Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Prolegomenon to a Southern Jurisprudence

  • Published:
Liverpool Law Review Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

It is good to take stock from time to time and to see how things stand in jurisprudence. So, what is the relationship of doctrine and theory with jurisprudence? Is private law theory apolitical while public law contains politics for the very many constitutional ends in the Global South? In India, legal theorist Chhatrapati Singh very originally asked if legal systems and normative systems were the same? Chhatrapati’s enquiry was however a species of the classical approach to the law that promotes the law’s purity. On the contrary, the postcolonial approaches account for the historical life as well as the political proclivities of the law. The private law theory often seen as impersonal and non-imperial comes under scrutiny in the postcolonial approaches. Duncan Kennedy and Roberto Unger notably problematized contract theory, while Upendra Baxi argued for mass tort as public law—contract and tort are both private law—to offer, if you will, a jurisprudence of the South. A southern jurisprudence essentially rejects an impersonal reading of the private law.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Foucault (1998: para 10).

  2. ‘[A]cademic doctrines and formulas count for very much more in American schools, it seems also in American Courts, than in ours.’ Pollock (1923: 163).

  3. ‘This conception of man as by nature a free and reasonable being gave rise to the potion of the liber et legalis homo, the free and lawful man of the English Law.’ O’Sullivan (1937: 27). ‘Arguments from precedent and analogy are two central forms of reasoning found in many legal systems, especially “Common Law” systems’. Lamond (2016: para.1).

  4. Finnis (1985: 23).

  5. Santos (2018: 4).

  6. Hegel (1824: 412).

  7. Marx (1847: 495).

  8. The Brazilian jurist Miguel Reale theorized ‘the law as experience’. Reale (1992: 7–20).

  9. Weber (1978: 53).

  10. Hegel defines custom as ‘activity without opposition’. Hegel (1824: 486).

  11. Anghie (1999: 1–80).

  12. Singh (1985) although original in his analysis is a dense writer. On 4 November 2019, an Indian Supreme Court bench comprising Gupta and Bose J.J. chided the Bombay High Court, one of the original colonial Presidency courts along with Madras and Calcutta, observing ‘we find it is unintelligible and we could not decipher what has been decided by the High Court.’ Accordingly, they ordered ‘the High Court to pass on an order which we can understand.’ Kapse v. State of Maharashtra (2019).

  13. Kennedy (1976: 1687).

  14. Ibid. 1778.

  15. Hart (1958: 594).

  16. Robert and Dreier (1990: 1).

  17. Singh (2019a: Section 2).

  18. Dagan and Kreitner (2011: 672).

  19. Ibid.

  20. Khaitan and Steel (2019: 1). Morss, on the other hand, reminds that “structuralism” was ‘a reaction against Husserl’s phenomenology.’ Foucault's ‘straddled the later phases of structuralism’ and those innovations were later defined as “post- structuralist”. Morss (2018: 246).

  21. Unger (1983: 565).

  22. Munshi (2017: 207–235)

  23. Baxi (2015: 21–40). ‘Human rights are as much about populations as they are about individuals.’ Morss (2019); Gupta (2019) on “mass tort” and India.

  24. Siddiq v. Das (2019: para 751).

  25. Unger (1983: 568).

  26. In Asia, while the civil law states often recruited European and Japanese lawyers to conduct legal reforms, the common law states were ex-colonies of Britain. Thus, semi-colonialism yielded civil law even as full-colonialism resulted in common law states. See, Singh (2019c).

  27. Santos (2018: 5).

  28. ‘[T]he global law “growing out of fragmented social institutions” does not emerge as integral but as itself fragmented’. Fitzpatrick (2001: 205).

  29. ‘Providing hospitable ground for critical and interdisciplinary projects aimed at exploring the colonial roots of both the contemporary nation-state system and globalized racial formations.’ Munshi (2017: 207).

  30. Kelsen (1982).

  31. ICJ Statute (1945, Art. 38.1.C). Finnis however gets it wrong when footnoting it to subsection “D” instead of “C” of the ICJ Statute Article 38(1). Finnis (2014: 134).

  32. Kelsen (1982, 65). Morss (2008: 85).

  33. Unger (1983: 567).

  34. I have tried to chart elsewhere the journey of jurisprudence in its many forms. Singh (2019a).

  35. ‘In common law, the method differs but is even more explicitly concerned to present determination as a function of prior determination, as the consequence of precedent decisions and their dry reiteration. In either case, the law is firmly placed “in the books,” and the method of extrapolation, elaboration, and instant determination is that of recovery and interpretation.’ Goodrich (2005: 190).

  36. Singh (2019a).

  37. Hart (1958: 593).

  38. Ibid.

  39. Ibid 595.

  40. Fuller (1958: 632).

  41. Fuller (1958: 632).

  42. Unger (1983: 563).

  43. Ibid. 564.

  44. Ibid.

  45. Finnis (1985).

  46. Unger (1983: 618).

  47. Finnis (1985: 21).

  48. Ibid. 26.

  49. DTC v. Mazdoor Congress (1990: para 15).

  50. Ibid.

  51. Ibid.

  52. Kennedy (1976: 1694).

  53. Jakson (1980: 5–20).

  54. Singh (2019b: 440).

  55. Serbian Loans case (1929: 40).

  56. Lauterpacht (1927: v).

  57. ‘The pure legal act, the determinant positing of autonomous law, has long been considered an inadequate rendering of what law “is”, even by legal positivists, yet there remains an operative commitment to its possibility that is hardly marginal. Without such a possibility, the rule of law could have no purchase.’ Fitzpatrick (2001: 73).

  58. “Indian judges have long used equity to ‘mitigated the rigour of the common law.’ Parelkar v. Mantri (1942: para 7).”

  59. ‘It is also well settled principle that the courts while interpreting the provision of an Act or rule the paramount consideration’ is “the ends of justice”. Reddy v. Bank of India (2002). ‘It was left to the discretion of the court to prescribe the limits of the retroactivity. There by, it enabled the court to mould the reliefs to meet the ends of justice.’ ECIL, Hyderabad v. Karunakar (1993: para. 29). ‘To enhance the sentence to seven years R.I. [rigorous imprisonment] by merely saying the “ends of justice” demand it is to continue the question, as Prof. Kelsen put it, not to meet it.’ Vijayakumar v. Public Prosecutor (1978: para 10). Gujarat v. Ambica Mills (1974: para. 37).

  60. Singh (2019a). ‘Laws in the postcolony do not lead to an automatic harvest of justice; justice requires us to harvest the law in a particular way.’ Singh (2018: 128).

  61. One of Baxi’s many contributions to jurisprudence in India is the rediscovery of Chhatrapati Singh. Baxi (2014: 5–24).

  62. Singh (1985).

  63. Ibid. 6.

  64. Ibid. 9.

  65. Singh (1985: 8).

  66. Law is a ‘juristic normative system’. Ibid.10.

  67. Ibid at 57.

  68. Ibid at 59.

  69. Singh (1985: 33).

  70. Swaminathan (2017: 28).

  71. Kesavananda Bharati case (1973: para 210) as cited in Madras Bar Association v. Union India (2014: para 56).

  72. Ibid 5.

  73. Ibid.

  74. Singh (1985: 22).

  75. Ibid. 22.

  76. Ibid. 23.

  77. Ibid at 37.

  78. Ibid at 37.

  79. Ibid. 38.

  80. Singh (1986: 38).

  81. Ibid. 38.

  82. Singh (1985: 38).

  83. Ibid. 39.

  84. Ibid. 60.

  85. Ibid. 61.

  86. Macaulay (1835: para. 34).

  87. Dworkin (1978: 7).

  88. Macaulay (1835: para. 34).

  89. Masani (2014: xiv).

  90. I make a distinction between Indian judges and the Indian Supreme Court. While the former is often methodless, the Supreme Court by the alchemy of legitimacy has created its own jurisprudence. Singh (2019a). It could be that the Court cares more for solutions than baring its method. And some judges, like Krishna Iyer, had more flare than other judges when writing opinions.

  91. ‘[O]ur constitution made legal issues out of problems that in England were political’. Dworkin (1978: 3).

  92. Baxi (2007: 7).

  93. Santos’s ‘Epistemologies of the South’ came out in 2014.

  94. Novartis case (2013: para 66).

  95. Kennedy (1976: 1777).

  96. Santos (2018: viii).

  97. Ibid. 12.

  98. Ibid.

  99. Hart (1958: 529).

  100. Fuller (1958: 669).

  101. Dworkin (1978: 3).

  102. Goodrich (1985: 112).

  103. ‘If the judgment does not represent in whole or in part the unanimous opinion of the judges, any judge shall be entitled to deliver a separate opinion.’ ICJ Statute (1945: Art. 57).

  104. Gingsburg (2010: 3).

  105. Ibid. 6.

  106. Anand (1965: 807).

  107. Karnataka v. Reddy (1977: para 45). About the addenda attached to Siddiq v Das (2019), Baxi says ‘anonymous judicial opinions are constitutionally impermissible’ and therefore ‘cannot be part of the judgment’. Baxi (2019: para 4).

  108. Ibid. para 50.

  109. ‘Legal relations between collectives can be analysed with reference to the classic account of Hohfeld without reducing those collectives to mere aggregates of individuals and without recourse to the legal fiction of treating the collective, for example the state, as a quasi-individual.’ Morss (2009: 289).

  110. Unger (1983: 569).

  111. Swaminathan (2019).

  112. For a critique of Dicey, see, Lino (2018: 739–764).

  113. Gupta (2019).

  114. Finnis (1985: 31).

  115. Baxi (2000: 301).

  116. Baxi (2015: 21–40). British and Indian courts have, moreover, generated remedies by finding tortious breach when contractual breach was not proved. Vader Veil and Compnay (1936: 405); National Bank of Lahore v. Sohanlal Sehgal (1965: 147).

  117. Khaitan and Steel (2019).

  118. Zumbansen notes ‘the recognition of a “world risk society” points to far-reaching consequences for legal theory, which has to assert itself’. Zumbansen (2012: 36).

  119. Unger (1983: 569).

  120. Jha (2019)

  121. Halpérin (2019)

  122. Hegel (1824: 487).

  123. Unger (1983: 568).

  124. Baxi (2015: 25).

  125. Santos (2018: 1).

  126. Kennedy (1976: 1685).

  127. Inspired by Richard Feynman’s tweet ‘Progress in science comes when experiments contradict theory.’ @ProfFeynman (31 October 2019, 7: 22 PM).

References

  • Anand, R.P. 1965. The Role of Individual and Dissenting Opinions in International Adjudication. International and Comparative Law Quarterly 14: 788–808.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anghie, Antony. 1999. Finding the Peripheries: Sovereignty and Colonialism in Nineteenth-Century International Law. Harvard International Law Journal. 40: 1–80.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baxi, Upendra. 2000. Mass Torts, Multinational Enterprise Liability, and Private International Law. Recueil des Cours 276: 301.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baxi, Upendra. 2007. The Rule of Law in India. Sur International Journal on Human Rights 6: 7–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baxi, Upendra. 2014. Chhatrapati Singh and the Idea of a Legal Theory. Journal of the Indian Law Institute 56: 5–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baxi, Upendra. 2015. Human Rights Responsibility of Multinational Corporations, Political Ecology of Injustice: Learning from Bhopal Thirty Plus? Business and Human Rights Journal 1: 21–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baxi, Upendra. 2019. Chiselling secularism. The Indian Express. November 12.

  • Dagan, Hanoch, and Roy Kreitner. 2011. The Character of Legal Theory. Cornell Law Review 96: 671.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, Ronald. 1978. Taking Rights Seriously. Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Finnis, John. 1985. On “The Critical Legal Studies Movement”. American Journal of Jurisprudence 30: 21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Finnis, John. 2014. What is the Philosophy of Law? American Journal of Jurisprudence 59: 133–142.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fitzpatrick, Peter. 2001. Modernism and the Grounds of Law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, Michel. 1998. Polemics, Politics and Problematizations. Interview by P. Rabinow, May 1984. In Essential Works of Foucault, vol. 1, ed. J.D. Faubion. New York: The New Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuller, Lon. 1958. Positivism and Fidelity to Law: A Reply to Professor Hart. Harvard Law Review 71: 630–672.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ginsburg, Ruth. 2010. The Role of Dissenting Opinion. Minnesota Law Review 95: 1–8.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodrich, Peter. 1985. Legal Hermeneutics; An Essay on Precedent and Interpretation. Liverpool Law Review 7: 99–155.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodrich, Peter. 2005. Slow Reading. In Nietzsche and Legal Theory: Half-Written Laws, ed. P. Goodrich and M. Velvedre, 185–200. New York/London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gupta, Arpita. 2019. Mass Tort Jurisprudence and Critical Epistemologies of Risk: Dissolution of Public-Private Divide in the Indian Mass Tort Law. Liverpool Law Review. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10991-019-09235-x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Halpérin, Jean-Louis. 2019. Personal Laws: Undetermined Norms and Undetermined Concept? Liverpool Law Review. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10991-019-09227-x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H.L.A. 1958. Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals. Harvard Law Review 71: 593–629.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, G.W.F. 1824. Philosophical History. In Man and the State: The Political Philosophers, ed. S. Commins and R. Linscott, 411–419. New York: Modern Pocket Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jakson, Bernard S. 1980. Towards a Structuralist Theory of Law. Liverpool Law Review 2: 5–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jha, Kinshuk. 2019. The Jurisprudence of Taxpayer Rights in India: An Evolutionary Tale in Direct Taxation. Liverpool Law Review. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10991-019-09239-7

  • Kelsen, Hans, and Stanley L. Paulson. 1982. The Concept of the Legal Order. American Journal of Jurisprudence 27: 64–84.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, Duncan. 1976. Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication. Harvard Law Review 89: 1685.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khaitan, Tarun, and Steel, Sandy. 2019. Theorising Areas of Law. https://ssrn.com/abstract=3464432.

  • Lamond, Grant. 2016. Precedent and Analogy in Legal Reasoning. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Edward Zalta. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/legal-reas-prec/. Accessed 1 Nov 2019.

  • Lauterpahct, H. 1927. Private Law Analogies of International Law. Calcutta: Longman, Greens & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lino, Dylan. 2018. The Rule of Law and the Rule of Empire: A.V. Dicey in Imperial Context. Modern Law Review 81: 739–764.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marx, Karl. 1847. The Communist Manifesto. In Man and the State: The Political Philosophers, ed. S. Commins and R. Linscott, 495–532. New York: Modern Pocket Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Masani, Zareer. 2014. Macaulay: Pioneer of India’s Modernization. Gurgaon: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morss, John. 2008. Can Custom Be Incorporated in Law? On the Place of the Empirical in the Identification of Norms. American Journal of Jurisprudence 53: 85–99.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morss, John. 2009. The Legal Relations of Collectives: Belated Insights from Hohfeld. Leiden Journal of International Law 22: 289–305.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morss, John. 2018. Description Without Apology? On Structures, Signs and Subjectivity in International Legal Scholarship. Indian Journal of International Law 58: 235–264.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morss, John. 2019. Cutting Global Justice Down to Size? Rights, Vulnerabilities, Immunities, Communities? Liverpool Law Review. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10991-019-09231-1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Munshi, Sherally. 2017. Comparative Law and Decolonizing Critique. American Journal of Comparative Law 65, Issue suppl_1: 207–235.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Sullivan, Richard. 1937. A Scale of Values in the Common Law. Modern Law Review 1: 27–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, Frederick. 1923. Plea for Historical Interpretation. Law Quarterly Review 39: 163–169.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reale, Miguel. 1992. O Direito Como Experiência: Introdução à Epistemologia Jurídica. 2nd ed. Editora Saraiva: São Paulo.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robert, Alexy, and Ralf Dreier. 1990. The Concept of Jurisprudence. Ratio Juris 3: 1–13.

    Google Scholar 

  • Santos, Boaventura de Sausa. 2014. Epistemologies of South. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Santos, Boaventura de Sausa. 2018. The End of the Cognitive Empire: The Coming of Age of Epistemologies of the South. Durham and London: Duke University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singh, Chhatrapati. 1985. Law from Anarchy to Utopia. New Delhi: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singh, Chhatrapati. 1986. The Dialectics of Law. Journal of the Indian Law Institute 28: 36–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singh, Prabhakar. 2018. More Norms, Less Justice: Refugees, the Republic, and Everyone in Between. Liverpool Law Review 39: 123–150.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singh, Prabhakar. 2019a. Spinning Yarns from Moonbeams: A Jurisprudence of Statutory Interpretation in Common Law. Statute Law Review. https://doi.org/10.1093/slr/hmy035.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Singh, Prabhakar. 2019b. The Private Life of Transnational Law: Reading Jessup from the Post-colony. In The Many Lives of Transnational Law Critical Engagements with Jessup’s Bold Proposal, ed. Peer Zumbansen, 419–440. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singh, Prabhakar. 2019c. Of International Law, Semi-colonial Thailand, and Imperial Ghosts. Asian Journal of International Law 9: 46–74. https://doi.org/10.1017/S204425131800005X.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swaminathan, Shivprasad. 2017. A Tale of two Harts: The Paradox in Essays on Bentham. Legal Theory 23: 27–54.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swaminathan, Shivprasad. 2019. Dicey and the Brick Maker: An Unresolved Tension Between the Rational and the Reasonable in Common Law Pedagogy. Liverpool Law Review. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10991-019-09228-w.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Unger, Roberto. 1983. The Critical Legal Studies Movement. Harvard Law Review 96: 561–675.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, Max. 1978 [1922]. Economy and Society: An Outline of Interpretive Sociology. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zumbansen, Peer. 2012. Comparative, Global and Transnational Constitutionalism: The Emergence of a Transnational Legal-Pluralist Order. Global Constitutionalism 1: 16–52.

    Google Scholar 

Cases, Statutes, Statements

  • Delhi Transport Corporation v D.T.C. Mazdoor Congress. 1990 Indlaw SC 224.

  • His Holiness Kesavananda Bharati v. State of Kerala. 1973. SCR Supp 1.

  • Kapse v. State of Maharashtra. 2019. Order. Criminal Appeal No.1638 of 2010.

  • Lingala Vijayakumar v. Public Prosecutor, Andhra Pradesh. 1978 Indlaw SC 149.

  • Madras Bar Association v. Union of India. 2014. 10 SCC 1.

  • Managing Director, ECIL, Hyderabad v. Karunakar. 1993 Indlaw SC 430.

  • National Archives of India.1965 [1835]. Minute by the Hon’ble T. B. Macaulay, dated the 2nd February 1835, in, H. Sharp (ed) Bureau of Education. Selections from Educational Records, Part I (17811839). Delhi, pp.107–117.

  • National Bank of Lahore v. Sohanlal Sehgal. 1965. Indlaw SC 147.

  • Novartis AG and others v Union of India. 2013. Indlaw SC 172.

  • Parelkar v. Mantri. 1942. 44 Bom LR 703.

  • Payment of Various Serbian Loans Issued in France (Fr. v. Yugo.). 1929. PCIJ (Ser. A) No. 20.

  • M. Siddiq (dead) v. Mahant Suresh Das & Ors. 2019. Civil Appeal Nos 10866–10867 of 2010.

  • State of Gujarat v. Shri Ambica Mills Ltd., Ahmedabad. 1974. Indlaw SC 404.

  • State of Karnataka v Shri Ranganatha Reddy. 1977. Indlaw SC 247.

  • Statute of the International Court of Justice. 1945. 33 UNTS 993.

  • Statute of the Permanent Court of International Justice. 1921. 6 LNTS 379.

  • Vander Veil and Co.1936. 1 KB 399.

  • Venkatachalapathu Reddy v. Bank of India. 2002. Indlaw AP 231.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Prabhakar Singh.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Singh, P. Prolegomenon to a Southern Jurisprudence. Liverpool Law Rev 40, 155–178 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10991-019-09237-9

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10991-019-09237-9

Keywords

Navigation