Skip to main content
Log in

On the Explanatory Power of Dispositional Realism

  • Article
  • Published:
Journal for General Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The article focuses on the unifying and explanatory power of the selective realism defended by Anjan Chakravartty. Our main aim is twofold. First, we critically analyse the purported synthesis between entity realism and structural realism offered by the author. We give reasons to think that this unification is an inconvenient marriage. In the second step, we deal with certain controversial aspects of the intended unification among three metaphysical concepts: causation, laws of nature and natural kinds. After pointing out that Chakravartty’s conception of laws is a plausible view that a scientific realist might endorse, we contend, on the contrary, that the concept of natural kind is dispensable in the framework of Chakravartty’s realism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In recent writings, Nancy Cartwright has defended a conception of laws based on the postulation of powers or capacities. Laws arise as causal regularities that emerge from the nomological machines. These consist of particular arrangements formed by the contribution of causal powers whose canonical effects are combined in the context of the experiment (Cartwright 2013). Laws, understood in this way, have the function of predicting facts, whether singular occurrence or a range of events; besides, they do not need to be universal or deterministic. In her view, causal laws are compatible with the contingency in the world, they can be permissive and limited, that is, admit events that are not covered by law (Cartwright and Merlussi 2018). Cartwright continues emphasizing the role of causality in science. She wrote “This paper [2009] was one of the early forays in a growing movement to reinstate causality as a respectable member of our ontology” (Cartwright 2009, 5). Furthermore, she seems to have subordinated the role of explanation in favour of prediction as an important goal of laws.

  2. Chakravartty acknowledges that both Kitcher and Psillos have advanced criteria to identify the parts of a theory that are preserved in successor theories. In effect, Kitcher distinguishes between “working posits (the putative referents of terms that occur in problem-solving schemata) and presuppositional posits (those entities that apparently have to exist if the instances of the schemata are to be true)” (1993, 149). From his part, Psillos makes a difference between idle and essentially contributing constituents (1999, 108ff). But, in Chakravartty’s opinion, although they are oriented towards the right objective, both leave their approach open to the charge of rationalization post hoc. His own strategy, on the other hand, has the advantage of improving on the weaknesses of those proposals (Chakravartty 2007, 46).

  3. The bending of light is another interesting example. Einstein’s General Relativity Theory published in 1915 predicted the phenomenon of the bending of light near a massive body. The light beams would not follow a Euclidian straight line but would show some bending. This hypothesis explained a number of anomalies that threatened Newtonian theory. In 1915 the bending of light should be considered an auxiliary property. But in 1919, when an eclipse occurred, astronomers were able to establish the bending of light rays near the Sun from two observatories located on Earth. So, if we apply the Chakravartty’s classification to this case, we will find that what was previously considered an auxiliary property postulated by the General Relativity Theory, after 1919 entered the set of detection properties.

  4. We thank an anonymous reviewer for providing this insightful comment.

  5. We believe that the notion of particulars as cohesive groups of dispositions is at least a constitutive part of Chakravartty’s conception of dispositional realism, although perhaps it is not a feature of all dispositional views. Chakravartty does think of objects as bundles of powers. Thus, there is an intimate connection between the dispositions that compose particulars and the properties they exhibit when manifesting themselves.

References

  • Bird, A., & Tobin, E. (2018). Natural kinds. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/natural-kinds/.

  • Boyd, R. (1984). The current status of the realism debate. In J. Leplin (Ed.), Scientific realism (pp. 41–82). Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1991). Realism, anti-foundationalism and the enthusiasm for natural kinds. Philosophical Studies, 61, 127–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1983). How the laws of physics lie. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (2009). How to do things with causes. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 83(2), 5–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N., & Merlussi, P. (2018). Are laws of nature consistent with contingency? In W. Ott & L. Patto (Eds.), Laws of nature, an anthology (pp. 221–244). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (1998). Semirealism. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 29, 391–408.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (2007). A metaphysics for scientific realism: Knowing the unobservable. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (2013). Dispositions for scientific realism. In R. Groff & J. Greco (Eds.), Powers and capacities in philosophy: The new aristotelianism (pp. 113–127). New York: Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (2017). Scientific ontology: Integrating naturalized metaphysics and voluntarist epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (2020). Acerca de la Relación entre el Realismo Científico y la Metafísica Científica. In B. Borge & N. Gentile (Eds.), La ciencia y el mundo inobservable: Discusiones contemporáneas en torno al realismo científico (pp. 99–121). Eudeba: Buenos Aires.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duhem, P. (1906). The aim and structure of physical theory, trans. P. Wiener, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1954.

  • Ellis, B. (2001). Scientific essentialism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • French, S. (1999). Models and mathematics in physics: The role of group theory. In J. Butterfield & C. Pagonis (Eds.), From physics to philosophy (pp. 187–207). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1983). Representing and Intervening. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1991). A tradition of natural kinds. Philosophical Studies, 61, 109–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Howson, C. (2000). Hume’s problem. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1993). The advancement of science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J. (1998). What is structural realism? Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 29, 409–424.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2002). Baseball, pessimistic inductions and the turnover fallacy. Analysis, 62, 281–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1981). A confutation of convergent realism. Philosophy of Science, 48, 19–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1984). Explaining the success of science: Beyond epistemic realism and relativism. In J. Cushing et al (Eds.), Science and reality (pp. 83–105). Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leplin, J. (1981). Truth and scientific progress. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 12(4), 269–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leplin, J. (Ed.). (1984). Scientific Realism. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leplin, J. (1997). A novel defense of scientific realism. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levin, M. (1984). What kind of explanation is truth? In J. Leplin (Ed.), Scientific realism (pp. 124–139). Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, P. (2001). Why the pessimistic induction is a fallacy. Synthese, 129(3), 371–380.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Magnus, P. D., & Callender, C. (2004). Realist ennui and the base rate fallacy. Philosophy of Science, 71(3), 320–338.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maxwell, G. (1962). The ontological status of theoretical entities. In H. Feigl & G. Maxwell (Eds.), Scientific explanation, space, and time: minnesota studies in the philosophy of science (pp. 181–192). Minnesota: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maxwell, G. (1970). Theories, perception, and structural realism. In R. G. Colodny (Ed.), The nature and function of scientific theories (pp. 3–34). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. (1882). A system of logic, ratiocinative and inductive (Eight Edition). New York: Harper and Brothers Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Musgrave, A. (1988). The ultimate argument for scientific realism. In R. Nola (Ed.), Relativism and realism in sciences (pp. 229–252). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Poincaré, H. (1902). La science et l’hypothese. Paris: E. Flammarion.

    Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (1999). Scientific realism: How science tracks truth. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (2002). Causation and explanation. Montreal: McGill University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (2006). Thinking about the ultimate argument for realism. In C. Cheyne & J. Worrall (Eds.), Rationality & reality: Essays in honour of Alan Musgrave (pp. 133–156). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (2011). Moving molecules above the scientific horizon: On perrin’s case for realism. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 42, 339–363.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). Philosophical papers: Mathematics, matter and method (Vol. 1). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. (1969). Ontological relativity and other essays. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1927). The analysis of matter. London: George Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saatsi, J. T. (2005). On pessimistic induction and two fallacies. Philosophy of Science., 72(5), 1088–1098.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smart, J. J. C. (1963). Philosophy and scientific realism. London: RKP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swoyer, C. (1982). The nature of natural laws. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 60, 202–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. C. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. C. (1989). Laws and symmetry. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Weyl, H. (1963). Philosophy of mathematics and natural science. New York: Atheneum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Worrall, J. (1997; 1989). Structural realism: The best of both worlds? In D. Papineau (Ed.), The philosophy of science (pp. 139–165). Oxford University Press.

  • Zahar, E. (1996). Poincaré’s structural realism and his logic of discovery. In J. L. Greffe, G. Heinzmann & K. Lorenz (Eds.), Henri Poincaré science and philosophy (pp. 45-68). Berlin: Academie Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zamora Bonilla, J. P. (2019). Realism versus anti-realism: Philosophical problem or scientific concern? Synthese, 196, 3961–3977.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nélida Gentile.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

We would like to thank Professors David Miller and Rodolfo Gaeta for their deep comments on an earlier version of this article, as well as the suggestions from the editorial staff of the journal. We are especially grateful to two anonymous referees for their insightful observations on some important issues of the work. All the criticisms and suggestions have been of great help to improve our manuscript.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Gentile, N., Lucero, S. On the Explanatory Power of Dispositional Realism. J Gen Philos Sci (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-020-09539-x

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-020-09539-x

Keywords

Navigation