cancer in microfluidic human organs-on-chips. Nature Reviews Cancer, 19, 65–81. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41568-018-0104-6.

  • Spivak, D. I., & Kent, R. E. (2012). Ologs: A categorical framework for knowledge representation. PLoS ONE, 7(1), e24274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stone, R. B., & Wood, K. L. (2000). Development of a functional basis for design. Journal of Mechanical Design, 122(4), 359–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M. (2003). Scientific representation: Against similarity and isomorphism. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 17(3), 225–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M. (2004). An inferential conception of scientific representation. Philosophy of Science, 71(5), 767–779.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M. (2010). Scientific representation. Philosophy Compass, 5(1), 91–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M. (2015). Deflationary representation, inference, and practice. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 49, 36–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, L. (2012). Observation of a new particle with a mass of 125 gev. CMS Public Website, CERN.

  • Ubbink, J. (1960). Model, description and knowledge. Synthese, 12(2), 302.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van de Poel, I. (2009). Values in engineering design. In A. Meijers (Ed.), Philosophy of technology and engineering sciences (pp. 973–1006)., Handbook of the philosophy of science Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Van den Hoven, J., Vermaas, P., & Van de Poel, I. (2015). Handbook of ethics, values and technological design. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Eck, D. (2016). The philosophy of science and engineering design. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. (2010). Scientific representation: Paradoxes of perspective. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vermaas, P., Kroes, P., van de Poel, I., Franssen, M., & Houkes, W. (2011). A philosophy of technology: From technical artefacts to sociotechnical systems. Synthesis Lectures on Engineers, Technology, and Society, 6(1), 1–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vincenti, W. G., et al. (1990). What engineers know and how they know it (Vol. 141). Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, S. (2004). The making of the standard model. The European Physical Journal C-Particles and Fields, 34(1), 5–13.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wong, J. Y., McDonald, J., Taylor-Pinney, M., Spivak, D. I., Kaplan, D. L., & Buehler, M. J. (2012). Materials by design: Merging proteins and music. Nano Today, 7(6), 488–495.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wu, S. L. (2014). Brief history for the search and discovery of the higgs particlea personal perspective. International Journal of Modern Physics A, 29(27), 1430062.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yaghmaie, A. (2017). How to characterise pure and applied science. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 31(2), 133–149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zhang, B., Korolj, A., Lai, B. F. L., & Radisic, M. (2018). Advances in organ-on-a-chip engineering. Nature Reviews Materials, 3(8), 257.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The paper has benefited greatly from valuable suggestions of two anonymous referees and the editors of this journal; I sincerely thank them. Thanks to Karim Thébault for reading a draft of this paper and providing useful comments. This article is a part of a project that has received funding from the Iran National Science Foundation (INSF) Grant number 95835408.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Aboutorab Yaghmaie.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Yaghmaie, A. Scientific Modeling Versus Engineering Modeling: Similarities and Dissimilarities. J Gen Philos Sci 52, 455–474 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-020-09541-3

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-020-09541-3

Keywords

Navigation