Skip to main content
Log in

Beyond Due Diligence: the Human Rights Corporation

  • Published:
Human Rights Review Aims and scope Submit manuscript

A Correction to this article was published on 25 February 2022

This article has been updated

Abstract

The modern corporation offers significant potential to contribute to the human rights project, in part because it is free from the challenges posed by national sovereignty. That promise has begun to be realized in businesses practicing corporate due diligence with regard to the human rights of persons involved in or affected by those enterprises. Yet due diligence preserves the self-seeking orientation of the conventional corporation and seeks only to protect itself from committing human rights abuses. This approach, typified by the UN Guiding Principles on Business and Human Rights, does not address background conditions for and root causes of vulnerability to human rights abuses. My alternative, the human rights corporation, takes an other-regarding orientation that advances human rights within the corporation and in its human, social, economic, and natural environments. It moves beyond the due diligence carrot-and-stick model to a model in which the corporation produces not only goods and services but also human rights consciousness and practice as well.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Change history

Notes

  1. UNCTAD, World Investment Report 2013 (Geneva 2013):135.

  2. International Labour Organization, Decent Work in Global Supply Chains (2016), http://www.ilo.org/ilc/ILCSessions/105/reports/reports-to-the-conference/WCMS_468097/lang--en/index.htm

  3. This notion includes small and medium enterprises as well as business enterprises owned or controlled by the state, or that receive substantial state support.

  4. See, e.g., Crane et al. (2008) and Néron and Norman (2008).

  5. UN Doc. HR/PUB/11/04 (2011) [www.ohchr.org/Documents/Publications/GuidingPrinciplesBusinessHR_EN.pdf]

  6. The movement began with the1984 draft UN Code of Conduct on Transnational Corporations.

  7. See Favotto and Kollman (2020) in this issue.

  8. Other authors intimate grounds for corporate human rights advancement but none develops such grounds in the direction I propose: corporate advocacy for human rights. Wettstein (2015:171) argues for “positive contributions to human rights improvement rather than merely with negative impacts and nonviolation.” According to Wood (2012:63), a corporation has a “responsibility to exercise leverage even though [...] [it] did nothing to contribute to the situation” if the threat to human rights is “substantial,” if it can “make a contribution to ameliorating the situation,” and if it can do so “at modest cost.” And Mende (2017:9) imagines an identity of corporate self-interest and human rights commitment: “Dient die menschenrechtliche Verantwortung auch dem Selbstinteresse oder ist sie zumindest damit vereinbar, erhöht das die Bereitschaft von Unternehmen, entsprechenden Forderungen nachzukommen.”

  9. For this paricular conception of human rights, see Gregg (2012) and Gregg (2016).

  10. See e.g., the United Nations “Guiding Principles on Business and Human Rights” (https://www.ohchr.org/documents/publications/GuidingprinciplesBusinesshr_eN.pdf); it outlines a “corporate responsibility to respect human rights.”

  11. Friedman (1962:133) correspondingly claimed that “there is one and only one social responsibility of business to use its resources and engage in activities designed to increase its profits” as long as it “engages in open and free competition without deception and fraud.”

  12. To be sure, enterprises may be “held liable for acts committed abroad by their subsidiaries” (CLTP 2009:6).

  13. For one of the Reports on Corporate Law Tools: see https://www.ohchr.org/EN/Issues/Business/Pages/SRSGTransCorpIndex.aspx

  14. There are no specific “restrictions on circulating shareholder proposals which deal with impacts on non-shareholders, including human rights impacts” (CLTP 2009:18).

  15. As I argue from various perspectives, in different contexts, and across a range of goals in Gregg (2012, 2016, 2017, 2019, 2020).

  16. This defensive position characterizes the Business and Human Rights model in general. See, e.g., the 2015 United Nations document Transforming our World: The 2030 Agenda for Sustainable Development (https://www.unfpa.org/resources/transforming-our-world-2030-agenda-sustainable-development), which would foster a “dynamic and well-functioning business sector, while protecting labour rights and environmental and health standards in accordance with relevant international standards” (para. 67).

  17. As Ruggie (2017:14) emphasizes in the next sentence: direct violators “should provide for or cooperate in” remediation; corporations not themselves violators but linked through a business relationship to violators should “exercise leverage to prevent or mitigate the harm.”

  18. In Gregg (2016) I confront the contradiction between human rights and nation state sovereignty by cultivating another institution that might advance human rights independently of, even against, the nation state: a social movement of self-selected citizens who advocate for the inclusion of human rights in the national constitution. They do so as a metaphorical “human rights state.”

  19. I analyze corporate due diligence as a particular form of self-seeking behavior marked by instrumental logic. I distinguish it from the human rights corporation as a form of other-regarding behavior oriented by communicative logic. This distinction reflects a rich tradition of differentiating among various ways in which humans orient their behavior for different tasks. My own framing begins with Weber’s (1975) distinction between two types of “ethic.” An “ethic of responsibility” (Verantwortungsethik) is concerned with achieving the best means to a given end. It is a technical matter of calculating how to achieve a desired consequence. An “ethic of conviction” (Gesinnungsethik) focuses on the end itself. It is driven by value-commitments, “ultimate decisions through which the soul … chooses its own fate”—or, for my purposes, ultimate decisions through which a political community, including its private sector, collectively decides the standards of decent treatment of individuals (Weber 1949:18). I then connect Weber’s “ethic of responsibility” to Horkheimer and Adorno’s (1972) notion of an instrumental reason oriented solely on self-interest and self-preservation. And I connect Weber’s “ethic of conviction” to the kind of reason that Horkheimer (1993:21) describes as seeking “human emancipation” from domination and oppression. People deploy such reason when they attempt to be “producers of their own historical form of life.” Then I tie this conception to Habermas’s (1990:32) depiction of a capacity for the moral evaluation of social and political practices. He calls this capacity “communicative rationality.” It facilitates individuals’ participation in achieving mutual understanding within their political community about its proper ends. And it identifies bureaucratic as well as economic imperatives that undermine civic participation and common ends. Where Habermas (1987) speaks of the instrumental reason of strategic forms of social action oriented on achieving goals, I speak of corporate due diligence. Where Habermas (1998, ch. 7) speaks of a communicative rationality of actors freely coordinating their behavior in pursuit of consensually shared goals embraced by all members as reasonable or worthy, I speak of a human rights corporation. On the one hand, the instrumental logic of due diligence cannot generate the solidarity between a corporation and its stakeholders that the communicative logic of human rights advocacy can. On the other hand, the demands on participants of first achieving and then maintaining agreement on corporate advocacy of human rights would be significant and cumbersome. Participants would always confront forces that encourage them to relax that agreement in favor of the less demanding program of corporate due diligence.

  20. I use the terms instrumental reason and means-end rationality synonymously; and the terms value-rationality and communicative reason synonymously.

  21. The “lifeworld” refers to the everyday world shared intersubjectively by members of a community, for example in family life, in school, in culture and in informal social interactions, but not in formal economic institutions or in administrative bureaucracies. According to Habermas (1987:154), the kind of rationality that orients behavior in the economic system (as well as in the bureaucratic–administrative system) does not require (indeed, does not allow) “norm-conforming attitudes and identity-forming social memberships.”

  22. This does not mean that all corporate norms are oriented in terms of communicative rationality.

  23. In Gregg (2012) and (2016) I pursue at length the question of how best to understand the source and proper scope of human rights. My argument here pursues a narrower question: What is specific to the possible corporate advocacy of human rights?

  24. Comprising the Universal Declaration of Human Rights and the main instruments through which it has been codified (the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights and the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights).

  25. Raising the question can corporations be partly responsible for global (and not just national) human rights welfare?

  26. Note that “poverty is not considered a human rights violation or a breach of international law” (Meyersfeld 2017:180).

  27. In the context of corporate accountability, Bernaz (2020) advocates regulation and enforcement of this sort.

  28. Human rights advocates cannot realistically expect states to foster human rights–oriented cultures, as I argue in Gregg (2012). This inspiration for this essay is the intuition that some corporations today might themselves undertake to revise their corporate culture in the ways I imagine an HRC.

  29. UNGPs, para. 21: corporate communications about operations that endanger human rights should “not pose risks to affected stakeholders, personnel or to legitimate requirements of commercial confidentiality.”

  30. https://www.unglobalcompact.org/

  31. In Gregg (2018) I argue that artificial intelligence is similarly incapable.

  32. A case from 1886 states that the Fourteenth Amendment to the U.S. Constitution (which reads in part: “nor shall any state ... deny to any person within its jurisdiction the equal protection of the laws”) “applies to … corporations” (Santa Clara County v. Southern Pacific R. Co., 118 U.S. 394 (1886)). This case interprets the term any person” now to include a corporation! And a case from 1910 states that the following legal proposition is “no longer open to discussion”: “That the corporation is a person, within the meaning of the Fourteenth Amendment” (Southern Railway Co. v. Greene, 216 U.S. 400 (1910)). Note that the American model “has been aggressively exported through contemporary rounds of economic globalization” (Barkan 2013:42).

  33. Hence my argument, in the section titled “The Instrumental Logic of Due Diligence in Contrast to the Communicative Logic of Advocacy” for human rights as social and economic rights championing material equality.

  34. See note 16.

  35. Another means to mediating this structural conflict would be an array of outside organizations that could provide support to an HRC, as I show in the section titled “Motivation and External Support for a Human Rights Corporation.”

  36. Sen (2001) analyzes poverty in part as a person’s lack of political rights and choice.

  37. https://www.nbim.no/en/the-fund/responsible-investment/exclusion-of-companies/

  38. https://www.corporatebenchmark.org/

  39. https://www.business-humanrights.org/en/knowthechain-benchmarking-2016

  40. See Brodie (2012).

  41. https://www.humanrights.dk/

  42. https://www.globalreporting.org/Pages/default.aspx

  43. But consider contemporary developments that appear somewhat compatible even if much less ambitious, e.g., Jena McGregor, Washington Post, 19 August 2019: “Group of top CEOs says maximizing shareholder profits no longer can be the primary goal of corporations” at https://www.washingtonpost.com/business/2019/08/19/lobbying-group-powerful-ceos-is-rethinking-how-it-defines-corporations-purpose/

  44. As examples, see Posner (2014) and Hopgood (2013).

  45. See Sikkink (2017) and Gregg (2012), for example.

References

  • Bardach E, Kagan R (eds) (1982) Social regulation: Strategies for reform. San Francisco, Institute for Contemporary Studies

    Google Scholar 

  • Barkan J (2013) Corporate sovereignty: Law and government under capitalism. Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press

  • Baumann-Pauly D, Nolan J (eds) (2016) Business and human rights: From principles to practice. Abingdon, Routledge

  • Bernaz N (2017) Business and human rights: History, law and policy: Bridging the accountability gap. Abingdon, Routledge

  • Bernaz N (2020) Conceptualizing corporate accountability in international law: Models for a business and human rights treaty. Human Rights Review (forthcoming)

  • Brenkert G.G. (1992) Private corporations and public welfare. Public Affairs Quarterly 6:155–168

  • Brodie M (2012) Pushing the boundaries: The role of national human rights institutions in operationalizing the ‘protect, respect and remedy’ framework. In Mares R (ed) The UN guiding principles on business and human rights: Foundations and implementation. Leiden, Martinus Nijhoff Publishers:245-272

  • Corporate Law Tools Project [CLTP] (2009) Jurisdiction: United Kingdom. Mandate of Special Representative of the Secretary-General on Issue of Human Rights and Transnational Corporations and Other Business Enterprises. http://www.reports-and-materials.org/Corporate-law-firms-advise-Ruggie-23-Mar-2009.pdf

  • Crane A, Matten D, Moon J (2008) Corporations and citizenship. New York, Cambridge University Press

  • DeGeorge R (1993) Competing with integrity in international business. New York, Oxford University Press

  • Donaldson T (1989) The ethics of international business. New York: Oxford University Press

  • Favotto A, Kollman K (2020) When rights enter the CSR field: British firms' engagement with human rights and the UN Guiding Principles. Human Rights Review (forthcoming)

  • Friedman M (1962) Capitalism and freedom. Chicago, University of Chicago Press

  • Friedman M (1970) The social responsibility of business is to increase its profits. The New York Times Magazine, September 13:32-33, 122-124

  • Gregg B (2012) Human rights as social construction. New York, Cambridge University Press

  • Gregg B (2016) The human rights state: Justice within and beyond sovereign nations. Philadelphia, University of Pennsylvania Press

  • Gregg B (2017) The human rights state: theoretical challenges, empirical deployments: Reply to my critics. International Journal of Human Rights 21 (3):359-385

  • Gregg B (2018) The coming political challenges of artificial intelligence. Digital Culture & Society 4 (1):157-180

  • Gregg B (2019) Indigeneity as social construct and political tool. Human Rights Quarterly 41 (4):823-848

  • Gregg B (2020) The indigenous rights state. Ratio Juris 33 (1):98-116

  • Habermas J (1987) The theory of communicative action, vol. 2: Lifeworld and system: A critique of functionalist reason. Boston, Beacon Press

  • Habermas J (1990) Moral consciousness and communicative action. Cambridge: MIT Press

  • Habermas J (1998) On the pragmatics of communication. Cambridge, MIT Press

  • Heath J (2014) Morality, competition and the firm. New York, Oxford University Press

  • Herzog L (2018) Reclaiming the system: Moral responsibility, divided labour, and the role of organizations in society. Oxford, Oxford University Press

  • Hopgood S (2013) The endtimes of human rights. Ithaca, Cornell University Press, 2013

  • Horkheimer M (1993) Between philosophy and social science. Cambridge, MIT Press

  • Horkheimer M, Adorno T.W. (1972) [1944] Dialectic of enlightenment. New York: Seabury

  • Hsieh N.-H (2004) The obligations of transnational corporations: Rawlsian justice and the duty of assistance. Business Ethics Quarterly 14:643–661

  • Isiksel T (2016) The rights of man and the rights of the man-made: Corporations and human rights. Human Rights Quarterly 38:294-349

  • Laufer W (2003) Social accountability and corporate green washing. Journal of Business Ethics 43:253-261

  • Li Y, McKernan J (2017) ‘Achieved not given’: human rights, critique and the need for strong foundations. International Journal of Human Rights 21 (3):252-269

  • Mansell S (2013) Shareholder theory and Kant’s ‘Duty of Beneficence.’ Journal of Business Ethics 117 (2013):583-599

  • Matten D, Crane A (2005) Corporate citizenship: Toward an extended theoretical conceptualization. Academy of Management Review 30:166–179

  • McMahon C (1994) Authority and democracy: A general theory of government and management. Princeton, Princeton University Press

  • Mende J (2017) “Unternehmen als gesellschaftlice Akteure: Die unternehmerische Verantwortung für Menschenrechte zwischen privater und öffentlicher Sphäre. MenschenRechtsMagazin 22:5-17

  • Meyersfeld B (2017) Committing the crime of poverty. In: Rodríguez-Garavito C (ed) Business and human rights: Beyond the end of the beginning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 173-185

  • Moyn S (2018) Not enough: Human rights in an unequal world. Cambridge, Harvard University Press

  • Néron P.-Y., Norman W (2008) Citizenship, Inc. Do we really want businesses to be good corporate citizens? Business Ethics Quarterly 18:1–26

  • O’Neill O (2001) Agents of justice. Metaphilosophy 32:180–195

  • Pettit P (2015) Two Fallacies about Corporations. In: Rangan S (ed) Performance and progress: Essays on capitalism, business, and society. Oxford, Oxford University Press:379-394

  • Posner E (2014) The twilight of human rights law. New York, Oxford University Press

  • Ruggie J (2013) Just business: Multinational corporations and human rights. New York, W.W. Norton & Company

  • Ruggie J (2017) Social construction of the un guiding principles on business and human rights. Corporate Responsibility Initiative Working Paper No. 67. Cambridge, Kennedy School of Government, Harvard University

  • Scherer A, Palazzo G (2011) The new political role of business in a globalized world: A review of a new perspective on CSR and its implications for the firm, governance, and democracy. Journal of Management Studies 48:899–931

  • Sen A (2001) Development as freedom. Oxford, Oxford University Press

  • Sikkink K (2017) Evidence for hope: Making human rights work in the 21st century. Princeton, Princeton University Press

  • Singer P (1972) Famine, affluence, and morality. Philosophy & Public Affairs 1:229–243

  • Smith A (1978) [1762/66] Lectures on jurisprudence. Oxford: Clarendon Press

  • Smucker J (2006) Pursuing corporate social responsibility in changing institutional fields. In: Bird F, Velasquez M. (eds) Just business practices in a diverse and developing world. Houndsmills, Basingstoke, Palgrave McMillan:81–108

  • Strudler A (2017) What to do with corporate wealth? Journal of Political Philosophy 25:108–126

  • Vogel D (2005) The market for virtue: The potential and limits of corporate social responsibility. Washington, DC, Brookings Institution Press

  • Weber M (1949) [1917]. The meaning of ‘ethical neutrality’. In: Shils E, Finch H (eds) The methodology of the social sciences. New York, Free Press

  • Weber M (1975) [1903-06] Roscher and Knies: The logical problems of historical economics. New York: Free Press

  • Weber M (1978 [1922]) Economy and society. Berkeley, University of California Press

  • Wettstein F (2009) Multinational corporations and global justice: Human rights obligations of a quasi-governmental institution. Stanford: Stanford Business Books

  • Wettstein F (2015) Normativity, ethics, and the UN guiding principles on business and human rights. Journal of Human Rights 14:162-182

  • Wood S (2012) The case for leverage-based corporate human rights responsibility. Business Ethics Quarterly 22 (2012):63-98

Download references

Acknowledgments

My notion of an HRC takes inspiration from Li and McKernan’s (2017:265-266) suggestion that “in an age where corporate power tests and sometimes exceeds the capacities of state control,” my notion of a human rights state (Gregg 2016) could be extended to corporations toward “carrying the recognition of moral responsibility for human rights into business culture,” reshaping “expectations against which managers in particular corporations hold themselves to account”—including a “dissensual moment” that would advocate from within the corporation for “those whose lives and rights are adversely affected by corporate activity.”

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Benjamin Gregg.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Gregg, B. Beyond Due Diligence: the Human Rights Corporation. Hum Rights Rev 22, 65–89 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12142-020-00605-x

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12142-020-00605-x

Keywords

Navigation