Skip to main content
Log in

How there Could be Reasons for Affective Attitudes

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Barry Maguire has recently argued that the nature of normative support for affective attitudes like fear and admiration differs fundamentally from that of reasons. These arguments appear to raise new and serious challenges for the popular ‘reasons-first’ view according to which normative support of any kind comes from reasons. In this paper, I show how proponents of the reasons-first view can meet these challenges. They can do so, I argue, if they can successfully meet some other well-known challenges to their view: distinguishing between right and wrong kinds of reasons, distinguishing between reasons, enablers, and defeaters, and providing an account of the relation between reasons and rationality. Whether proponents of the reasons-first view can meet these other challenges remains controversial. I do not try to settle these questions here, but rather show that the debate about the nature of normative support for affective attitudes is not going to be settled in isolation from them.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Rowland (2017) and Schroeder (2010) for arguments that proponents of the reasons-first view can distinguish between right and wrong kinds of reasons and McHugh and Way (2016) and Howard (2019) for arguments that they cannot. For arguments that the distinction between reasons, enablers, and defeaters is problematic see Hooker (2000), Crisp (2000), and Raz (2000). Bader (2016) argues that these problems can be solved. For arguments that rational requirements can be analysed in terms of reasons see Kiesewetter (2017) and Lord (2018). See Broome (2013) for critique of this view.

  2. Though Faraci does not address this point directly, none of his replies to Maguire’s arguments question them, so we can reasonably take this is another point of agreement.

  3. The buck-passing view originates from Scanlon’s (1998) account of value, but most agree that it can be extended to other normative properties such as admirability, see e.g. Schroeder (2010).

  4. See the literature cited in n. 1 for an overview of this debate.

  5. If you are skeptical of this claim, see Howard (2019) for a summary of persuasive arguments that it is not easily resisted.

  6. Faraci (2020, 228–9) similarly suggests that one can resist Maguire’s argument simply by maintaining that FMCs for disappointment are not ipso facto unfit-making considerations for pleasure. The present point is that the appeal to the right/wrong distinction allows us to not merely claim that this is so, but also to explain why it is.

  7. There are a number of reasons one might wish to be hesitant here. First, as we have seen, our intuitions about reasons for actions can easily be misleading when applied to affective attitudes. Second, our intuitions about reasons can be equally misleading when there are enablers or defeaters involved, as I discuss below. Finally, it is not clear why critics of the reasons-first approach should accept the claim that the facts about the dragon’s sharp claws and murderous looks combine as individual reasons for fear in Dragon Revisited. After all, they will say, that is precisely the claim the original Dragon case invites us to deny.

  8. Inspired by one of Jonathan Dancy’s (2004, 172).

  9. One might object that the propositional component is something like credences which are gradable, but it remains plausible that these credences would have gradable content. In any case, I take it that this is another point on which the merits of the reasons-based analysis should not turn.

  10. For arguments that rational requirements can be analysed in terms of reasons see Kiesewetter (2017) and Lord (2018). See Broome (2013) for critique of this view.

  11. As one reviewer points out, the basic idea here is similar to the suggestion by Maguire (2018, 798–9) that fittingness standards for complex or ‘overall’ affective attitudes may derive from standards for their component parts. The suggestion here is that, given that affective attitudes are generally complex, fittingness standards for affective attitudes are generally derivative in this way.

References

  • Bader R (2016) Conditions, modifiers, and holism. In: Lord E, Maguire B (eds) Weighing reasons. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 27–55

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Broome J (2013) Rationality through reasoning. Wiley-Blackwell, Chichester

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Crisp, Roger (2000). ‘Particularizing Particularism.’ In Brad Hooker and Margaret Olivia Little (eds.). Moral Particularism. Oxford University Press, Oxford, 23–47

  • Dancy J (2004) Ethics without principles. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Darwall S (2012) Bipolar Obligation. Oxford Studies in Metaethics 7:333–358

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Faraci D (2020) We have no reason to think there are no reasons for affective attitudes. Mind 129(513):225–234

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heuer U (2010) Wrongness and reasons. Ethical Theory Moral Pract 13(2):137–152

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hooker B (2000) Moral Particularism: Wrong and Bad. In Brad Hooker and Margaret Olivia Little (eds.). Moral Particularism. Oxford Univer- sity Press, Oxford, pp 1–22

  • Howard C (2019) The fundamentality of fit. Oxford Studies in Metaethics 14:216–236

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kiesewetter B (2017) The normativity of rationality. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lord E (2018) The importance of being rational. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Maguire B (2018) There are no reasons for affective attitudes. Mind 127(507):779–805

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McHugh C, Way J (2016) Fittingness first. Ethics 126(3):575–606

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raz J (2000) The Truth in Particularism. In Brad Hooker and Mar- garet Olivia Little (eds.). Moral Particularism. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 48–78

  • Rowland R (2017) Reasons or fittingness first? Ethics 128(1):212–229

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon TM (1998) What we owe to each other. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press

  • Schroeder M (2010) Value and the right kind of reason. Oxford Studies in Metaethics 5:25–55

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace RJ (2013) The Deontic Structure of Morality. In David Bakhurst, Margaret Olivia Little, and Brad Hooker (eds.). Thinking About Reasons: Themes From the Philosophy of Jonathan Dancy. Ox- ford University Press, Oxford, pp 137–168

Download references

Acknowledgements

For generous discussion of earlier versions of these ideas I am grateful to Alison Hills, Roger Crisp, Stephen Darwall, and Andreas Mogensen, as well as an audience at the University of Copenhagen and two anonymous referees from this journal.

Funding

Research for this article was supported by a grant from the Carlsberg Foundation, grant number CF18-0791.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alexander Heape.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Heape, A. How there Could be Reasons for Affective Attitudes. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 23, 667–680 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-020-10106-y

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-020-10106-y

Keywords

Navigation