Skip to main content
Log in

The Contradictions of Conscience: Unravelling the Structure of Obligation in Equity

  • Published:
Law and Critique Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Conscience rests within the heart of equity, yet it is a manifestly nebulous and contradictory concept. In particular, equity has never been clear about exactly whose conscience we are concerned with: the Chancellor or judge, or the court, or the defendant? Furthermore, in some lights conscience appears to compel obedience to the authority of law, whilst in others it gives expression to ethical drives that escape the formal strictures of legal rules. Contextualised within the broader history of ideas of Western modernity, this article sets out to understand the rhetorical significance of conscience in equity, making the argument that its disparate and contradictory modes of expression do not undermine its significance, and instead are essential to its construction of juridical obligations. By invoking conscience as a contradictory expression of both vertical state authority and personal ethical autonomy, equity asserts not only a unique normative structure, but also a distinct mode of power.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Alternatively: ‘the language of conscience conveys the message that the defendant is being compelled to do [what] she “really ought to do”, and not simply what she “ought to do according to the law”’ (Agnew 2018, p. 504).

  2. Alternatively, see Sinead Agnew’s (2018) analysis of the explanatory base that conscience provides to modern doctrine. Additionally, see Pawlowski (2018).

  3. Specifically, ‘dishonest’ accomplices: Royal Brunei Airlines v Tan (1995) 2 AC 378.

  4. The doctrine of notice continues to govern the enforceability of equitable interests in many cases, despite being usurped by land registration.

  5. Per Lord Browne-Wilkinson, Westdeutsche (pp. 705–706). Cf Chambers, Resulting Trusts (1997, pp. 207–209).

  6. See Westdeutsche.

  7. See: Taylors Fashions v Liverpool Victoria Trustees (1982) 1 QB 133; Gillett v Holt (2001) Ch 210.

  8. De Bruyne v De Bruyne (2010) EWCA Civ 519, [49] per Patten LJ.

  9. On conscience and fiduciary relationships, see: Hospital Products v US Surgical Corp (1984) 55 ALR 417, p. 430; Indata Equipment Supplies Ltd v ACL Ltd (1998) FSR 248, pp. 255–256. On the scope of the rule, see Boardman v Phipps (1966) 2 AC 46.

  10. Hart v O’Connor (1985) AC 1000; Credit Lyonnais Bank v Burch (1997) 1 All ER 144.

  11. See Watt (2009), p. 111. On the tension between subjective and objective standards in conscience generally, see Samet (2012).

  12. E.g. Pennington v Waine (2002) EWCA Civ 227, and see Halliwell’s (2003) commentary.

  13. Courtney v Glanvil (1614) 79 ER 294, p. 294; Edmunds v Povey (1683) 1 Vern 187, p. 187.

  14. Carpenter v Tucker (1635) 1 Rep Ch 78, p. 79; Hunt v Matthews (1686) 1 Vern 408, p. 408.

  15. Salsbury v Bagott (1677) 2 Swans 603, p. 606.

  16. Crisp v Bluck (1674) 2 Rep Ch 88, p. 91; Nourse and others v Yarworth (1674) Rep t Finch 155, p. 160.

  17. Luke v Bridges and Christy (1700) Prec Ch 146, pp. 148–149; Sheffield v Lord Castleton (1700) 2 Vern 393, p. 393; Keen v Stuckely (1718) Gilb Ch 155, p. 156; Countess of Coventry v Earl of Coventry (1721) Gilb Ch 160, pp. 165–166.

  18. Hopkins alias Dare v Hopkins (1738) 1 Atk 581, p. 591; Le Neve v Le Neve (1747) 1 Ves Sen 64, p. 69; Garth v Sir John Hind Cotton (1750) 1 Ves Sen 546, p. 555.

  19. Attorney-General v Day (1749) 1 Ves Sen 218, p. 221.

  20. Barnesly v Powel (1749) 1 Ves Sen 284, p. 289.

  21. The Earl of Kildare v Sir Morrice Eustace (1686) 1 Vern 405, p. 405.

  22. Ayliffe v Murray (1740) 2 Atk 58, p. 60.

  23. Rochefoucauld v Boustead (1897) 1 Ch 196.

  24. For a critique of the association of conscience with freedom, see Stone (2018).

  25. I should also add, for the benefit of clarity, that the breach of such incontestable standards is not on its own sufficient to invoke liability. The unconscientious behaviour must also be of a recognised type deserving a remedy (e.g. wilful lying is an example of bad conscience, but is not itself an equitable wrong). Conversely, there are cases where equity imposes liability despite ostensibly good conscience, such as Boardman v Phipps (1966).

  26. Nietzsche’s outlook, however, is predictably more cynical than Freud’s. The Genealogy of Morals (2003) depicts conscience as a way of dignifying our powerlessness behind a façade of pious ethics. And by telling ourselves that all other people are bound by the same rules, we feel able to judge others.

  27. See also Ojakangas (2013, pp. 203–204).

  28. By the time of the Judicature Acts, taking evidence was no longer held in secret and could be taken by the parties themselves following the Chancery Practice Amendment Act 1852. See Kessler (2005, p. 1236 n. 297).

  29. This article consciously avoids debating the distinction between ‘inference’ and ‘imputation’. It suffices to say both rest on the same legal fiction. Asserting an intention that the court believes the party should hold (imputation) is equivalent to saying they did hold it (inference) if both judgements derive from normalised ideas of familial behaviour.

  30. Per Lord Diplock, Pettitt v Pettitt (1970) AC 777, p. 824.

References

  • Agnew, Sinéad. 2018. The meaning and significance of conscience in private law. Cambridge Law Journal 77 (3): 479–505.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, Hannah. 1971. Thinking and moral considerations: A lecture. Social Research 38 (3): 417–446.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker, J.H. 2007. An introduction to English legal history, 4th ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Birks, Peter. 1996. Trusts raised to reverse unjust enrichment: The Westdeutsche case. Restitution Law Review 4: 3–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Birks, Peter. 1999. Equity, conscience, and unjust enrichment. Melbourne Law Review 23 (1): 1–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Browne, Denis. 1933. Ashburner’s principles of equity, 2nd ed. London: Butterworth & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butler, Judith. 1997. The psychic life of power: Theories in subjection. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chambers, Robert. 1997. Resulting trusts. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Constable, Marianne. 2014. Our word is our bond: How legal speech acts. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drakopoulou, Maria. 2000. Equity, conscience, and the art of judgment as ius aequi et boni. Law Text Culture 5 (1): 345–375.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, Ronald. 1982. Law as interpretation. Critical Inquiry 9: 179–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fish, Stanley. 1989. Doing what comes naturally: Change, rhetoric, and the practice of legal theory in literary and legal studies. Durham: Duke University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, Michel. 1980. Power/knowledge. Brighton: Harvester.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, Michel. 1998. The will to knowledge. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, Michel. 2002. The subject and power. In Power: The essential works of Foucault 1954–1984, vol. 3, ed. James D. Faubion, 326–348. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freud, Sigmund. 1995. The economic problem of masochism. In Essential papers on masochism, ed. Margaret Ann Fitzpatrick Hanly, 274–285. London: New York University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freud, Sigmund. 2002. Civilization and its discontents. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freud, Sigmund. 2010. The ego and the id. Seattle: Pacific Publishing Studio.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, Lowell. 1991. Medusa’s gaze: Casuisitry and conscience in the Renaissance. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodrich, Peter. 1987. Legal discourse: Studies in linguistics, rhetoric and legal analysis. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Halliwell, Margaret. 1997. Equity and good conscience in a contemporary context. London: Old Bailey Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Halliwell, Margaret. 2003. Perfecting imperfect gifts and trusts: Have we reached the end of the Chancellor’s foot? Conveyancer and Property Lawyer 67: 192–202.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holdsworth, William. 1915. The early history of equity. Michigan Law Review 13 (4): 293–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holdsworth, William. 1966. A history of English law, vol. IV, 3rd ed. London: Methuen & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hopkins, Nicholas. 2006. Conscience, discretion and the creation of property rights. Legal Studies 26 (4): 475–499.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hudson, Alastair. 2016. Conscience as the organising concept of equity. Canadian Journal of Comparative and Contemporary Law 2 (1): 261–299.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones, David H. 1966. Freud’s theory of moral conscience. Philosophy 41 (155): 34–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1991. The metaphysics of morals. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 2005. The moral law: Groundwork to the metaphysics of morals. Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keren, Hila. 2016. Undermining justice: The two rises of freedom of contract and the fall of equity. Canadian Journal of Comparative and Contemporary Law 2 (2): 339–402.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kessler, Amalia D. 2005. Our inquisitorial tradition: Equity procedure, due process, and the search for an alternative to the adversarial. Cornell Law Review 90 (5): 1181–1275.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klinck, Dennis. 2010. Conscience, equity and the Court of Chancery in early modern England. Farnham: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kries, Douglas. 2002. Origen, Plato, and conscience (synderesis) in Jerome’s Ezekiel commentary. Traditio 57: 67–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Longuenesse, Béatrice. 2012. Kant’s ‘I’ in ‘I ought to’ and Freud’s superego. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 86: 19–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Macnair, Mike. 2007. Equity and conscience. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 27 (4): 659–681.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • May, Larry. 1983. On conscience. American Philosophical Quarterly 20 (1): 57–67.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, Friedrich. 2003. The genealogy of morals. Mineola: Dover Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ojakangas, Mika. 2013. The voice of conscience: A political genealogy of Western ethical experience. London: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pawlowski, Mark. 2018. Unconscionability in modern trust law. Trusts and Trustees 9 (1): 842–848.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peperzak, Adriaan. 2004. Elements of ethics. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perelman, Chaim. 1980. Justice, law, and argument: Essays on moral and legal reasoning. London: D. Reidel Publishing.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, Frederick. 1913. The transformation of equity. In Essays in legal history, ed. Paul Vinogradoff, 286–296. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Potts, T.C. 1982. Conscience. In The Cambridge history of later medieval philosophy, ed. Norman Kretzmann et al., 687–704. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rotman, Leonard I. 2016. The ‘fusion’ of law and equity? A Canadian perspective on the substantive, jurisdictional, or non-fusion of legal and equitable matters. Canadian Journal of Comparative and Contemporary Law 2 (2): 497–536.

    Google Scholar 

  • Samet, Irit. 2012. What conscience can do for equity. Jurisprudence 3 (1): 13–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sarat, Austin, and T.R. Kearns. 1996. The rhetoric of law: An interdisciplinary critique of the relationship between words and the law. Ann Arbour: University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skorupski, John Maria. 2010. Conscience. In The Routledge companion to ethics, ed. John Maria Skorupski, 550–561. London: Routledge.

  • Stone, Matthew. 2018. Why should I listen to my conscience? Equity and the question of ontological obligation. In Law, obligation, community, ed. Dan Matthews and Scott Veitch. Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Velleman, J.David. 1999. The voice of conscience. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 99 (1): 57–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Watt, Gary. 2009. Equity stirring: The story of justice beyond law. Oxford: Hart.

    Google Scholar 

  • White, James Boyd. 1985. Law as rhetoric, rhetoric as law: The arts of cultural and communal life. University of Chicago Law Review 52 (3): 684–702.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wood, Allen. 2008. Kantian ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Youdan, T.G. 1984. Formalities for trusts of land, and the doctrine in Rochefoucauld v Boustead. Cambridge Law Journal 43 (2): 306–336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

CASES

  • Attorney-General v Day (1749) 1 Ves Sen 218.

  • Ayliffe v Murray (1740) 2 Atk 58.

  • Barnesly v Powel (1749) 1 Ves Sen 284.

  • Boardman v Phipps (1966) 2 AC 46.

  • Carpenter v Tucker (1635) 1 Rep Ch 78.

  • Countess of Coventry v Earl of Coventry (1721) Gilb Ch 160.

  • Courtney v Glanvil (1614) 79 ER 294.

  • Credit Lyonnais Bank v Burch (1997) 1 All ER 144.

  • Crisp v Bluck (1674) 2 Rep Ch 88.

  • De Bruyne v De Bruyne (2010) EWCA Civ 519, [49].

  • Earl of Oxford’s Case (1615) 1 Ch Rep 485.

  • Edmunds v Povey (1683) 1 Vern 187.

  • Garth v Sir John Hind Cotton (1750) 1 Ves Sen 546.

  • Gillett v Holt (2001) Ch 210.

  • Hart v O’Connor (1985) AC 1000.

  • Hopkins alias Dare v Hopkins (1738) 1 Atk 581.

  • Hospital Products v US Surgical Corp (1984) 55 ALR 417.

  • Hunt v Matthews (1686) 1 Vern 408.

  • Indata Equipment Supplies Ltd v ACL Ltd (1998) FSR 248.

  • Jones v Kernott (2011) UKSC 53.

  • Keen v Stuckely (1718) Gilb Ch 155.

  • Le Neve v Le Neve (1747) 1 Ves Sen 64.

  • Luke v Bridges and Christy (1700) Prec Ch 146.

  • Nourse and others v Yarworth (1674) Rep t Finch 155.

  • Pennington v Waine (2002) EWCA Civ 227.

  • Pettitt v Pettitt (1970) AC 777.

  • Rochefoucauld v Boustead (1897) 1 Ch 196.

  • Royal Brunei Airlines v Tan (1995) 2 AC 378.

  • Salsbury v Bagott (1677) 2 Swans 603.

  • Sheffield v Lord Castleton (1700) 2 Vern 393.

  • Stack v Dowden (2007) 2 AC 432.

  • Taylors Fashions v Liverpool Victoria Trustees (1982) 1 QB 133.

  • The Earl of Kildare v Sir Morrice Eustace (1686) 1 Vern 405.

  • Westdeutsche-Landesbank v Islington LBC (1996) AC 669.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Matthew Stone.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Stone, M. The Contradictions of Conscience: Unravelling the Structure of Obligation in Equity. Law Critique 30, 159–178 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10978-019-09239-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10978-019-09239-6

Keywords

Navigation