Skip to main content
Log in

Undeformable Bodies that are Not Rigid Bodies: A Philosophical Journey Through Some (Unexpected) Supertasks

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Axiomathes Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

There is broad consensus (both scientific and philosophical) as to what a rigid body is in classical mechanics. The idea is that a rigid body is an undeformable body (in such a way that all undeformable bodies are rigid bodies). In this paper I show that, if this identification is accepted, there are therefore rigid bodies which are unstable. Instability here means that the evolution of certain rigid bodies, even when isolated from all external influence, may be such that their identity is not preserved over time. The result is followed by analyzing supertasks that are possible in infinite systems of rigid bodies. I propose that, if we wish to preserve our original intuitions regarding the necessary stability of rigid bodies, then the concept of rigid body must be clearly distinguished from that of undeformable body. I therefore put forward a new definition of rigid body. Only the concept of undeformable body is holistic (every connected part of an undeformable body is not always an undeformable body) and every connected part of a rigid body in this new sense is always a rigid body in this new sense. Finally, I briefly discuss the connection between this conceptual distinction and the dimensionality of space, thereby enabling it to be supported from a new and interesting perspective.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. "A continuous body is a set B of points called material points" (Silhavý 1997, p. 29).

  2. Consider P's interior topological boundary, which completely overlaps Q's topological boundary. Let us call this common boundary BPQ. Given the fact that the (constant) density of P and Q is the same (= ρ), it follows that P + Q is a homogeneous rigid body of density ρ and, therefore, dynamically identical to P*. In particular, as is evident, the density at any one point p BPQ is ρ, identical to the density of the corresponding point of P*. The same consideration applies, of course, to rigid bodies R and S discussed later in the text and also to all the cases of rigid bodies in contact in the subsequent sections of the paper.

  3. Earman describes this principle thus: "particle world lines do not have beginning or end points and mass is constant along a world line" (p. 38). Strictly speaking he formulates it for point particles (with non-null mass). However extending it to the material points of a rigid solid (with non-null mass density, although their mass may be null) is natural. In this paper I assume this extension which is, understandably, also reasonable because a rigid body is partially specified by the material points that belong to it. The principle of conservation of mass also explains why an isolated unstable rigid body cannot instantly cease to exist and simply leave empty space in its place.

  4. Each of the multiple collisions is dynamically undetermined. From the infinite solutions possible compatible with the laws of conservation, I have chosen a particularly interesting one. The same occurs in the other examples of collisions analyzed subsequently. The important thing in all this is not indeterminism as such; it is rather the type of forms of evolution that turn out to be compatible with dynamics even without being required by it. In the literature on Newtonian supertasks little or no philosophical advantage has yet been taken of indeterministic collisions (even in the non-philosophical technical literature, these types of situations are only considered in engineering-oriented publications such as, e.g. Brogliato 2016). The present paper also aims to put this to rights by showing a significant result that could not be reached by the usual path of analyzing deterministic binary collisions. Note that, since multiple collisions involving block d2i-1 and block d2i are dynamically undetermined, post-collision states other than those assumed in the basic supertask execution are possible. For example, both block d2i-1 and block d2i could rebound from each collision they undergo without losing any of their parts as a consequence of the collision. This would correspond to a form of evolution devoid of interest, whereby no supertask would take place. The form of evolution assumed in the basic supertask is therefore just one among an infinite number of other possible forms, most of which are of no interest. This is a possible, but not necessary, supertask. Nevertheless, such a possibility is all that is needed. As mentioned earlier, it corresponds to a form of evolution that is compatible with dynamics even though the later does not require it.

  5. As a time [2/(√2 − 1)](L/v1) goes by from the de-blocking of the pair (d1, d2) to the completion of the type-ω supertask (which corresponds to the situation in Fig. 2), the same occurs from the beginning of the type-ω* supertask (which corresponds to the situation in Fig. 2) to the blocking of the pair (d1, d2). Finally, a time (2L/v1) evidently passes from the blocking of (d1, d2) to their de-blocking. In all, 2[2/(√2 − 1)](L/v1) + (2L/v1) = (2 + √2)2(L/v1).

  6. The idea originally comes from Laraudogoitia (1998). See, for example, Angel (2005) for discussion surrounding this topic.

  7. The idea of extending the sphere of possible solutions is not uncommon and is useful in mathematical physics involving, for instance, differential equations. In this case one goes beyond classical solutions to generalized solutions (distributional and weak solutions). Kanwal (2004, pp. 228–229).

  8. In other respects, the strategy of rejecting the possibility of certain supertasks on the sole basis of the kind of consequences they have sheds little light on the problem.

  9. One might consider describing the situation, in more detail, in this way: all parts of C* are rigidly joined together, but not all parts of C + D are rigidly joined together. However, this only makes "empirical" sense, as noted above, if the space has at least four dimensions.

  10. In particular, we saw that if the space is three-dimensional, then unstable three-dimensional undeformable non-rigid solids exist. The surprising thing was the form in which the new degrees of freedom of translation appeared, which were not dependent on increasing the dimensionality of space.

References

  • Adams EW (1959) The foundations of rigid body mechanics and the derivation of its laws from those of particle mechanics. In: Henkin L, Suppes P, Tarski A (eds) North-holland, the axiomatic method, Amsterdam, pp 250–265

  • Angel L (2005) Even and odds in Newtonian collision mechanics. Br J PhilosSci 56:179–188

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Atkinson D, Johnson P (2009) Nonconservation of energy and loss of determinism I. Infinitely many colliding balls. Found Phys 39:937–957

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barber JR (2010) Elasticity. Springer, Dordrecht

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brogliato B (2016) Nonsmooth mechanics. Models, dynamics and control. Springer, Switzerland

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Earman J (1986) A primer on determinism. D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Earman J (1989) World enough and space-time. Absolute versus relational theories of space and time. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Haupt P (2000) Continuum mechanics and theory of materials. Springer, Berlin

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kanwal RP (2004) Generalized functions. Theory and applications. Birkhäuser, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Kilborn W (2007) Contact and continuity. Oxford Stud Metaphys 3:267–280

    Google Scholar 

  • Kline D, Matheson CA (1987) The impossibility of collision. Philosophy 62:509–515

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lange M (2002) The philosophy of physics. Locality, fields, energy and mass. Blackwell Publishing, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Laraudogoitia JP (1998) Infinity machines and creation ex nihilo. Synthese 115:259–265

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laraudogoitia JP (2015) On the Atkinson-Johnson homogeneous solution for infinite systems. Found Phys 45:496–506

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laraudogoitia JP (2018) Rigidity, instability and dimensionality. Synthese 195:4047–4062

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laraudogoitia JP (2020) Some surprising instabilities in idealized dynamical systems. Synthese 197:3007–3026

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Margenau H (1950) The nature of physical reality: a philosophy of modern physics. McGraw-Hill Bok Company, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Norton JD (1999) A quantum mechanical supertask. Found Phys 29:1265–1302

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rickless D (2017) The philosophy of physics. Polity press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Romano A, Marasco A (2014) Continuum mechanics using mathematica. Birkhäuser, Basel

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rucker RVB (1977) Geometry relativity and the fourth dimension. Dover Publications, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Salencon J (2001) Handbook of continuum mechanics. Springer, Berlin

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sherry D (2015) Fields and the intelligibility of contact action. Philosophy 90:457–477

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Silhavý M (1997) The mechanics and thermodynamics of continuous media. Springer, Berlin

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sklar L (1992) Philosophy of physics (dimensions of philosophy). Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith S (2007) Continuous bodies, impenetrability, and contact interactions: the view from the applied mathematics of continuum mechanics. Br J PhilosSci 58:503–538

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sneed JD (1979) The logical structure of mathematical physics. D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Truesdell C (1966) The elements of continuum mechanics. Springer, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Varzi A (2015) Boundary. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2015 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2015/entries/boundary

  • Wilson M (2013) What is “Classical Mechanics” Anyway? In: Batterman R (ed) The oxford handbook of philosophy of physics. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Yamanouchi K (2012) Quantum mechanics of molecular structures. Springer, Berlin

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Research for this work is part of the research project GIU19/051 (funded by the University of the Basque Country UPV/EHU)

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jon Pérez Laraudogoitia.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The authors declare that they have no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Laraudogoitia, J.P. Undeformable Bodies that are Not Rigid Bodies: A Philosophical Journey Through Some (Unexpected) Supertasks. Axiomathes 32, 605–625 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-021-09543-w

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-021-09543-w

Keywords

Navigation