Skip to main content
Log in

The Likelihood of Actions and the Neurobiology of Virtues: Veto and Consent Power

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

An increasing number of studies indicate that virtues affect brain structure. These studies might shed new light on some neuroethical perspectives suggesting that our brain network activity determines the acquisition and permanence of virtues. According to these perspectives, virtuous behavior could be interpreted as the product of a brain mechanism supervised by genes and environment and not as the result of free choice. In this respect, the neural correlates of virtues would confirm the deterministic theory. In contrast, I maintain that these findings do not undermine the role of willpower and freedom while reinforcing an interactionist view of free will. If virtues affect our neural system, then the predictability of the virtuous behavior follows. The likelihood of our future (moral) actions is primarily virtue-dependent; therefore, the acquired naturality of virtuous behavior is a source of predictable behavioral patterns outlining expected actions, which I propose to call Hypotheses of Action (HAs). However, the predictability of an action indicates its likeliness and not its certainty or necessity. The neural traces of virtues can be interpreted as major indicators of HAs. It is always possible for the agents to depart from their more likely, virtue-induced actions, but their deviations from the virtuous behavioral pattern are rare, as it is rare for the vicious/non-virtuous person to behave well systematically. This implies a reaffirmation of the notions of veto and consent as they provide a universal practical power affecting the subject’s use of moral virtues.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The idea of a discrepancy between rationality and emotivity has been widely criticized in contemporary moral philosophy and psychology, while the idea that emotions can be labelled as cognitive has been gaining strength within the world of emotion theories, thus widening the concept of knowledge (Solomon 2007II). Rationality and emotivity, from this perspective, cooperate toward global knowledge.

  2. The reference here is to the Kantian claim that the universalizability test is adequate to motivate moral acts, to be found especially in his Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals (trans Beck 1959, pp. 63–64). On this topic see also O’Neill (2004) and McCarty (2009).

  3. The kind of rationalism here addressed is related to internalism (Williams 1979), which typically maintains – in one of its basic forms – that the subject’s knowledge of the good, therefore her rational motivation, is necessary and sufficient to act morally, since normative reasons are dependent of one’s psychology (Schroeder 2007). By contrast, externalism assumes that moral judgment and motivation are just contingently connected, for moral motivation would require the combination of a moral judgment with a desire (Shafer-Landau 2000). Moral rationalism can be actually claimed both by internalists and externalists (Lord & Plunkett 2017).

  4. This basically physical interpretation of the role of emotions is countered by some experiential evidence, for example by our (at least partial and/or theoretical) capability of voluntarily containing our emotional impulses in our behavior, thanks to adequate motivations (De Sousa 1987).

  5. According to the evaluative theory of emotions based on appraisal, however, emotions would not necessarily induce likely moral actions, since a stimulus would be able to generate very different emotions in different people, or also in the same person at different times. For this reason, this theory suggests that it is not stimuli that elicit emotions, but stimuli as appraised (Arnold 1960; Frijda 1986).

  6. This is through the crucial role of self-control, which is also a virtue in their account (Roberts & Wood 2004; see also Mele 1985).

  7. The idea that virtues are emotion regulators is fascinating and deserves more attention in both virtue ethics and emotion studies (Algoe & Haidt 2009; Wilburn 2015; Navarini & De Monte 2019; Baima 2019).

  8. The idea that experience and behavior affect brain development is not new, although such a sensitivity of our synaptic connections to behavioral changes has been interpreted differently. Flanagan (1991, 1996) elaborated a deterministic view of the mind and the will that leaves no room for moral progress, all changes being driven by social and biological factors, whereas MacIntyre (2007III) believes that—after the Enlightenment—humankind had a sort of moral regress due to the loss of the traditional doctrine about virtues. Therefore, moral theories and practices must regain that perspective, which is stuck in the past. Others consider some recent neuroscientific research on morality and education (from Libet 1999 onwards), while trying to overcome them through a creative and flexible interpretation of the role of virtues in human moral behavior (Johnson 2003).

  9. Libet asked experimental subjects to perform simple movements, mostly the flexion of the fingers or wrist, and to estimate the time of their conscious awareness of the “urge to move” by reporting the position of a spot moving in a circle in an oscilloscope screen. He also recorded data with EEG. He discovered that our brain activates corresponding neural areas at least half a second before movement, and 250 milliseconds before we feel the urge to move. These data have been reinforced by subsequent studies (Soon et al. 2008). The fact that the change in brain potential occurred before the conscious decision has been interpreted sometimes as proof that our conscious decision to act is not the cause of the movement. Libet-like experiments suggest that conscious will is too slow to make things happen, and that volitional acts must result from unconscious processes in the brain, not from conscious will. Notably, Libet has always admitted that there is a power of veto allowing the subject to depart from the neurologically expected action.

  10. Thank you to an anonymous reviewer for suggesting me these observations on Soon et al. (2008).

  11. I am aware that this assimilation of brain innatism with (a sort of) determinism may sound too extreme, since in Churchland’s account there is an unquestionable contribution of experience to one’s progressive moral setting. Still, in his perspective brain schemes seem to prevail over personal will and conscious choices. Therefore, the interaction between brain and mind seems more in the brain-to-mind direction than in the mind-to-brain one, which is more consistent with the experientialist view I am suggesting.

  12. “This view of the assembled moral virtues as slowly acquired network of skills also contains an implicit critique of a popular piece of romantic nonsense, namely, the ideal of the ‘sudden convert’ to morality […]. Moral character is not something—is not remotely something—that can be acquired in a day by an Act of Will or by a single Major Insight” (Churchland 1998, p. 89).

  13. This means that moral activity is mapped on scientific activity, displaying the same neurological processes. The coexistence of a neurobiological hard base of virtue functioning and the emotional imaginative structure of morality makes him criticize Flanagan’s and McIntyre’s virtue ethics theories because of their alleged pessimistic or skeptical stance on moral progress caused by modern fragmentation. Churchland states that the contemporary loss of unity in social and moral values is the price to pay for humanity to grow up, thus rejecting the traditional “golden age” narrative with its nice but unproductive naïve imagery of good and evil. However, he considers himself a virtue ethicist, sharing Mark Johnson’s view of moral imagination (Johnson 1993).

  14. As an anonymous reviewer of this article noticed, this statement addresses the difference between the knowledge of what a virtue is and the fact of being virtuous.

  15. I am aware that my interpretation of Churchland’s account might be further discussed, since it could be argued that human neural architecture—developed by experience—is not necessarily linked to neural determinism. However, if I understood his though correctly, the pre-determined (neurological) component of virtues in his perspective is prevailing over experience and education, so limiting the role of willpower.

  16. She also underlines that deliberative rational ethics and intuitive ethics have to cooperate to illustrate moral phenomena. Nevertheless, when she comes to describing how morality works, she puts less emphasis than Churchland on the formal structure while stressing the intuitive component. Also see Narvaez and Vaydich (2008).

  17. Narvaez also shares Churchland’s view that moral rationalization does not necessarily promote good behavior, in tune with the larger virtue ethics tradition.

  18. Among neuroethical theories, determinism has been considered either incompatible with free will, such as in scientific isolationism and philosophical isolationism (De Caro 2007), or compatible, basically by affirming the dualistic nature of knowledge, which would involve free will at a psychological level (the mind) and would exclude it at a biological one (ibid).

  19. The interactionist model, when applied to neuroethics, can ascribe to the way of classifying the possible relationships between scientific determinism and human freedom (De Caro 2007, 2018).

  20. Tachibana (2017) apparently supports the idea of a moral change through neurofeedback training: “a subject is required to control the size of a circle, flame, or whatever visually and metaphorically represents the difference between the current and target brain states. By trial and error, a participant gradually modulates the brain activity into the target figure. The better the subject controls those visual representations, the more his or her current brain state approximates the target brain state. Since each of these states is the neural representation of target human faculties such as emotions, cognition, and/or behaviors (ECB), neurofeedback training enables a subject to self-regulate his or her ECB” (p. 26). Although this article has a different general end, namely the discussion of the admirability of moral exemplars, it seems that the possibility of virtue acquisition through this neural training is realistic and acceptable.

  21. De Caro (2007) argues that moving a finger or pressing a button when the subject “feels the urge” to do so (as the instructions of the Libet-like experiments reported) implicitly exclude free acts, which by definition are not urged. Therefore, either these acts are not free from the very beginning, or they are modifiable by the subject’s will until the very end of the deliberative process.

  22. As Gimenez Ayala (2011) points out, “the detection of neural activity at any morphological point in these networks does not necessarily imply that they are controlled independently of what we normally understand as the will. In other words, although they are not part of our ‘consciousness,’ it does not follow that the subject does not freely control them” (p. 53). The burden of proof remains with the neurobiological model and not vice versa.

  23. For example, Peterson and Seligman’s (2004) dispositional virtues can be interpreted in this way, while situational virtues are more similar to positive psychology’s state virtues.

  24. I do not intend here that being substantially virtuous and being continent overlap, since the latter condition is characterized by an inner fight against contrary desires, while the first displays the typical effortless feature of virtuous behavior, although in limited contexts (Athanassoulis 2013).

  25. I refer here to the traditional notion of free will as liberum arbitrium, or the power to choose among alternatives and to choose the means toward the ends (Aquinas, S.Th. I, q. 83). As Hoffmann and Michon (2017) put it, “free will in the broad sense does not require alternative possibilities, while free will in the narrow sense, which is liberum arbitrium, is precisely the power to make choices between alternative possibilities” (p. 2). Contrary to other scholars, Hoffmann and Michon claim that the Thomistic idea of free will is not a compatibilist one.

  26. I am very thankful to the two anonymous reviewers who helped improving this paper with their helpful comments.

References

  • Alfano M (2015) Ramsifying virtue theory. In: Alfano M (ed) Current controversies in virtue theory. Routledge, Oxon, pp 123–135

    Google Scholar 

  • Algoe SB, Haidt J (2009) Witnessing excellence in action: the “other-praising” emotions of elevation, gratitude, and admiration. J Posit Psychol 4(2):105–127. https://doi.org/10.1080/17439760802650519

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle (1925) Nicomachean ethics, trans. Ross D. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Arnold MB (1960) Emotion and personality. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Athanassoulis N (2013) Virtue ethics. Bloomsbury Academic, London-New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Baima NR (2019) Fighting pleasure: Plato and the expansive view of courage. J Value Inq 53(2):255–273. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10790-018-9666-5

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baumeister RF, Gailliot M, DeWall CN, Oaten M (2006) Self-regulation and personality: how interventions increase regulatory success, and how depletion moderates the effects of traits on behavior. J Pers 74(6):1773–1801. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-6494.2006.00428.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boella L (2008) Neuroetica. La morale prima della morale. Raffaello Cortina, Milano

    Google Scholar 

  • Carron P (2014) A case for virtue: Aristotle’s psychology and contemporary accounts of emotion regulation. In: Espina Y (ed) images of Europe. Past, present, future: ISSEI 2014 - conference proceedings, Universidade Catòlica Editora, Porto, pp. 1354—1362

  • Churchland PM (1998) Toward a cognitive neurobiology of the moral virtues. Topoi 17(2):83–96. https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1017186710699

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Caro M (2007) How to Deal with the free will issue: the roles of conceptual analysis and empirical science. In: De Caro M, Ferretti F, Marraffa M (eds) Cartographies of the mind. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 255–268

    Google Scholar 

  • De Caro M (2018) Free will and free rides. Acta Philosophica 27(1):15–26

    Google Scholar 

  • De Caro M, Vaccarezza MS, Niccoli A (2018) Phronesis as ethical expertise: naturalism of second nature and the Unity of virtue. Journal of Value Inquiry 52(3):287–230. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10790-018-9654-9

  • De Sousa R (1987) The rationality of emotion. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg M, Willer R, Antonenko O, John OP (2012) Liberating reason from the passions: overriding intuitionist moral judgments through emotion reappraisal. Psychol Sci 23(7):788–795. https://doi.org/10.1177/0956797611434747

  • Flanagan O (1991) Varieties of moral personality: ethics and psychological realism. Harvard University Press, Harvard

    Google Scholar 

  • Flanagan O (1996) Self expression: mind, morals and the meaning of life. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Frijda NH (1986) The emotions. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Gimenez Ayala JM (2011) A better understanding of freedom. An interdisciplinary approach to neuroscience and philosophy. In: Sanguineti JJ, Acerbi A, Lombo JA (eds) Moral behaviour and free will. A Neurobiological and Philosophical Approach. IF Press, Morolo, pp 47–60

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene Joshua D (2016) Our Driveless Dilemma. Science 352(6293):1514–1515. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.aaf9534

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gross JJ (2002) Emotion regulation: affective, cognitive, and social consequences. Psychophysiology 9(3):281–291. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0048577201393198

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • John OP, Gross JJ (2004) Healthy and unhealthy emotion regulation: personality processes, individual differences, and life span development. J Pers 72(6):1301–1333. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-6494.2004.00298.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haidt J, Joseph C (2004) Intuitive ethics: how innately prepared intuitions generate culturally variable virtues. Dedalus 133(4):55–66. https://doi.org/10.1162/0011526042365555

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haynes JD, Rees G (2005) Predicting the stream of consciousness from activity in human visual cortex. Curr Biol 15(14):1301–1307. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cub.2005.06.026

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Han H (2016) How can neuroscience contribute to moral philosophy, psychology and education based on Aristotelian virtue ethics? International Journal of Ethics Education 1(2):201–217. https://doi.org/10.1007/s40889-016-0016-9

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoffmann T, Michon C (2017) Aquinas on free will and intellectual determinism. Philosophers’ Imprint 17(10):1–36

    Google Scholar 

  • Immordino-Yang MH, McColl A, Damasio H, Damasio A (2009) Neural correlates of admiration and compassion. Proc Natl Acad Sci U S A 106(19):8021–8026. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.0810363106

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Libet B (1999) Do we have free will? J Conscious Stud 6(8–9):47–57

    Google Scholar 

  • Lord E, Plunkett D (2017) Reasons Internalism. In: McPherson T, Plunkett D (eds) The Routledge handbook of Metaethics. Routledge, New York, pp 324–339

    Google Scholar 

  • James W (1884) What is an emotion? Mind 9(2):188–205. https://doi.org/10.1093/mind/os-IX.34.188

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James W (1890) The principles of psychology. Holt, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson M (1993) Moral imagination. Implications of cognitive science for ethics. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago-London

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson R (2003) Virtue and right. Ethics 113(4):810–834

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (1959) Foundations of the metaphysics of morals. Trans Beck LW. Library of Liberal arts, New York

  • Kenny A (1963) Action, emotion and will. Philos Q 15(59):186–187

    Google Scholar 

  • Kristjánsson K (2018) Virtuous Emotions. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Kristjánsson K (2019) Flourishing as the aim of education: a neo-Aristotelian view. Routledge. https://doi.org/10.4324/9780429464898

  • McCarty R (2009) Kant's theory of action. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre A (2007III) After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory. Notre Dame University Press: Notre Dame

  • Mele AR (1985) Self-control, action, and belief. Am Philos Q 22(2):169–175

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller C (2014) Character and moral psychology. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Mullins AP (2012) An investigation into the neural substrates of virtue to determine the key place of virtues in human moral development, Dissertation, University of Notre Dame Australia. researchonline.nd.edu.au/theses/78. Accessed 25 June 2019

  • Narvaez D (2008) Human flourishing and moral development: cognitive and neurobiological perspectives of virtue development. In: Nucci LP, Narvaez D (eds) Handbook of moral and character education. Routledge, New York, pp 310–327

    Google Scholar 

  • Narvaez D, Vaydich JL (2008) Moral development and behaviour under the spotlight of the neurobiological sciences. J Moral Educ 37(3):289–312. https://doi.org/10.1080/03057240802227478

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Navarini C (2012) Autonomia e immaginazione morale. Etica, bioetica e neuroscienze. Editori Riuniti University Press, Roma

    Google Scholar 

  • Navarini C (2014) La difficile autodeterminazione dell’io fra esistenza ed etica. Dasein Journal 4(3):88–102

    Google Scholar 

  • Navarini C (2017) Autonomia eteronoma e diritti: la coesione sociale fra desideri e bisogni in prospettiva universalistica. In: Mauro L (ed) Social cohesion and human rights. Reflections on the Contemporary Society. FrancoAngeli, Milano, pp 103–116

    Google Scholar 

  • Navarini C, De Monte E (2019) Fear as related to courage: an Aristotelian-Thomistic redefinition of cognitive emotions. HUMANA.MENTE. J Philos Stud 12(35):167–189

    Google Scholar 

  • Neu J (2000) A tear is an intellectual thing: the meaning of emotion. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum MC (2001) Upheavals of thought: the intelligence of emotions. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • O'Neill O (2004) Kant: rationality as practical reason. In: Mele A, Rawling P (eds) the Oxford handbook of rationality. Oxford University press, Oxford; New York, pp. 93-108

  • Peterson C, Seligman MEP (2004) Character strengths and virtues: a handbook and classification. Oxford University Press, New York and American Psychological Association, Washington, DC

    Google Scholar 

  • Prinz J (2004) Gut reactions: a perceptual theory of emotions. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Rasmussen DM (2004) Defending reasonability: the centrality of reasonability in the later Rawls. Philosophy & Social Criticism 30(5–6):525–540. https://doi.org/10.1177/0191453704045751

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roberts RC, Wood WJ (2004) Proper function, emotion, and virtues of the intellect. Faith and Philosophy 21(1):3–24. https://doi.org/10.5840/faithphil200421114

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sauer H (2017) Moral judgments as educated intuitions: a rationalist theory of moral judgment. MIT press, Cambridge, mass; London

  • Schroeder M (2007) Slaves of the passions. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Shafer-Landau R (2000) A defense of motivational externalism. Philos Stud 97(3):267–291. https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1018609130376

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sibley W (1953) The rational versus the reasonable. The Philosophical Review 62(4):554–560. https://doi.org/10.2307/2182461

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Solomon RC (2003) Thinking About Feelings: Philosophers on Emotions. Oxford University press Oxford, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon RC (2007II) Not passion's slave: emotions and choice. Oxford University Press, New York

  • Soon C, Brass M, Heinze H, Haynes H (2008) Unconscious determinants of free decisions in the human brain. Nat Neurosci 11:543–545. https://doi.org/10.1038/nn.2112

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stark S (2001) Virtue and emotion. Noûs 35(3):440–455

    Google Scholar 

  • Stichter M (2018a) The skillfulness of virtues. Improving our moral and epistemic lives. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108691970

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stichter M (2018b) Virtue as a Skill. In: Snow N (ed) The Oxford handbook of virtue. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 57–81

    Google Scholar 

  • Tachibana K (2017) Neurofeedback-based moral enhancement and traditional moral education. HUMANA.MENTE. J Philos Stud 11(33):19–42

    Google Scholar 

  • Weng HY, Fox AS, Shackman AJ, Stodola DE, Caldwell JZ, Olson MC, Rogers GM, Davidson RJ (2013) Compassion training alters altruism and neural responses to suffering. Psychol Sci 24(7):1171–1180. https://doi.org/10.1177/0956797612469537

  • Wilburn J (2015) Courage and the spirited part of the soul in Plato’s republic. Philosophers' Imprint 15:1–21

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams B (1979) Internal and external reasons. In: Harrison R (ed) Rational action. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 101–113

    Google Scholar 

  • Younis R (2015) Neuroscience, Virtues, Ethics and the Question of Character. PESA Conference 2015 Papers. Retrieved from http://pesa.org.au/conference-2015/papers

  • Zagzebski LT (1996) Virtues of the mind: an inquiry into the nature of virtue and the ethical foundations of knowledge. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebski LT (2017) Exemplarist moral theory. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Claudia Navarini.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Navarini, C. The Likelihood of Actions and the Neurobiology of Virtues: Veto and Consent Power. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 23, 309–323 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-020-10081-4

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-020-10081-4

Keywords

Navigation