Skip to main content
Log in

The Dead-Alive Physicist Experiment: A Case-Study Against the Hypothesis that Consciousness Causes the Wave-Function Collapse in the Quantum Mechanical Measurement Process

  • Published:
Foundations of Physics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

    We’re sorry, something doesn't seem to be working properly.

    Please try refreshing the page. If that doesn't work, please contact support so we can address the problem.

A Correction to this article was published on 13 April 2021

This article has been updated

Abstract

The aim of this paper is to refute the hypothesis that the observer’s consciousness is necessary in the quantum mechanics measurement process. In order to achieve our target, we propose and investigate a variation of the Schrödinger’s cat thought experiment called “DAP”, short for “Dead-Alive Physicist”, in which a human being replaces the cat. This strategy enables us to logically disprove the consistency of the above hypothesis, and to oblige its supporters either to be trapped in solipsism or to rely on an alternative interpretation of quantum mechanics in which the conscious observer plays the sole role of acknowledging the experimental results. Our analysis hence provides support to clarify the relationship between the observer and the objects of her/his experimental observation; this and a few other implications are discussed in the fourth section and in the conclusions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Change history

Notes

  1. There are two main theses arguing that consciousness and quantum mechanical measurement are connected to each other: one thesis (von Neumann, London and Bauer, Wigner, Stapp; see Refs 3,4,5 and 22) holds that the observer's consciousness causes the collapse of the wave function, thus claiming to complete the quantum-to-classical transition, while the other thesis (Penrose; Penrose and Hameroff; see Refs [18, 20, 21]) aims at demonstrating the opposite, i.e. that consciousness emerges from the so called "Orchestrated Objective Reduction".

  2. We don't know how consciousness works and do not have any idea of its nature. Nonetheless we are undoubtedly certain to possess it as the intimate and the most familiar of our experiences. In general, consciousness is defined as the faculty that allows a human subject to be aware of her/his self and of her/his mental activities, as well as the faculty to learn from the perception of external events to which these activities are directed. Leading contemporary scientists in the field have tried to lay the foundations for a science of consciousness, but none of them has yet been able to boast a promising theoretical approach. The Australian philosopher of the mind David J. Chalmers argues that, to open a window towards the understanding of consciousness, it would be required to solve the so called "difficult problem", consisting in finding a correlation between the functional mechanisms engendered by the neural activity of the brain and conscious experience, i.e. the phenomenon that allows the owner of that brain to feel specific effects in the first person.

  3. In such a mechanism a battery is supplying electric power.

  4. This rule, introduced by Max Born in 1926, states that in QM experiments the probability of obtaining any possible outcome, after a measurement/observation, is equal to the square of the corresponding probability amplitude.

  5. Wigner's friend, here called “F”, is a physicist left alone inside a laboratory with the task of checking attentively whether or not a detector has emitted a flash (has registered the arrival of a photon or not). Wigner is waiting outside and suspects that F (as well as all other human beings) may have weird perceptions and be in the superposition of macroscopically distinct states|F has perceived a flash > + |F has not perceived a flash > . Finally, Wigner enters the lab and asks F whether or not he perceived a flash. His reply (yes or no) should remove any doubt as to whether the wave-function collapse has occurred. However, Wigner will question whether it is acceptable or not to establish that the collapse into one only of the two possible alternatives is determined by his action (his request and reception of an unambiguous answer). He poses this question since his initial way of interpreting the state of the system gives rise to a rather embarrassing paradox, from which he has three possible ways of escape: (1) accept a relative form of solipsism, in the sense that he believes to be, among all living creatures, the only one who has unambiguous perceptions, (2) assume that QM is an incomplete theory, (3) assume that QM is not applicable to human beings; he refutes solipsism and, being a firm supporter of QM completeness, opts for the last solution, assuming that there are beings, at least human beings, endowed with consciousness that constitutes an ultimate reality and plays an active role in determining the measurement process by rules that are not susceptible to scientific description.

  6. The question of causality is problematic, since it requires a distinction between the subjective and the objective aspects of this concept. Causality entails another (arguable) question called "cause and effect simultaneity", which has been discussed and investigated in depth by several philosophers, such as I. Kant, D. Hume, G.W. Leibniz and, recently, by Donald Gillies, Jay F. Rosenberg, Sylvain Bromberger et al.; for a detailed understanding see Buzzoni M.: The Agency Theory of Causality, Anthropomorphism, and Simultaneity, Sect. 6, published online: 29 Jan 2015, https://doi.org/10.1080/02698595.2014.979668.

  7. There are two different forms of solipsism: one is described in note 2 as a relative solipsism, the other (associated to an inflexible belief in the CCCH) would lead to an absolute solipsism, that is to say "I believe to be the only thinking entity, while an external reality (including my body), being a product of my mind, does not exist".

References

  1. Einstein, A., Podolsky, B., Rosen, N.: Can quantum mechanical description of physical reality be considered complete? Phys. Rev. 47, 777–780 (1935)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  2. Schrödinger, E.: Die gegenwärtige Situation in der Quantenmechanik, Naturwissenschaften 23. Heft 48, 807–812 (1935)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  3. von Neumann, J.: Mathematische Grundlagen der Quantenmechanik, Julius. Springer, Berlin (1932)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  4. von Neumann, J.: Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics. Princeton University Press, Princeton NJ (1955)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  5. London, F., Bauer, E.: La Théorie de l’observation en méchanique quantique. Hermann, Paris (1939)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  6. Bohm, D.: A suggested interpretation of the quantum theory in terms of “hidden” variables. Phys. Rev. 85, 166–193 (1952)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  7. Bohm, D.: Quantum Theory. Prentice-Hall, New York (1952)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  8. Everett, H.: ‘Relative State’ formulation of quantum mechanics. Rev. Modern Phys. 29, 454–462 (1957)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  9. E.P. Wigner, Remarks on the mind-body question. In: Good, L.J., Editions, W. (eds.) The Scientist Speculates. Heinemann, London (1962)

  10. Wigner, E.P.: The problem of measurement. Am. J. Phys. 31, 6–15 (1963)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  11. Wigner, E.P.: Symmetries and Reflexions. Indiana University Press, Indiana (1967)

    Google Scholar 

  12. Wheeler, J.A.: Assessment of everett’s ‘relative state’ formulation of quantum theory. Rev. Modern Phys. 29, 463–465 (1957)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  13. DeWitt, B.S.: The Many Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. Princeton Series in Physics. University Press, Princeton (1973)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  14. Zurek, W.H.: Decoherence and the transition from quantum to classical. Phys. Today 44, 36–44 (1991)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Albert, D.Z.: Quantum Mechanics and Experience. Harvard University Press, Cambridge (1992)

    Google Scholar 

  16. Ghirardi, G.C., Rimini, A., Weber, T.: Unified dynamics for microscopic and macroscopic systems. Phys. Rev. D 34, 470 (1986)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  17. Ghirardi, G.C., Grassi, R., Pearle, P.: Relativistic dynamical reduction models: general framework and examples. Found. Phys. 20(11), 1271–1316 (1990)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  18. Penrose, R.: The Emperor’s New Mind. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1989)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  19. Penrose, R.: Shadows of the Mind. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1994)

    Google Scholar 

  20. Penrose, R.: The Large, the Small and the Human Mind. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1997)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  21. Hameroff, S., Penrose, R.: Orchestrated reduction of quantum coherence in brain microtubules: a model for consciousness. Math. Comput. Simul. 40, 453–480 (1996)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Stapp, H.P.: Mind, Matter and Quantum Mechanics. Springer, Berlin (1993)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  23. Gell-Mann, M., Hartle, J.: Strong decoherence. In: Feng, D.H., Hu, B.L. (eds.) Quantum Classical Correspondence. The 4th Drexel Symposium on Quantum Nonintegrability, pp. 3–35. International Press, Cambridge, MA (1997)

  24. Rovelli, C.: Relational quantum mechanics. Int. J. Theor. Phys. 35(8), 1637–1678 (1996)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  25. Tegmark, M.: The interpretation of quantum mechanics: many worlds or many words? Fortschrritte der Physik—Progress of Physics 46(6–8), 855–862 (1998)

    ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  26. Haroche, S.: Entanglement, decoherence and the quantum/classical boundary. Phys. Today 51, 36–42 (1998)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Bell, J.S.: Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics: Collected Papers on Quantum Philosophy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge MA (2004)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  28. Barros, J.A., Oas, G.: Can we falsify the consciousness-causes-collapse hypothesis in quantum mechanics. Found Physics 47(10), 1294–1308 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-017-0110-7

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  29. Omnès, R.: Converging Realities: Toward a Common Philosophy of Physics and Mathematics. Princeton University Press, Princeton (2004)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  30. Schlosshauer, M.: Decoherence and the Quantum-to-Classical Transition. Springer, Berlin (2007)

    Google Scholar 

  31. Wallace, D.: The Emergent Multiverse: Quantum Theory According to the Everett Interpretation. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2012)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  32. d’Espagnat, B.: Quantum Physics and Reality. Found. Phys. 41(11), 1703–1716 (2011)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  33. Hobson, A.: Review and Suggested Resolution of the Problem of Schrodinger’s Cat. Contemporary Physics 59, 16–30 (2018)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  34. Hobson, A.: Entanglement and the Measurement Problem (2020)

  35. Weinberg, S.: The Trouble with Quantum Mechanics in Third Thoughts. Harvard University Press, Cambridge (2018)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Our special gratitude goes to the late Giancarlo Ghirardi Professor Emeritus of Physics, Università di Trieste, Carlo Rovelli Professor of Physics, Université de Aix-Marseille, Art Hobson Professor Emeritus of Physics, University of Arkansas, Gianni Battimelli Professor of Physics, Università La Sapienza di Roma, Enrico Marchetti, Professor of Economic Policy, Università degli Studi di Napoli Parthenope, and Lorenzo Stella Professor of Physical Chemistry, Università di Roma 2, for reading and commenting on the manuscript. Finally, we have to thank Susan Beswick for her scrupulous control of the English language of the text.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Bruno Raffaele Stella.

Ethics declarations

Author Contributions

CR devised the thought experiment, both CR and BRS wrote the article.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Bruno Raffaele Stella—Currently retired from Dipartimento di Fisica, Università Roma Tre and INFN Roma Tre, Rome, Italy.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Roselli, C., Stella, B.R. The Dead-Alive Physicist Experiment: A Case-Study Against the Hypothesis that Consciousness Causes the Wave-Function Collapse in the Quantum Mechanical Measurement Process. Found Phys 51, 21 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-021-00427-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-021-00427-y

Keywords

Navigation