Skip to main content
Log in

Introspection and Primacy of Perception: A Critical Reflection on Naïve Realism

  • Published:
Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

A fundamental issue in philosophy of perception is to understand the nature of experience and the relation of the experience with objects or states of affairs that is experienced. A prominent philosophical issue here is posed by the possibility of hallucinatory experiences, which are subjectively indistinguishable from veridical perception for the experiencer. The philosophical views in this matter can be grouped into three major positions on the basis of the nature of the subjective experience and relation of the subjective experience with the object. These are the sense-data theories—which consider that the objects of perception are mental entities; the representative theories—according to which perception is a representation of the objects in the external world; and the naïve realist theories—which proclaim that the external objects are constitutive of the very perceptual experience and not a representation of it. Naïve realism claims it is the defence of common-sense notion regarding experience i.e. how experience seems to the experiencer upon introspective reflection on it. This position has a growing number of proponents in philosophy especially in the last two decades. But it also entails radical departure of established philosophical views regarding the nature of experience, the phenomenal character of experience, and the experiencer–object relation. In this paper, we critically examine naïve realism from two crucial aspects pertaining to it—the question of introspection being basis of naïve realist thesis, and the notion of primacy of perception over non-veridical forms of experiences. We find that there are significant problems which weaken the naïve realist thesis.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Similarly, the sense-data theorist can maintain the indistinguishability is explained by the presence of the same kind of object.

  2. Whereas the sense-data theory believes what is common is the object of perception, the representational view thinks perception and hallucination share a common content.

  3. Siegel also provides another interesting example. She asks us to consider a virtual reality depiction of Escher’s staircase. Escher’s staircase is an impossible staircase which can be pictorially represented; however, it can never be actually made in the real world. Siegel says it is possible for us to have an (illusory or hallucinatory) perceptual experience of Escher’s staircase; however, it is not possible to have a (veridical) perception of such staircase simply because such staircase cannot exist in reality. Thus again, we have a case where mere indistinguishability with veridical perception is not sufficient to characterise non-veridical experiences or perceptual experiences in general.

  4. It should be noted, however, that this hypothesis does not prove the implausible naïve realist claim discussed earlier that hallucinations lack phenomenal character to be true. However, it still shows that hallucinatory phenomenology is dependent on phenomenology derived from actual perception. In contrast to the naïve claim, the present claim may be considered to be a weaker version of the primacy of perception claim. Now the question arises: Do we need to accept even this weaker version of the primacy claim?

  5. For instance, consider a typical perceptual scene of seeing an apple in the dinner table. Even when one veridically perceives parts of the apples and the table which is not in our direct view, like any other three-dimensional opaque object parts of the table or the apples are occluded from us. However, despite this while perceiving we have a sense of the presence of the apples as whole or the table as whole. We don’t perceive them as half-apples or half-tables. This is because the brain uses its acquired beliefs in creating a perceptual scene. It “knows” how apples are, or how tables are, and thus generate an experience of a whole table and whole apples even with partial sensory information presented to it at that particular moment.

References

  • Austin, J. (1962a). How to do things with words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J. (1962b). Sense and sensibilia. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ayer, A. (1953). The foundations of empirical knowledge. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2013). Expecting the world: Perception, prediction, and the origins of human knowledge. Journal of Philosophy, 110(9), 469–496.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1995). Naturalizing the mind. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1982). Epiphenomenal qualia. Philosophical Quarterly, 32(127), 127–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1986). What Mary didn’t know. Journal of Philosophy, 83(5), 291–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kveraga, K., Ghuman, A. S., & Bar, M. (2007). Top-down predictions in the cognitive brain. Brain and Cognition, 65(2), 145–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. (2002). The transparency of experience. Mind and Language, 17(4), 376–425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. (2004). The limits of self-awareness. Philosophies Studies, 120(1/3), 37–89.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1974). What Is it like to be a bat? The Philosophical Review, 83(4), 435–450.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rao, R., & Ballard, D. (1999). Predictive coding in the visual cortex: A functional interpretation of some extra-classical receptive-field effects. Nature Neuroscience, 2(1), 79–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, H. (1994). Perception. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (2015). Seeing things as they are: A theory of perception. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Seth, A. K. (2015). Presence, objecthood, and the phenomenology of predictive perception. Cognitive Neuroscience, 6(2–3), 111–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, S. (2004). Indiscriminability and the phenomenal. Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition, 120(1/3), 91–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Soteriou, M. (2016). Disjunctivism. New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sarthak Ghosh.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Ghosh, S. Introspection and Primacy of Perception: A Critical Reflection on Naïve Realism. J. Indian Counc. Philos. Res. 36, 247–263 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40961-019-00172-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40961-019-00172-8

Keywords

Navigation