Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Collective choice in Aristotle

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Constitutional Political Economy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

“At its most general and fundamental level Aristotle’s analysis of the polis is a highly abstract exercise in rational choice theory.” (Schofield 2005, p. 318).

Abstract

In his Politics VI 3, 1318a–b, Aristotle discusses constitutional procedures for achieving justice in a society where its classes have different views on it. He analyzes the case of a society consisting in two groups, the poor and the rich, each holding a specific understanding of justice (democratic or oligarchic). In this paper we give, first, a non-formal summary of this section of Politics. Then we approach it in the framework of social choice theory and argue that a social rule for selecting between alternatives may be extracted from it. As Aristotle argued, this rule is consistent with the views on justice and equality of the supporters of both democracy and oligarchy. Finally, we study its properties, as well as some extensions of it when multiple classes are allowed or more than two alternatives are present.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The quotations from Aristotle’s Politics are in Reeve’s translation (Aristotle 1998).

  2. The issue of the so-called middle class will be discussed in Sect. 5.

  3. Cf. Reeve (in Aristotle 1998, p. 176, note 7): “Numerical equality (to ison kata arithmon) involves equal participation in political office by each citizen, and so an interchange of ruling and being ruled (see 1261a 30-b 6), it does not seem necessarily to involve equality of property, since none of the ways of establishing it discussed in VI.3 involves a redistribution of property.”

  4. For an interesting discussion of constitutional choice in ancient Athens see Tridimas (2012, 2017).

  5. In his Laws Plato describes a voting procedure in the imagined city of Magnesia. His goal was also to construct a system of selection that will “effect a compromise between a monarchical and a democratic constitution” (Plato 1997, p. 1433, 756e). Aristotle was critical of Plato’s proposal; see his Politics (1266a).

  6. See also Simpson (1998, pp. 433–435), who gives a very clear description of it.

  7. In Sect. 2 we shall refine this assertion as follows: step 1 results in a social decision if either both classes choose the same alternative, or one of them chooses an alternative and the other is indifferent between the alternatives. If we allow for at least three classes in the society, things become much more complicated (see Sect. 5).

  8. We thank Roger Crisp for pointing this fact to us.

  9. For example, Aristotle argues that, as regards the courts, one device used in constitutions to deceive people is that of “fining the rich for not serving on juries, but not the poor, or else imposing a large fine on the former and a small one on the latter” (1279b 21–23).

  10. For these qualifications see the next section, where we describe a case in which the poor do not form a majority.

  11. For an example in this sense, see in the next section our discussion of Kraut’s arguments.

  12. Take the following example (here we follow Rackam’s interpretation of 1318a 21–23): one man would own more than the property of all the others put together According to the oligarchic principle of justice it is just for him to rule alone, i.e. tyranny must be established.

  13. For the role of leisure, see also Aristotle’s discussion in Metaphysics 981b 20–24: science was first discovered in places where men had begun to have leisure.

  14. We thank the journal's anonymous reviewer for drawing our attention to these points.

  15. Here and in the next sections we give a number of examples to illustrate our points made in the formal framework. Given the aim of this article, we do not focus on a more formal, algebraic approach. Clearly, in general this is difficult to construct, especially because the rules we study are given by a multiple steps process.

  16. This example, with W(j) = 3 for all j ∊ X, is analyzed in Kraut (2002, p. 458).

  17. Kraut (2002, p. 445) highlights another important idea: Aristotle believes that the many are more susceptible to act in a cohesive way than the few; factions are more probable to occur among the rich than among the poor (1302a 8–15). Therefore the poor have a higher capacity than the rich to socially impose their preferences. This view of Aristotle is difficult to accept. If we agree with the (modern economists’) logic of collective action (Olson 1965), things look differently: since the rich are less numerous, they are priviledged and can develop collective action, while the many poor have difficulties in coordinating their actions.

  18. This phrase expresses what Miller (1995, 285 sq.) called the “superiority principle”. There are many other places in Aristotle’s Politics that support this principle. See for example 1297b 4–6; 1320b 26–28. For Aristotle “superiority” involves both a qualitative and a quantitative element.

  19. Analogously, we can study the case when the city consists in n groups or classes.

  20. It would be interesting to compare this option with the voting procedures in the Roman comitia centuriata; see for example Taylor (1966) and the famous passage in Rousseau’s Social Contract (2012, IV4) on the reform of Servius. However, this is beyond the scope of this paper.

  21. It is interesting to remark that when the society is partitioned in at least three classes this Pareto rule is not representative (Fine 1972). The reason is that \(Ar_{P}^{[3]}\) does not satisfy Fine’s NZZ property (see footnote 23 below).

  22. However, the alternative criterion advanced by Newman (1902) is oligarchic.

  23. Fine (1972) proves that a choice function is representative if and only if it satisfies Mon, N and a property he calls Non-Zigzaggedness (NZZ). Since, as showed above, Ar is representative, it must have the three properties. Morover, Ar satisfies MR, which is a stronger property than NZZ.

References

  • Aristotle (1944). Politics. In Aristotle in 23 volumes (H. Rackham, Trans.) (Vol. 21). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Aristotle (1998). Politics (translated, with Introduction and Notes by C. D. C. Reeve). Indianapolis: Hackett.

  • Burnyeat, M. (2001). Plato. Proceedings of the British Academy, 111, 1–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartledge, P. (2009). Ancient Greek political thought in practice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (1972). Some necessary and sufficient conditions for representative decision on two alternatives. Econometrica, 40, 1083–1090.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hansen, M. H. (1999). The Athenian democracy in the age of Demosthenes: Structure, principles and ideology (J. A. Crook, Trans.). Norman: University of Oklahoma Press.

  • Jones, A. H. M. (1958). Athenian democracy. New York: Praeger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jowett, B. (1885). The politics of Aristotle, part I. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kraut, R. (2002). Aristotle: Political philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • May, K. O. (1952). A set of independent necessary and sufficient conditions for simple majority decisions. Econometrica, 20, 680–684.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, F. D., Jr. (1995). Nature, justice, and rights in Aristotle’s politics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mulgan, R. (1991). Aristotle’s analysis of oligarchy and democracy. In D. Keyt & F. D. Miller Jr. (Eds.), A companion to Aristotle’s politics (pp. 307–322). Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murakami, Y. (1966). Formal structure of majority decisions. Econometrica, 34, 709–718.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newman, W. L. (1902). The politics of Aristotle (Vol. IV). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ober, J. (1998). Political dissent in democratic Athens. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olson, M. (1965). The logic of collective action. Public goods and the theory of groups. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato. (1997). Laws. In J. M. Cooper (Ed.), Plato: Complete works, edited with Introduction and Notes. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau, J.-J. (2012). The social contract and other political writings. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schofield, M. (2005). Aristotle: An introduction. In C. Rowe & M. Schofield (Eds.), The Cambridge history of Greek and Roman political thought (pp. 310–320). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simpson, P L Ph. (1998). A philosophical commentary on the politics of Aristotle. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tangian, A. (2014). Mathematical theory of democracy. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, L. S. (1966). Roman voting assemblies: From the Hannibalic War to the dictatorship of Caesar. Ann Arbor: The University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tridimas, G. (2012). Constitutional choice in ancient Athens: The rationality of selection to office by lot. Constitutional Political Economy, 23, 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tridimas, G. (2017). Constitutional choice in ancient Athens: The evolution of the frequency of decision making. Constitutional Political Economy, 28, 209–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Adrian Miroiu.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Appendices

Appendix 1

The appendix includes the proofs of the Lemmas 1, 2 and 4 and the Theorems 1 and 2.

Lemma 1

The social choice function w is representative.

Proof

Starting with the group G = {j1, j2,… jm} we shall construct another group G* with the property that w(pG) = μ(pG*). To do this, replace in G each member ji of it with a group Gi defined as follows. Suppose that W(ji) = ai. Then Gi = \(\{ \{ j_{i} \} ,\{ \{ j_{i} \} \} , \ldots \underbrace {{\{ \ldots \{ }}_{\substack{ a_{i} \\ times } }j_{i} \underbrace {{\} \ldots \} }}_{\substack{ a_{i} \\ times } }\}\). So, ji is replaced by a set consisting in a number of ai sets, and for each of them μ gives the same value as R(ji). Now put G* = \(\cup_{i = 1}^{m} G_{i}\).We can immediately check that w(pG) = μ(pG*). □

Lemma 2

Ar is representative.

Proof

The proof consists in defining a (higher-order) society H with the property that for each profile p we have: Ar(pG) = μ(pH) (here we assume that H is such that all the individuals occurring in it are members of G). To do this, let

$$H = \left\{ {\left\{ {X,Y} \right\},\left\{ {\left\{ {X,Y} \right\}} \right\},G*} \right\}$$

where, as we saw above, G* is a group with the property that w(pG) = μ(pG*). The group H includes two occurrences of the society {X, Y}. To differentiate them, the latter occurrence was constructed as the singleton consisting in this very society.

It can be proved that for each profile p we have:

$$Ar\left( {p_{G} } \right) =\upmu\left( {p_{H} } \right)$$

We shall consider three cases:

  • Case 1: Ar(pG) = 1. By definition, we have three subcases:

    • Subcase 1a: μ(pX) = 1 and μ(pY) ≥ 0. We have: μ(p{{X, Y}, {{X, Y}}, G*}) = μ(μ(μ(pX), μ(pY)), μ(μ(μ(pX), μ(μ(pY))), μ(pG*)) = μ(μ(μ(1), μ(1/0)), μ(μ(μ(1), μ(μ(1/0))), μ(pG*)) = μ(μ(1, 1/0), μ(μ(1), μ(1/0)), μ(pG*)) = μ(μ(1, 1/0), μ(1, 1/0), μ(pG*)) = μ(1, 1, μ(pG*)) = 1.

    • Subcase 1b: μ(pX) ≥ 0 and μ(pY) = 1: it is similar to subcase 1a.

    • Subcase 1c: μ(pX) = − μ(pY) and w(pG) = 1, i.e. μ(pG*) = 1. Then we have both μ(μ(pX), μ(pY)) = 0 and μ(μ(μ(pX), μ(μ(pY))), therefore μ(p{{X, Y}, {{X, Y}}, G*}) = μ(0, 0, μ(pG*)) = μ(pG*). But μ(pG*) = 1 and so μ(p{{X, Y}, {{X, Y}}, G*}) = μ(0, 0, 1) = 1.

  • Case 2: Ar(pG) = − 1. This is analogous to case 1.

  • Case 3. Ar(pG) = 0. Just like in case 1c, we get μ(p{{X, Y}, {{X, Y}}, G*}) = μ(0, 0, 0) = 0. □

Lemma 4

\(Ar_{\upmu}^{[3]}\) is representative.

The proof consists simply in constructing the society H3 = {{X, M, Y}, {{X, M, Y}}, G*}. Clearly, we have \(Ar_{\upmu}^{[3]}\)(pG) = μ(\(p_{{H^{3} }}\)).

Theorem 1

Ar satisfiesMon,NandMR.

Proof

I shall sketch the proofs for N and Mon, and then focus on the proof that Ar satisfies MR.Footnote 23 For N, we need to show that μ(\(p_{H}^{'}\)) = − μ(pH). Suppose that all the members of the group G have reversed choices, i.e. at profile \(p_{G}^{'}\) it holds that R′(j) = –R(j) for all j ∈ G. Observe that μ satisfies N (May 1952) for all first-order societies like X and Y. So μ(\(p_{X}^{'}\)) = − μ(pX) and μ(\(p_{Y}^{'}\)) = − μ(pY). Thus μ(\(p_{{\{ X,Y\} }}^{'}\)) = μ(μ(\(p_{X}^{'}\)), μ(\(p_{Y}^{'}\))) = μ(− μ(pX), − μ(pY)) = − μ(μ(pX), μ(pY)) = − μ(p{X, Y}). Now μ(p{X}) = μ(μ(pX)). So μ(\(p_{{\{ \{ X,Y\} \} }}^{'}\)) = μ(μ(\(p_{{\{ X,Y\} }}^{'}\))) = μ(− μ(p{X, Y})) = − μ(μ(p{X, Y})). This result can also be used to show that μ(\(p_{G*}^{'}\)) = − μ(pG*). Finally, μ(\(p_{H}^{'}\)) = μ(μ(\(p_{{\{ X,Y\} }}^{'}\)),μ(\(p_{{\{ \{ X,Y\} \} }}^{'}\)),μ(\(p_{G*}^{'}\))) = μ(− μ(p{X, Y}), − μ(μ(p{X, Y})), − μ(pG*)) = − μ(pH). The proof for Mon also uses the fact that μ satisfies it for first-order societies; it will be omitted here.

Moving to MR, notice first that if Ar(pG) = 1 and R′(j) > R(j) for some individual j in G, then by the monotonicity of Ar we get Ar(\(p_{G}^{'}\)) = 1. So let Ar(pG) = 0 and R′(j) > R(j) for some individual j in G. By definition, Ar(pG) = 0 when the following conditions hold: μ(pX) = − μ(pY) and sgn (\(\sum\limits_{i = 1}^{m} {W(j_{i} )R(j_{i} )}\)) = 0. We have three cases:

  • Case 1: μ(pX) = − μ(pY) = 0. Then, since µ satisfies MR for all first-order groups, we get µ(\(p_{X}^{'}\)) = 1 if j ∊ X or µ(\(p_{Y}^{'}\)) = 1 if j ∊ Y. In each case µ(\(p_{{\{ X,Y\} }}^{'}\)) = 1 and so µ(\(p_{H}^{'}\)) = 1.

  • Case 2: μ(pX) = − μ(pY) and μ(pX) = 1 and μ(pY) = − 1. Then, if j ∊ X, by monotonicity we have µ(\(p_{X}^{'}\)) = 1 and also µ(\(p_{Y}^{'}\)) = − 1. So µ(\(p_{X}^{'}\)) = − µ(\(p_{Y}^{'}\)). But then in the second step we get \(\sum\nolimits_{i = 1}^{m} {W^{\prime}(j_{i} )R^{\prime}(j_{i} )}\) > 0 and so sgn (\(\sum\nolimits_{i = 1}^{m} {W^{\prime}(j_{i} )R^{\prime}(j_{i} )}\)) = 1. Therefore µ(\(p_{G*}^{'}\)) = 1 which entails that µ(\(p_{H}^{'}\)) = 1. If j ∊ Y, we have two subcases.

    • Subcase 2a: μ(\(p_{Y}^{'}\)) = 0. Then µ(\(p_{{\{ X,Y\} }}^{'}\)) = 1 and so µ(\(p_{H}^{'}\)) = 1.

    • Subcase 2b: μ(\(p_{Y}^{'}\)) = − 1. Then µ(\(p_{{\{ X,Y\} }}^{'}\)) = 0. But as above we can show that µ(\(p_{G*}^{'}\)) = 1 and thus µ(\(p_{H}^{'}\)) = 1.

  • Case 3: μ(pX) = − μ(pY) and μ(pX) = − 1 and μ(pY) = 1. It is similar to Case 2. □

Theorem 2

Let two profiles pG = (G, W, n, R) and \(p_{G}^{'}\) = (G, W′, n, R) differ only in that there is some individual j ∊ G such that W′(j) > W(j). If Ar(pG) = 0 and j is not pivotal for Y, then Ar(\(p_{G}^{'}\)) = R(j).

Proof

Two cases can be distinguished.

  • Case 1: j ∊ X, i.e. j is rich. Then j ∊ X at \(p_{G}^{'}\): if the individual j was rich at pG, then clearly he is also rich at \(p_{G}^{'}\). Since the individual choice function are the same in the two profiles we have both μ(pX) = μ(\(p_{X}^{'}\)) and μ(pY) = μ(\(p_{Y}^{'}\)). Since f(pG) = 0, we have μ(pX) = − μ(pY) and consequently we get μ(\(p_{X}^{'}\)) = − μ(\(p_{Y}^{'}\)). So μ(\(p_{{\{ X,Y\} }}^{'}\)) = 0. Moreover, f(pG) = 0 entails that \(\sum\nolimits_{i = 1}^{m} {W(j_{i} )R(j_{i} )}\) = 0. But, since W′(j) > W(j) we get \(\sum\nolimits_{i = 1}^{m} {W^{\prime}(j_{i} )R(j_{i} )}\) = \(\sum\nolimits_{i = 1}^{m} {W(j_{i} )R(j_{i} )}\) + (W′(j) − W(j))R(j) and so μ(\(p_{G*}^{'}\)) = sgn(\(\sum\nolimits_{i = 1}^{m} {W^{\prime}(j_{i} )R(j_{i} )}\)) = sgn((W′(j) − W(j))R(j)) = R(j). So μ(\(p_{H}^{'}\)) = R(j).

  • Case 2. j ∊ Y, i.e. j is poor. We have two subcases.

    • Subcase 2a: j ∊ Y at \(p_{G}^{'}\). Although his property increases, j remains poor. The proof is just like in case 1.

    • Subcase 2b: j ∊ X at \(p_{G}^{'}\). This means that the property of j increases enough to move j from the class of the poor to the class of the rich. Let R(j) = 1 (the same argument works for R(j) = − 1, therefore it will be omitted). Suppose that μ(pY) = − 1. Then clearly μ(\(p_{{Y - \{ j\} }}^{'}\)) = − 1 and μ(\(p_{{X \cup \{ j\} }}^{'}\)) = 1. So μ(\(p_{{\{ X,Y\} }}^{'}\)) = 0. But, as argued in Case 1, μ(\(p_{G*}^{'}\)) = R(j) = 1 and so μ(\(p_{H}^{'}\)) = 1. Secondly, let μ(pY) = 0 and therefore μ(pX) = 0. Then of course μ(\(p_{{Y - \{ j\} }}^{'}\)) = − 1 and μ(\(p_{{X \cup \{ j\} }}^{'}\)) = 1, which again entails that μ(\(p_{{\{ X,Y\} }}^{'}\)) = 0 and, as above, μ(\(p_{G*}^{'}\)) = R(j) = 1; consequently, μ(\(p_{H}^{'}\)) = 1. Third, suppose that μ(pY) = 1 and therefore μ(pX) = − 1. Since j is not pivotal for Y, we have μ(pY – {j}) = 1. But given that μ(pX) = − 1 and by supposition R(j) = 1, it follows that μ(pX ∪ {j}) ≤ 0.Then μ(\(p_{{\{ X,Y\} }}^{'}\)) ≥ 0. If μ(\(p_{{\{ X,Y\} }}^{'}\)) = 1, then immediately μ(\(p_{G}^{'}\)) = 1; if μ(\(p_{{\{ X,Y\} }}^{'}\)) = 0, then apply again the above argument to get μ(\(p_{G*}^{'}\)) = 1 and thus μ(\(p_{H}^{'}\)) = 1 = R(j). Finally, note that if R(j) = 0 then i’s vote does not influence the social decision and so we have f(\(p_{G}^{'}\)) = f(pG) = 0 = R(j). □

Appendix 2

When more than two alternatives are available, the rule Ar may of course produce undesirable results. Social circles are the most obvious example. But it also induces other paradoxical results. One of them is a reversal effect. We shall present below one example in this sense. Clearly, it is a consequence of the fact that Ar does not satisfy the independence property.

Suppose there are three alternatives x, y and z. Again, let the group G consist in 30 members, of whom 20 are poor and 10 are rich. Let 2 poor citizens rank the alternatives in the order zyx, and the remaining 18 in the order yzx. Then all 20 poor citizens prefer y to x and z to x, while 18 prefer y to z. By the majority rule, the social order is yzx. The preferences of the rich are a bit more diversified: 1 has the order xyz, 5 have xzy, and 4 have zxy. Then all 10 citizens prefer x to y, 4 prefer x to z and 1 prefers y to z. By the majority rule, the social order is xzy.

The two classes have opposing choices: the alternative preferred by the rich is y, while the alternative preferred by the poor is x. The alternative z is irrelevant. We need to move to the second step to appeal to the weighted function in order to reach a social decision. Again, let n = 1, and suppose that W(j) = 3 for all j ∊ X and W(j) = 1 for all j ∊ Y. This means that in the second step each poor citizen has 1 vote, and each rich citizen has 3 votes. Given the preferences we already established, x gets 30 votes when compared with y, while z gets 38 votes when compared with x and 29 votes when compared with y. Since the total number of votes is 50, it follows that the social order we get in this second step is zxy.

But this is counterintuitive, because in the first step neither the poor no the rich preferred alternative z to the other two alternatives. The rule allows for a reversal in social preference in the move from the first to the second step.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Miroiu, A., Partenie, C. Collective choice in Aristotle. Const Polit Econ 30, 261–281 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10602-019-09279-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10602-019-09279-1

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation