Hostname: page-component-7c8c6479df-8mjnm Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-03-29T13:31:56.770Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Filtering Friendship through Phronesis: ‘One Thought too Many’?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  11 October 2019

Abstract

An adequate moral theory must – or so many philosophers have argued – be compatible with the attitudes and practical requirements of deep friendship. Bernard Williams suggested that the decision procedure required by both deontology and consequentialism inserts a fetishising filter between the natural moral motivation of any normal person to prioritise friends and the decision to act on it. But this injects ‘one thought too many’ into the moral reaction mechanism. It is standardly assumed that virtue ethics is somehow immune to this objection. The present article explores this assumption and finds it wanting in various respects. Virtue ethics filters friendship through phronesis and thus inserts an extra thought into the mechanism in question. To escape Williams's curse, the only way is to argue that the extra thought required by virtue ethics is not ‘one thought too many’. The article closes with an attempt to show that, contra deontology, the friendship motivation in virtue ethics is derived from the moral virtue, not the intellectual filter, and, contra consequentialism, phronesis does not require the maximisation of value. The presumed advantage of virtue ethics must lie in the content of its filter rather than the filter's non-existence.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 2019 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, trans. Irwin, T. (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing, 1985), 207 [1155a5–6]Google Scholar.

2 Kapur, N. Badhwar, ‘Why It Is Wrong to Be Always Guided by the Best: Consequentialism and Friendship’, Ethics 101 (1991): 483504, p. 485CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

3 Williams, B., Moral Luck: Philosophical Papers 1973–1980 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

4 Cf. Kristjánsson, K., ‘Is the Virtue of Integrity Redundant in Aristotelian Virtue Ethics?Apeiron 53 (2019): 93115CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

5 Aristotle, The Athenian Constitution, The Eudemian Ethics, On Virtues and Vices, trans. Rackham, H. (London: William Heinemann, 1935), 405 [1240b15–19]Google Scholar; op. cit. note 1, 246–247 [1166b1–25].

6 Kristjánsson, K., Virtuous Emotions (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2018)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

7 Op. cit. note 1, 207 [1155a1–2].

8 See e.g. Card, R. F., ‘Consequentialism, Teleology, and the New Friendship Critique’, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 85 (2004): 149172, p. 149CrossRefGoogle Scholar, although Card refrains from categorising virtue ethics as a ‘theory’.

9 Op. cit. note 5, 433 [1244a17–19].

10 Contra e.g. Nehamas, A., On Friendship (New York: Basic Books, 2016)Google Scholar.

11 Kristjánsson, K., ‘Ten un-Aristotelian Reasons for the Instability of Aristotelian Character Friendships’, Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 49 (2019): 4058Google Scholar.

12 Op. cit. note 3, 14, my italics; cf. Bernstein, M., ‘Friends without Favouritism’, Journal of Value Inquiry 41 (2007): 5976, 67–68CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

13 Op. cit. note 3, 11.

14 Wolf, S., ‘“One Thought too Many”: Love, Morality, and the Ordering of Commitment, in Heuer, U. and Lang, G. (eds.), Luck, Value, and Commitment: Themes from the Ethics of Bernard Williams (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012): 7192, 74CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

15 See e.g. Railton's, P. classic piece, ‘Alienation, Consequentialism, and the Demands of Morality’, Philosophy and Public Affairs 13 (1984): 134171Google Scholar.

16 See e.g. Conee, E., ‘Friendship and Consequentialism’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 79 (2001): 161179CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Bernstein op. cit. note 12.

17 Flanagan, O., Varieties of Moral Personality: Ethics and Psychological Realism (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1991), 32Google Scholar.

18 See e.g. Telfer, E., ‘Friendship’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 71 (1970–1971), 223241, 235CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

19 Lyons, D., Forms and Limits of Utilitarianism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1965)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

20 Conee op. cit. note 16, 178–179.

21 Railton, P., ‘Intuitive Guidance: Emotion, Information and Experience’, in Seligman, M. E. P., Railton, P., Baumeister, R. F. and Sripade, C. (eds.), Homo Prospectus (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016): 33–85, 4546Google Scholar.

22 Op. cit. note 14.

23 Stocker, M., ‘The Schizophrenia of Modern Ethical Theories’, Journal of Philosophy 73 (1976): 453466CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

24 Cf. Woodcock, S., ‘Moral Schizophrenia and the Paradox of Friendship’, Utilitas 22 (2010): 125, 14CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

25 Cf. Cocking, D. and Kennett, J., ‘Friendship and Moral Danger’, Journal of Philosophy 97 (2000): 278296CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Cicero, How to Be a Friend, trans. Freeman, P. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2018), 35 and 45Google Scholar.

26 See Kristjánsson, K., Aristotle, Emotions and Education (Aldershot: Ashgate/Routledge, 2007), chap. 11Google Scholar.

27 Op. cit. note 1, 153, 154, 159, 164, 171 [1140a26–29, 1140b4–6, 1141b30–31, 1143a8–9, 1144b30–32].

28 Brienza, J. P., Kung, F. Y. H., Santos, H. C., Bobocel, D. R. and Grossmann, I., ‘Wisdom, Bias, and Balance: Toward a Process-Sensitive Measurement of Wisdom-Related Cognition’, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 115 (2018): 10931126CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

29 See Grossman, I., ‘Wisdom in Context’, Perspectives on Psychological Science 12 (2017): 233257CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

30 Darnell, C., Kristjánsson, L. Gulliford, K. and Panos, P., ‘Phronesis and the Knowledge–Action Gap in Moral Psychology and Moral Education: A New Synthesis?Human Development 62 (2019): 101129CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

31 See further in ibid.

32 Kaspar, D., ‘How We Decide in Moral Situations’, Philosophy 90 (2015): 5981CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

33 Dunne, J., Back to the Rough Ground: ‘Phronesis’ and ‘Techné’ in Modern Pilosophy and in Aristotle (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1993)Google Scholar.

34 Op. cit. note 26, chap. 11.

35 Op. cit. note 33, 157.

36 Ibid., 311.

37 Ibid., 314.

38 Ibid., 280, 293, 297 and 361.

39 Op. cit. note 1, 160–161 [1142a12–30].

40 Ibid., 243 [1165a35].

41 See e.g. Haidt, J., ‘The Emotional Dog and its Rational Tail: A Social Intuitionist Approach to Moral Judgment’, Psychological Review 108 (2001): 814834CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

42 See further in Kristjánsson, K., Flourishing as the Aim of Education: A Neo-Aristotelian View (London: Routledge, 2020), chap. 8Google Scholar.

43 Cf. Müller, A. W., ‘Aristotle's Conception of Ethical and Natural Virtue’, in Szaif, J. and Lutz-Bachmann, M. (eds.), Was ist das für den Menschen Gute?/What is Good for a Human Being? (Berlin: De Gruyter, 2004): 1853Google Scholar.

44 Op. cit. note 23.

45 Op. cit. note 1, 246 [1166a27].

46 Hursthouse, R., On Virtue Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), 74Google Scholar; cf. also. Carr, D., ‘Virtue, Mixed Emotions and Moral Ambivalence’, Philosophy 84 (2009): 3146CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

47 Hursthouse, ibid., 165.

48 Cf. op. cit. note 24.

49 Op. cit. note 1, 168, 171–172 [1144a6–9, 1145a4–6].

50 Ibid., 39–40, 168–169 [1105a28–32, 1144a13–22].

51 Irwin, T. H., ‘Aristotle on Reason, Desire, and Virtue’, Journal of Philosophy 72 (1975): 567578, 571CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

52 Op. cit. note 2, 503.

53 Mill, J. S., Utilitarianism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998)Google Scholar.

54 Kristjánsson, K., Justice and Desert-Based Emotions (Aldershot: Ashgate/Routledge, 2006), 146148Google Scholar.

55 Op. cit. note 2, 484.

56 Op. cit. note 8, 157.

57 Cicero op. cit. note 25, 35.

58 Bernstein op. cit. note 12, 67.

59 Op. cit. note 1, 224–225 [1160a4–6]; cf also 256 [1169a18–34].

60 Ibid., 241 [1164b25–1165a4].

61 Op. cit. note 5, 431–433 [1244a1–19].

62 Bernstein op. cit. note 12.

63 Op. cit. note 10.

64 Op. cit. note 3, 15–16.

65 Aristotle, On Rhetoric, trans. Kennedy, G. A. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007), 76 [1366b3–6]Google Scholar.

66 Op. cit. note 1, 43 [1106b1–7].

67 Ibid.,  295 [1180b9–11].

68 Op. cit. note 53, 71.

69 Op. cit. note 23, 458.

70 Op. cit. note 24.