Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-nr4z6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-09T06:15:53.572Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

COMPARATIVE VALUE AND THE WEIGHT OF REASONS

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  21 June 2018

Itai Sher*
Affiliation:
Department of Economics, Crotty Hall, 412 North Pleasant Street, University of Massachusetts, Amherst, MA, 01002, USA. Email: itaisher@gmail.com. URL: https://sites.google.com/site/itaisher/

Abstract:

One view of practical reasoning is that it involves the weighing of reasons. It is not clear, however, how the weights of reasons combine, especially given the logical and substantive relations among different reasons. Nor is it clear how the weighing of reasons relates to decision theoretic maximization of expected value. This paper constructs a formal model of reasons and their weight in order to shed light on these issues. The model informs philosophical debates about reasons, such as the question of whether reasons or values are more fundamental and the opposing doctrines of atomism and holism about reasons.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2018 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Alvarez, M. 2016. Reasons for action: justification, motivation, explanation. In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2016 Edition. ed. Zalta, E.N.. <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2016/entries/reasons-just-vs-expl/>..>Google Scholar
Billingsley, P. 1995. Probability and Measure. New York, NY: John Wiley & Sons.Google Scholar
Bolker, E. D. 1966. Functions resembling quotients of measures. Transactions of the American Mathematical Society 124: 292312.Google Scholar
Bolker, E. D. 1967. A simultaneous axiomatization of utility and subjective probability. Philosophy of Science 34: 333340.Google Scholar
Broome, J. 2013. Rationality through Reasoning. Chichester: Wiley.Google Scholar
Brown, C. 2014. The composition of reasons. Synthese 191: 779800.Google Scholar
Cariani, F. 2013. Aggregating with reason(s). Synthese 190: 125.Google Scholar
Crupi, V. and Tentori, K.. 2016. Confirmation theory. In The Oxford Handbook of Probability and Philosophy, ed. Hájek, A. and Hitchcock, C., 650665. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dancy, J. 2004. Ethics without Principles. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dekel, E., Lipman, B. L. and Rustichini, A.. 1998. Standard state-space models preclude unawareness. Econometrica 66: 159173.Google Scholar
Dietrich, F. and List, C.. 2013. A reason-based theory of rational choice. Noûs 47: 104134.Google Scholar
Dietrich, F. and List, C. 2016. Reason-based choice and context-dependence: an explanatory framework. Economics and Philosophy 32: 175229.Google Scholar
Domotor, Z. 1978. Axiomatization of Jeffrey utilities. Synthese 39: 165210.Google Scholar
Fogal, D. 2016. Reasons, reason, and context. In Weighing Reasons, ed. Lord, E. and Maguire, B., 74103. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Halpern, J. Y. 2001. Alternative semantics for unawareness. Games and Economic Behavior 37: 321339.Google Scholar
Harman, E. 2015. The irrelevance of moral uncertainty. Oxford Studies in Metaethics 10: 5379.Google Scholar
Heifetz, A., Meier, M. and Schipper, B. C.. 2006. Interactive unawareness. Journal of Economic Theory 130: 7894.Google Scholar
Horty, J. F. 2003. Reasoning with moral conicts. Noûs 37: 557605.Google Scholar
Horty, J. F. 2007. Reasons as defaults. Philosophers' Imprint 7 (3).Google Scholar
Horty, J. F. 2012. Reasons as Defaults. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Jeffrey, R. C. 1990. The Logic of Decision. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kearns, S. and Star, D.. 2009. Reasons as Evidence. Oxford Studies in Metaethics 4: 215242.Google Scholar
Lockhart, T. 2000. Moral Uncertainty and its Consequences. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lord, E. and Maguire, B., ed. 2016. Weighing Reasons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
MacAskill, W. 2016. Normative uncertainty as a voting problem. Mind 125: 9671004.Google Scholar
Maguire, B. 2016. The value-based theory of reasons. Ergo 3: 233262.Google Scholar
Modica, S. and Rustichini, A.. 1994. Awareness and partitional information structures. Theory and Decision 37: 107124.Google Scholar
Nair, S. 2016. How do reasons accrue?, in Weighing Reasons, ed. Lord, E. and Maguire, B., 5673. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1999. Practical Reason and Norms. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. 1998. What We Owe to Each Other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Schroeder, M. 2007. Slaves of the Passions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sepielli, A. 2009. What to do when you don't know what to do. Oxford Studies in Metaethics 4: 528.Google Scholar
Snedegar, J. 2015. Contrastivism about reasons and ought. Philosophy Compass 10: 379388.Google Scholar
Snedegar, J. 2018. Reasons for and reasons against. Philosophical Studies 175: 725743.Google Scholar
Spohn, W. 2012. The Laws of Belief: Ranking Theory and its Philosophical Applications. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Weatherson, B. 2014. Running risks morally. Philosophical Studies 167: 141163.Google Scholar