Skip to main content
Log in

Representing the Mind as Such in Infancy

  • Published:
Review of Philosophy and Psychology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Tyler Burge claims in a recent high-profile publication that none of the existing evidence for mental-state attribution by children prior to the age of four or five really supports such a conclusion; and he makes this claim, not just for beliefs, but for mental states of all sorts. In its place, he offers an explanatory framework according to which infants and young children attribute mere information-registering states and teleologically-characterized motivational states, which are said to lack the defining properties of the mental. I argue that Burge’s claims are poorly motivated and irrelevant to the goals of developmental psychology.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. All references to Burge are to this paper unless otherwise noted.

  2. It is generic because it contains our adult mentalistic action-explanation scheme as a special case, or species. The two schemes can be structurally identical, but only the mentalizing one employs a (full-blown or mentalistic) notion of representation, Burge thinks.

  3. For a review of the many and varied ways in which infants and young children can display sensitivity to the mental states of others—albeit not representing them as mental, if Burge is correct—see Baillargeon et al. (2016). For a review, more specifically, of the many ways in which infants and toddlers can display sensitivity to the false beliefs of others—albeit not representing them as beliefs, if Burge is right—see Scott and Baillargeon (2017). Note that Burge himself doesn’t challenge the reliability of these data, and says nothing about alleged problems of replication. His challenge is to their interpretation. I will return to this point in footnote #9. For discussion of the data collected with somewhat older children, see Wellman (2014).

  4. Although the necessity described here is a disjunction, in fact almost all of Burge’s focus in the paper is on the representation clause. This is because the developmental data mostly concern representational states like perceptions and beliefs. I will follow him in this.

  5. Even those who defend representationalism about the mind in general, for example (Tye 1995, 2000; Seager and Bourget 2007)—and who thus claim that all mental states (including moods and bodily feelings) are representational ones—do so not as part of a conceptual analysis of the concept mental, nor as part of an explication of the folk conception of the mind. Rather, they advance their claim as part of their naturalizing project, attempting to reductively explain phenomenal consciousness in representational and functional terms.

  6. Seen in this light, it isn’t clear that phenomenal consciousness would figure in the folk-definition of mentality at all. For it is a term of philosophical art. The distinction between phenomenal (or “what-it-is-like”) mental states and others is pretty much invisible from the perspective of common-sense psychology. Agents can be conscious as opposed to asleep, of course; and likewise the folk make use of the notion of an agent being conscious of some thing or event, meaning that the agent perceives it. But neither of these is the same as phenomenal consciousness, which is thought by philosophers to be an introspectively-accessible—and especially puzzling—property that some mental states possess.

  7. Note that although common sense is mentioned here, it plays no further role in Burge’s argument. Or rather, the role that is does play is to provide a contrast with the sorts of representations that he thinks are the signature of true mentality. For example, on p.414 he writes: “As far as current evidence has shown, an infant’s representation is like the common-sense attribution of generic agency to a snail in being silent about whether the agent has a mind.”

  8. In the course of building their models of aboutness philosophers often employ concepts like possible world, or even proposition, that the folk may lack. But this is, arguably, to enable a rigorous treatment of people’s intuitions when employing ordinary concepts like meaning and sameness of meaning.

  9. Although there are now well over 30 studies that provide evidence of false-belief understanding in infants and young children, using a variety of materials and methods, and coming out of a number of different labs (Scott and Baillargeon 2017), there have recently been some failures to replicate individual findings (for examples: Dörrenberg et al. 2018; Kammermeier and Paulus 2018). But Baillargeon et al. (2018) point out the methodological weaknesses of many of these attempted replications, while also acknowledging that some methods (specifically anticipatory looking) might not be reliable. And in the meantime, new studies both replicating and extending previous findings continue to be published (Király et al. 2018). Moreover, Burge himself doesn’t challenge the reliability of the data; his challenge is to its interpretation, and that is my own primary focus here too.

References

  • Apperly, I., and S. Butterfill. 2009. Do humans have two systems to track beliefs and belief-like states? Psychological Review 116: 953–970.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. 1968. A materialist theory of the mind. Oxford: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baillargeon, R., R. Scott, and Z. He. 2010. False-belief understanding in infants. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 14: 110–118.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baillargeon, R., R. Scott, and L. Bian. 2016. Psychological reasoning in infancy. Annual Review of Psychology 67: 159–186.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baillargeon, R., V. Southgate, and D. Buttelmann. 2018. Interpreting failed replications of early false-belief findings: Methodological and theoretical considerations. Cognitive Development 46: 112–124.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barwich, A. 2019. A critique of olfactory objects. Frontiers in Psychology 10: 1337.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, J. 1978. Some remarks about concepts. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 1: 557–560.

    Google Scholar 

  • Botterill, G., and P. Carruthers 1999. The philosophy of psychology. Cambridge, NY: Cambridge University Press.

  • Burge, T. 2010. Origins of objectivity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. 2018. Do infants and nonhuman animals attribute mental states? Psychological Review 125: 409–434.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buttelmann, D., M. Carpenter, and M. Tomasello. 2009. Eighteen-month-old infants show false belief understanding in an active helping paradigm. Cognition 112: 337–342.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buttelmann, F., J. Suhrke, and D. Buttelman. 2015. What you get is what you believe: Eighteen-month-olds demonstrate belief understanding in an unexpected-identity task. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology 131: 94–103.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butterfill, S., and I. Apperly. 2013. How to construct a minimal theory of mind. Mind & Language 28: 606–637.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carey, S. 2009. The origin of concepts. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. 2016. Two systems for mindreading? Review of Philosophy and Psychology 7: 141–162.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. 2017. Mindreading in adults: Evaluating two-systems views. Synthese 194: 673–688.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. 1996. The conscious mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P.M. 1979. Scientific realism and the plasticity of mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clement, J. 1982. Students’ preconceptions in introductory mechanics. American Journal of Physics 50: 66–70.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. 1978. Beliefs about beliefs. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 1: 568–570.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. 1991. Consciousness explained. Penguin Press.

  • Dörrenberg, S., H. Rakoczy, and U. Liszkowski. 2018. How (not) to measure infant theory of mind: Testing the replicability and validity of four non-verbal measures. Cognitive Development 46: 12–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. 1988. Explaining behavior. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elekes, F., M. Varga, and I. Király. 2016. Evidence for spontaneous level-2 perspective taking in adults. Consciousness and Cognition 41: 93–103.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flavell, J., E. Flavell, and F. Green. 1983. Development of the appearance-reality distinction. Cognitive Development 15: 95–120.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flavell, J., F. Green, E. Flavell, M. Watson, and J. Campione. 1986. Development of knowledge about the appearance-reality distinction. Monographs of the Society for Research in Child Development 51: 1–87.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. 1990. A theory of content and other essays. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. 2015. Burge on perception. In The conceptual mind: New directions in the study of concepts, ed. E. Margolis and S. Laurence. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. 2006. Simulating Minds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A., and A. Meltzoff. 1997. Words, thoughts, and theories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A., and H. Wellman. 1992. Why the child’s theory of mind really is a theory. Mind & Language 7: 145–171.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. 1978. Studying the chimpanzees’ theory of mind. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 1: 576–577.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heyes, C. 2014a. False belief in infancy: A fresh look. Developmental Science 17: 647–659.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heyes, C. 2014b. Submentalizing: I am not really reading your mind. Perspectives on Psychological Science 9: 131–143.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacob, P. 2020. What do false-belief tests show? Review of Philosophy and Psychology. 11: 1–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kammermeier, M., and M. Paulus. 2018. Do action-based tasks evidence false-belief understanding in young children? Cognitive Development 46: 31–39.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keil, F. 1989. Concepts, kinds, and cognitive development. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Király, I., K. Oláh, G. Csibra, and Á. Kovács. 2018. Retrospective attribution of false beliefs in 3-year-old children. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 115: 11477–11482.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. 1966. An argument for the identity theory. Journal of Philosophy 63: 17–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. 1970. How to define theoretical terms. Journal of Philosophy 67: 427–446.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. 1986. On the plurality of worlds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCloskey, M. 1983. Naïve theories of motion. In Mental Models, ed. D. Gentner and A. Stevens. Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. 1984. Language, thought and other biological categories. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, G. 2002. The big book of concepts. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. 1987. Reality and representation. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. 1983. Sense and content. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. 1986. Thoughts: An essay on content. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Penn, D., and D. Povinelli. 2007. On the lack of evidence that non-human animals possess anything remotely resembling a “theory of mind”. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London, B 362: 731–744.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perner, J. 1991. Understanding the representational mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perner, J., and T. Ruffman. 2005. Infants’ insight into the mind: How deep? Science 308: 214–216.

    Google Scholar 

  • Premack, D., and G. Woodruff. 1978. Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? Behavioral and Brain Sciences 1: 515–526.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. 1967. The nature of mental states. In Art, mind and religion, Pittsburgh University Press. Reprinted in H. Putnam (1975). Mind, language and reality, ed. W. Capitan and D. Merrill. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.V. 1951. Main trends in recent philosophy: Two dogmas of empiricism. The Philosophical Review 60: 20–43.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saul, J. 2007. Simple sentences, substitution, and intuitions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scott, R., and R. Baillargeon. 2009. Which penguin is this? Attributing false beliefs about object identity at 18 months. Child Development 80: 1172–1196.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scott, R., and R. Baillargeon. 2017. Early false-belief understanding. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 21: 237–249.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scott, R., R. Baillargeon, H. Song, and A. Leslie. 2010. Attributing false beliefs about non-obvious properties at 18 months. Cognitive Psychology 61: 366–395.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seager, W., and D. Bourget. 2007. Representationalism about consciousness. In A companion to consciousness, ed. M. Velmans and S. Schneider. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shea, N. 2018. Representation in cognitive science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shtulman, A., and J. Valcarcel. 2012. Scientific knowledge suppresses but does not supplant earlier intuitions. Cognition 124: 209–215.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sloman, S., B. Love, and W. Ahn. 1998. Feature centrality and conceptual coherence. Cognitive Science 22: 189–228.

    Google Scholar 

  • Song, H., and R. Baillargeon. 2008. Infants’ reasoning about others’ false perceptions. Developmental Psychology 44: 1789–1795.

    Google Scholar 

  • Southgate, V., and A. Vernetti. 2014. Belief-based action prediction in preverbal infants. Cognition 130: 1–10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. 1999. Context and content: Essays on intentionality in speech and thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, G. 2006. Realistic monism – Why physicalism entails panpsychism. Journal of Consciousness Studies 13 (10–11): 3–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. 1989. Explanatory coherence. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12: 435–467.

    Google Scholar 

  • Träuble, B., V. Marinovic, and S. Pauen. 2010. Early theory of mind competencies: Do infants understand others’ beliefs? Infancy 15: 434–444.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. 1995. Ten problems of consciousness. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. 2000. Consciousness, color and content. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wellman, H. 1990. The child’s theory of mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wellman, H. 2014. Making minds: How theory of mind develops. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wellman, H., D. Cross, and J. Watson. 2001. Meta-analysis of theory-of-mind development: The truth about false belief. Child Development 72: 655–684.

    Google Scholar 

  • Westra, E. 2017. Spontaneous mindreading: A problem for the two-systems account. Synthese 194: 4559–4581.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimmer, H., and J. Perner. 1983. Beliefs about beliefs: Representation and constraining function of wrong beliefs in young children’s understanding of deception. Cognition 13: 103–128.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to Pierre Jacob, Evan Westra, and two anonymous referees for their comments on an earlier version of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Peter Carruthers.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Carruthers, P. Representing the Mind as Such in Infancy. Rev.Phil.Psych. 11, 765–781 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-020-00491-9

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-020-00491-9

Navigation