1 A slippery slope

The “return of religion” is a topic that has led to immense public attention and scholarly interest, especially in the last two decades. A vast variety of related phenomena quickly comes to mind. Consider, for instance, the resurgence of religious communities in many areas around the globe,Footnote 1 the development of novel forms of lived religiosity and “spiritual imaginaries,”Footnote 2 the comeback of “political theologies,”Footnote 3 and of course the problem of “religious violence.” All of these issues have motivated disputes across disciplines and sometimes even caused shrill polemics. Of paramount importance in this regard are especially the various forms in which “religious violence” appears and their spectacular display in the media. Whatever the primordial exemplary instances of “religious violence” may be, the category as such is already highly problematic and widely contested. Just consider a few concrete issues such as, e.g., the various brands of so-called religious fundamentalism, fanaticism, and terrorism “in the name of God”; literalist justifications of “sacred wars,” including forms of “caring Jihad,” “sexual jihad,” or so-called “suicidal bombing”; the return of ostracized practices such as exorcism, flagellation, and even crucifixion; the oppressive implications of “new puritanism” in the “bible belt” and elsewhere; or, finally, the refurbishment of religious narratives concerning purification and punishment in the recent “Corona-crisis.” As this selective survey indicates, and as work on “epistemic violence” has managed to demonstrate in a systematic fashion more recently, the concept of “religious violence” as such is highly problematic: all too often it works as a readymade label of social pathology, political defection, or, most generally put, “marker of irrationality” and is easily misused for ideological (and often racist) ends, most notably after the key event of 9/11.Footnote 4

The floating images of “religious violence” that we so easily encounter on the web and the related footage that is used to provide us with evidence of such things really happening undoubtedly raise a lot of concern. Given the all too apparent “irrationality,” the backward “barbarism,” and incomprehensible “senselessness” as well as “horrorism”Footnote 5 that seem to be the root cause(s) of such disconcerting incidents, we find ourselves perplexed. Still, as anthropologist Neil Whitehead formulated, such perplexity is not innocent. It is habitually used to commit us to a “scientific hunt for causation”Footnote 6 that is designed to bring things to a rationally justified “solution.” Confronted with the “other of reason,” it appears most necessary to use an “ethical epoché,” as Husserl once called it.Footnote 7 This is a practical epoché that is designed to guide us along if we find ourselves in pressing need to understand but feel that we should avoid short-circuited judgement. In a nutshell, “violence” and most notably “religious violence” epitomize the kind of otherness that befalls us and easily shakes our faculties of unbiased understanding and interpretation. Thus viewed, they indeed present a challenge to reason as such. As I argue here, this proves especially true for its disengaged brands, which became predominant and even hegemonic with the rise of political modernity, secularism, and the “liberal imaginary.”

“Discursive reason,” as Habermas has shown in this regard more recently,Footnote 8 is in fact not at all completely innocent. It definitely needs to preserve itselfFootnote 9 in light of such threatening challenges and has to remain vigilant in order not to fall prey to mere “imaginations of disorder” that are proliferating in our contemporary “cultures of fear.”Footnote 10 In order to promote a truly universal quest for “the inclusion of the other,”Footnote 11 our practice of “discursive reason” has to be careful in every step it takes: on the one hand, it must be cautious to not rationalize such otherness away, turning it into a problem to merely be solved, some “social pathology” to be remedied, a kind of deviance to be sanctioned, or a systemic dysfunction to be effectively adjusted. In other words, it must avoid falling into a self-righteous posture that all too easily renders itself sacrosanct but accounts for the other only on paternalist grounds.Footnote 12 Still, “discursive reason” also must avoid to let itself be swept away by the inspiration of some “wholly other,” whose claims irremediably call for answers but easily may become overwhelming, too.Footnote 13 Responding to the “religious other” and its sometimes indeed excessive claims, thus viewed, becomes a truly tricky affair.Footnote 14 Caught between our beloved illusions of autonomy and threatening imaginations of heteronomy, we end up between a rock and a hard place: tied at this threshold the inclination becomes strong to resort to dear patterns of thought that either silence this call of the other or turn us indifferent to the irrational babble it so ostensibly proves to be.Footnote 15

Given the previously mentioned, however, things perhaps are more complicated than they seem to be in the first place. By presenting “religious violence” as a marker for the presumed irrationality of religion, the “secularist doctrine”Footnote 16 did not only establish a profound schism between religious and secular world-views. It also managed to disavow every critical questioning of secularism’s normative claims to be prone to relativism and, in the last analysis, fanaticism.Footnote 17 As I argue, however, the secular quest for order is not only equilibrated by identifying some aberrant, unruly or disorderly quality in its “relevant others,” most notably its religious others. As we rather start to realize today, this quest indeed proves to be deeply dependent upon related projections. It does so to such an extent, that, finally, it becomes parasitic upon their presumed otherness.Footnote 18 This gesture, however, is more than suspicious. By way of pitting a whole imaginary of violence incarnate against the presumedly pacifying effects of secular modernity, the “liberal imaginary”—and its ideals of “discursive reason” and deliberation that it is said to actively purport—feed(s) into what Cavanaugh has aptly termed the modern “myth of religious violence.”Footnote 19 This myth, however, is not only most effective by way of exculpating state violence; it is most egregious indeed as it renders people structurally indifferent to the far-reaching effects of manifold invisible violences, thus impregnating the existential frameworks they are always already living in with inherently violent social imaginaries. Given this, our stance toward violence turns out to be truly fraught with ambiguities, the most disconcerting one being the inherently ambiguous embodiment—or “including exclusion” in Agamben’s wordsFootnote 20—of (especially religious) violence in our purportedly non-violent modern social imaginaries. To sum up in Mahmood’s words: “secular necessity” and “religious threat” are correlated in a vexed way today—a way that one-sidedly stigmatizes “religious affect” and sanctifies “secular reason.” It does so at the cost of eclipsing the potentials of “religious reason” and of exculpating the consequences of the “secular affect” going awry, however.Footnote 21

In light of this suspicion and of the conceptual inaccuracy—and finally ethical indifference—of the canon when confronted with this multi-faceted phenomenon, the discourse on “religious violence” indeed appears vexed with various quandaries. As has been discussed in religious studies more recently, the very conceptualization of “religious violence” is already a most critical one, albeit frequently eclipsed issue in contemporary philosophy and most notably in phenomenology, too.Footnote 22 This is not only due to the fact that this discussion has for a long time more or less been relegated to a host of neighboring disciplines which have been declared to be in charge of the issue: As to my hypothesis, this simple empirical fact concerning the social distribution of research agendas testifies to an even more basic problem that philosophy seems to have. Namely, the problem with its relevant others. Alongside the “specters of faith” and the narrative semantics of religious traditions returning to haunt the eternal “quest of reason” in a truly unprecedented—and also most ambiguous—way, one requires reason to confront its own discontents as well as productive participation in the imagination of its relevant others. Here, philosophy’s mission indeed becomes all the more difficult, perhaps even tainted.

We might employ some metaphoric resources of our philosophical imaginary in order to offer an account of the situation depicted. In the twilight of reason the Owl of Minerva, already threatened by an extinction of sorts, has to fly this low and is arriving this late, that perhaps it must face the light of some untimely sunrise, one which indeed might burn her feathering. Unlike Husserl believed, however, we do not seem to have any assurance left that the quest of reason still bears the Phoenix-like capacities to be reborn again in this kind of confrontation. Will, in other words, the very problem of “religious violence,” with its much more painful reedition of the more traditional question concerning faith and reason, become the Waterloo of philosophy? Or do we still own the tools to counteract this abysmal challenge, this widening gyre, which threatens to swallow up everything and let loose—to quote Yates—“mere anarchy” “upon the world”? Although these borrowings from the traditional philosophical imaginary might strike some readers to exaggerate the depicted state of affairs, I still deem it apt to catch at least one cardinal point: everything in this very imaginary seems to revolve around the threats of “mere anarchy,” “disorder,” or the lurking “fall into hostility toward the spirit and into barbarity.”Footnote 23 Perhaps the quest of reason, in a nutshell, has to turn into a quest for reason, some yet un-thought kind of reason to come, one which opposes both its relativist self-liquidation as well as its self-righteous (and hegemonic) ways of universalizing implementation. This situation—the ambiguity of religion in regard to violence, and the ambiguity that philosophy finds itself entrenched in once it confronts this issue head on—offers a true challenge for philosophy today.

As far as I can see, this challenge is mirrored in many contemporary questions that concern the interlacement of secular modernity with its assumed (or perhaps projected) other. In this regard the questions whether we have ever been really secular,Footnote 24 whether the concept of secularism applies only to the special case of “Europe,”Footnote 25 and whether the concept of religion is perhaps nothing but a secret weapon of Western hegemonic universalism,Footnote 26 are all of paramount importance. Adopting Asad’s most general answer, we may hold that the secular “is neither continuous with the religious that supposedly preceded it […] nor a simple break from it” and that “the concept of the secular cannot do without the idea of religion.”Footnote 27 This insight demonstrates clearly that any reasonable reflection concerning a “pure essence” of “religion” and, consequently, some permanent (assumedly opaque and irrational) core of all “religious violence” is, at best, simply misleading or, at worst, attests to a disavowed orientalist prerogative.Footnote 28 While such kind of critical assessment has come to be more accepted recently, it still has to face high stakes, as Mahmood expressly noted:

While these analytical reflections have complicated the state of academic debate about the religious and the secular, they are often challenged by scholars who fear that this manner of thinking forestalls effective action against the threat of “religious extremism” that haunts our world today. By historicizing the truth of secular reason and questioning its normative claims, one paves the way for religious fanaticism to take hold of our institutions and society. One finds oneself on a slippery slope of the ever-present dangers of ‘relativism.’ Our temporal frame of action requires certainty and judgment rather than critical rethinking of secular goods.Footnote 29

The introduction laid before you—and in fact all the contributions gathered in this special issue of Continental Philosophy Review—revolve around the conviction that questions, such as those mentioned, are not merely of interest for the sociology of religion, religious studies, the social psychology of religion, inter-religious pedagogics, or cultural anthropology. In pointing to the deep ambiguity toward “religion” that marks the prevalent self-understanding of secular modernity, those questions rather harbor an immense, albeit disconcerting philosophical potential, too. Without any doubt, this ambiguity has recently moved into the focus of quite many investigations across disciplines: religion is often reclaimed as a vessel for peace yet in very many instances it is also exposed as a major reason for, and medium of, violent conflict. It is controversially and oftentimes polemically discussed whether we are duped by the afore-mentioned “myth of religious violence” or whether inherently religious justifications of violence existFootnote 30; whether basically mundane forms of violence intentionally parade as “purported sanctity” (Pope Francis), mimic the splendor of some “divine violence” and hence misuse “religion” in instrumental terms, or whether there is something about it that attests to some irreducible “violent core” to be found in (all) “religion”; whether violence is intrinsic to religion or rather is to be conceived as some “temporarily misdirected behavior fostered by the narrative semantics of religion”Footnote 31—a misuse that but overshadows its positive potentials by definition. Still, one may respond to the quandary that all those formulations refer to. One might argue that it seems to be safe to assume that religion and violence are hardly strangers to each other but rather intersect—perhaps even intertwine—in various respects. However, the question then arises: does such a most general assessment help us in going further with and delving deeper into the question that we are facing?

2 Contextualizing the problem: on secularism and its discontents

To emphasize the deep ties between religion and violence attests to an insight, both old and most general. This insight does not tell us anything about the relationship between religion and violence as such; the specific forms it assumes, and the possible dynamisms it sets free. Without a doubt, “religious violence” is not at all picked as a novel topic. Perceptions, or rather interpretations of it, definitely played a foundational role in the constitution of modern political philosophy, especially in Hobbes’ work. It has since then persisted to influence the “philosophical imaginary”Footnote 32 of our political modernity. Today, however, the coordinates for thinking about it definitely have changed, although it frequently seems to take over the same role as the war-like “state of nature” as for Hobbes. The cultural anthropologist Appadurai has claimed more recently for a “new logics of violence”Footnote 33 with regard to globalization. Today, it calls upon us to revisit the claimed relationship once again and delve deeper into it. Given its spectacular appearances and unprecedented forms we need to give a contemporary account of it.Footnote 34

Building upon Appadurai’s anthropological insights, I argue that the changing “economies of violence” in the context of a globalizing modernity “spinning out of control,”Footnote 35 bear a massive impact on the ways we perceive and represent contemporary forms of what we have gotten used to unanimously call religious violence. Without a doubt, in the maelstrom of globalization such violence often (re)appears as something that is presented as the “accursed share” (Bataille) of a (premodern) condition we believe to have overcome and thus feel entitled to project onto our “others.” Today, however, “religious violence” cannot so easily be pinned down any more by conjuring up such a teratology of backward otherness and abject “medievalism.”Footnote 36 In fact, such a gesture not only disregards an existing variety of self-critical knowledge (e.g., in the so-called “wisdom traditions”) that has always been operative in all religious traditions, albeit in often suppressed and shrouded forms. The true problem about this gesture, however, is the fact that it proceeds as if our “neon Gods” of progress, “rationalist assimilation,”Footnote 37 or “relational co-existence” wouldn’t harbor a truly monstrous and inherently violent potential, too.Footnote 38 As we might rather suspect, these potentials are simply lurking so nearby and are so perfectly disguised in our liberal social technologies that we tend to overlook them by definition.Footnote 39 In this regard, our accustomed habits of indifference and projection go dearly hand in gloves. In addition to this already tantalizing insight yet another problem must be mentioned. As many scholars have recently shown, “religious violence” often appears as a critical, perhaps unavoidable reaction to the disconcerting discontents that late modernity has in fact brought about from within.Footnote 40 Accordingly, it also appears, as Derrida famously put it, as a kind of violence that—astonishingly only at first sight—belongs to “two ages” at once. In other words, it is triggered by the very tendencies that have once been implemented by attempting to effectively ban it:

In our ‘wars of religion’, violence has two ages. The one, already discussed above, appears ‘contemporary’, in sync or in step with the hypersophistication of military tele-technology—of ‘digital’ and cyberspaced culture. The other is a ‘new archaic violence’, if one can put it that way. It counters the first and everything it represents. Revenge. Resorting, in fact, to the same resources of mediatic power, it reverts (according to the return, the resource, the repristination and the law of internal and autoimmune reactivity we are trying to formalize here) as closely as possible to the body proper and to the premachinal living being. In any case, to its desire and to its phantasm. Revenge is taken against the decorporalizing and exproriating machine by resorting—reverting—to bare hands, to the sexual organs or to primitive tools, often to weapons other than firearms <l’arme blanche> […] This archaic and ostensibly more savage radicalization of ‘religious’ violence claims, in the name of ‘religion’, to allow the living community to rediscover its roots, its place, its body and its idiom intact (unscathed, safe, pure, proper). It spreads death and unleashes self-destruction in a desperate (auto-immune) gesture that attacks the blood of its own body: as though thereby to eradicate uprootedness and reappropriate the sacredness of life safe and sound. Double root, double uprootedness, double eradication.Footnote 41

According to Derrida, this “auto-immune logic,” however, distinguishes not only the pragmatic incapacity of religious life forms to come to terms with the challenges that late modernity and globalization bring about. It is also, in a truly constitutive way, part and parcel of the secular (that is, presumedly legitimate)—violence, albeit perfectly disavowed in our master narratives of rationalization and legitimization.Footnote 42 What Nietzsche in Daybreak once called the Apollonian “veil of reason,” perfectly seems to apply in this context:

Wars or military ‘interventions’, led by the Judaeo-Christian West in the name of the best causes […], are they not also, from a certain side, wars of religion? The hypothesis would not necessarily be defamatory, nor even very original, except in the eyes of those who hasten to believe that all these just causes are not only secular but pure of all religiosity.Footnote 43

If we read these two quotes together, we come to see the deep ties that silently bind the very phenomenon of “religious violence” to the profound crisis of our contemporary “social imaginaries.” Indeed, as a closer look reveals, the unprecedented phenomenal presence of “religious” motives and justifications in our “new logics of violence”—especially in the theater of today’s “new wars” and the excessive media staging of such apparently irrational cruelties—betrays an intricate yet disavowed relationship between our late “modern social imaginaries”Footnote 44 and its presumed other. In this context the trope of “religious violence”Footnote 45 is frequently used to epitomize this “wholly other” in a most exemplary fashion. Represented in terms of some unassimilable “opacity,” “irrationality per se,” or “violence incarnate,” this trope is ready at hand to animate imaginations of disorder. Thus viewed, it furnishes the self-righteousness of “secularized reason” on its hunt for “rationalist assimilation” (Kearney), “inclusion on Draconian terms” (Appadurai), or generally speaking a provisory integration (Habermas) with a good conscience. In a nutshell, however, all these phenomena are complicit in further creating an image of violence—and in particular “religious violence”—as the other per se, while disavowing the normatively embellished violences they contain and proliferate on a global scale. A vast variety of phenomena attests to the discontents that this situation brings about: the overstrained promises of globalization turning wild; a neoliberal world order running havoc in the name of progress; the fault lines of a political modernity giving rise to a deep political vacuum today, inviting populism and perhaps something worse; and the indifferent nihilism of a widespread “ideological secularism” that seems to have no answers left to the existential claims of finitude and suffering, and for all that “cries to heaven” (Habermas)—all these disconcerting developments indeed point at the irreducible ambiguity of our late modern predicament.

As for my hypothesis, this ambiguity of our contemporary situation is due to the fact that the widening fault lines of “secularized reason” and a modernity “spinning out of control” do not simply mirror the deficiencies—or rather antinomies—of a yet unfinished project. In other words, the predicament of late modernity is not a merely contingent crisis that will be overcome by further reliance on some teleological spirit, civilizational process or functional algorithm, which will in the long run help to dissolve all contingent forms of “deviance,” “disorder,” and “irrationality.” On contrary, the predicament of our post-secular constellation rather points at a much more deeply rooted intertwining of (late) modernity and its own, disavowed violences. As it has been argued recently on various occasions, this twisted intertwining becomes more and more visible today in the context of global developments in technology, communication, and finance capital. Developments in exactly those fields have especially led to a profound transformation of our political economy of conflict, traditionally conceived in terms of a “strained harmony” (harmonia palintrope) (from Heraclitus to Hegel and beyond). The proliferation of so-called “new wars,” to mention just one striking example, is most telling in this regard. This most recent phenomenon reflects a profound change in contemporary warfare with war turning into “a mutual enterprise rather than a contest of wills.”Footnote 46 This development attests to an exemplary transformation of the occidental matrix of political thought since it undercuts all traditional attempts at thinking war in relation to an overarching principle of peace, or some other way of securing some basic “bonds of separation.” Furthermore, it indicates clearly that the afore-mentioned predicament needs to be addressed critically with a view to the afore-mentioned new global “logics of violence,” that is, by looking at those potentials which obviously thrive on the unprecedented implications of a derailing modernity and, especially, the neoliberal calculus running havoc on the global scale, e.g. by way of creating “war economies” that feed back into said “cultures of violence.”

Given the incapacity of our beloved modern master narratives of “progress,” “cosmopolitan justice,” “discursive reason,” “reciprocal recognition,” etc., to confront these challenges in a productive and sustainable way,Footnote 47 this situation calls for different means of articulation and response. It is exactly in this context that the global “return of religion” has become of paramount importance for our beleaguered late modern “social imaginaries,” especially with regard to their by now all too apparent fault lines and proliferating discontents. “Religion,” in this context, has to be explored as a transformative or liberating way of life rather than in traditional terms of belief or doctrine; in terms of meaning-generative schemas that guide the basic human “struggle for concordance in discordance” (Ricoeur) instead of some presupposed subjective “core experience” or isolated subjective act and attitude; and in terms of the existential truth of religion and its practical as well as expressive relevance. Caputo, on his part, clearly points at all of this, attempting to clarify what kind of “truth” it might be:

Religious truth is not found in having certain information or beliefs that will gain one insight into a supersensible world or a ticket of admission to an afterlife. Religious truth is not a matter of information—as if it reveals certain facts of the matter otherwise unavailable to empirical inquiry or speculative ‘reason’—but a matter of transformation, with the result that religious truth takes place in and as the truth of a form of life. […] Religious truth is more a matter of doing than of knowing, as when Kierkegaard said that the name of God is the name of a deed. That means that religious truth flies beneath the radar of both the theism and the atheism of the Enlightenment. Its truth has to do with a more elemental experience that precedes this distinction, one that cannot be held captive either by confessional religion or reductionistic critiques of religion.Footnote 48

3 Detours into a phenomenology of “religious violence”

In order to explore this “truth” and the transformative potential that “religion” harbors, both for good and bad, a phenomenological account appears to be suited. It seems to be most promising indeed inasmuch as it enables us to explore the meaning-generative force that this elemental experience so ambiguously introduces into our contemporary social imaginaries—imaginaries, which, as I have argued thus far, engender their own fault lines and unprecedented discontents. What appears most intriguing in the context of the contemporary “return of religion” and related attempts at thinking a “post-secular constellation” (that would be able to meet this challenge head on) is the very ambiguity of what is returning now under the former name of “religion.” On the one hand, the “post-secular constellation,” understood in light of critical reflections as those, appears to replete with imaginations of “religious violence” and social technologies created in order to confront a variety of disorderly threats, taking shape both without and within. Such hetero-normative social technologies of “religion making” reverberate heavily, as Goldstone argues, especially in the liberal imaginary and how it is designed to take care of the “religious other”:

To be sure, secularism takes on myriad configurations, and they do not all insinuate a common telos; likewise, the subjects it produces and the relationship to ‘religion’ it enjoins will vary across time and space. […] But amid the geopolitical-ideological terrain in which we currently find ourselves […] secularism is ineluctably bound up with sovereign power, and together they constitute a politics of religion-making. Violence figures prominently in this arrangement: both as that which might at any time erupt among certain forms of religious life and as that which the secular state inflicts in order to forestall such threats and to better facilitate its various modes of subjectivation and accumulation. One is transgressive, inhumane, gratuitous; the other, necessary and salvific, administered on behalf of universal humanity and in accordance with ‘a secular calculus of social utility and a secular dream of happiness’ (T. Asad).Footnote 49

On the other hand, the various forms in which the “revival of religion” today stand up in opposition against an aggressive “ideological” and sometimes explicitly “sacrificial” secularism,Footnote 50 masquerading the purported liberation and autonomy, the salvific qualities of progress and technology, or the near deification of the (post)human—all of these forms attest to the yet unequalled, creative potentials of “religion,” that is, the wager of religious imagination. Epitomizing the insight that indeed “something is missing” (Habermas) in our secularistically hardened attempts to creatively outbalance our modernity “spinning out of control,” these forms testify—for better or worse—to the truly poietic force of the religious imagination.

Such force, however, not only shapes and sustains traditional patterns of individual conduct and collective existence. It also embodies the critical power to transform them and create new ones. Meandering, on the one hand, between unprecedented acts of violence done “in the name” of rehearsing religious narratives of “purity” or “unscathed belonging” and, on the other hand, promises of non-violent self-transcendence as well as “making transcendence together,” religion epitomizes for many—especially for those whose dissent cannot be expressed in the paternalist medium of “achieved consensus” (and “salvaging translations”)—perhaps the only remaining “force of exception.”Footnote 51 The question whether or not it indeed is the only force that might still be able to transform our contemporary “wastelands of sense”Footnote 52 and recreate the human appeal in a disordering world, cannot be taken up here in more detail. The much smaller but definitely haunting question to be answered is a different one: we need to ask how the appeal of this transformative potential, which promises even “hope for the hopeless” and “the truly destitute ones,”Footnote 53 can be channelled constructively so as to avoid its tendency of turning obsessive, fundamentalist, or fanatic, that is, become violent.Footnote 54 As we have come to see, this question still gains importance in a situation where the crisis of secular liberalism converges with the collapse of a truly disembodied and fully procedural society, with traditional resources of meaning clearly becoming scarce. In that context we also begin to realize that the post-secular premise is not only overly rationalistic, but also heavily underestimates the affective, community instituting power of religion.Footnote 55

In this regard, following Charles Taylor’s analysis developed in A Secular Age,Footnote 56 we may argue that the “buffered self” that secular modernity has birthed, is about to pay for its newly won autonomy with symptoms of exhaustion as well as depression, and for social emancipation with ever deepening experiences of loneliness and isolation. Deteriorating visions of the “good life” and the “common good” also feed into this development, as we confront a truly uncanny alienation from our sustaining life-worlds today. Such proliferating alienation and affective collapse of societies, however, seems to be but a side-effect of our all too successful attempts to liberate ourselves from the constraints of nature, finitude, and contingency. By projecting a trans-, or posthuman nature that appears to be designed to assure something as a “global immanence” or “relational existence” in an age of spectacular “super-diversity,”Footnote 57 the “tragedy of the modern condition”Footnote 58 confronts us with a real loss of grounds, which only travesties as purported autonomy. As a closer look reveals, this malaise but exposes our deep, disavowed dependency on the perceived threats that our cultures of fear and paranoid securitization are selling out systemically, to the extent of finally becoming obsequious to and finally even parasitic upon such threats and projections. A recent critical discussion of the “Anthropocene” and its “relational universalism” testifies to this very tragic ambiguity:

Despite the mournful tenor of discourses on the Anthropocene, where we regret having thought of ourselves as separate from nature for so long, the era of the Anthropocene has more often than not figured the end of the world as what must be avoided; we must not fall back into a nomadism that would bear no profound relationship to the globe. There is very little sense, however, that – despite the common recognition that the Anthropocene has a violent, destructive and barbarous history as its cause – other (less robustly global and relational) forms of existence might be viable, desirable, or recognizable. Those other forms of human existence, which were erased in order to achieve the state-centered history of humanity that recognizes itself as ‘Anthropos,’ are deemed to be the ‘end of the world’ – primarily because of their impoverished conception of relationality.Footnote 59

As this disconcerting passage tells us, the “explicit moralism” of “post-human relationality” (following up on the implicit moralism of communicative reason) produces the “accursed share” that the social fabrics of our late modern imaginaries require in order to work. Whatever contradicts the presumed immanence of “relational becoming” and its procedural avatars (with neoliberalism being the lone figurehead today), it epitomizes the worst violence imaginable. Neoliberalism, thus viewed, is a true “theology of waste”: it recycles or rather produces its “ir/relevant other,” and in fact manages to do so by relegating its otherness to those contested spaces around the globe (both within and beyond the traditional borders of the nation state) that are represented to be prone to violence, that is, to embody a disorderly threat to the neoliberal rollout.Footnote 60 Neoliberalism, thus viewed, appears paradigmatic for modernity’s being parasitic upon the imagination of some non-integrable, violent otherness. This need permanently be (re)produced as its very other in order to keep its literally “critical” business alive and kicking.

Thus viewed, the inherently modern business of critique closely relates to the systemic crisis brought about by the very project of modernity. In this regard, the critical developments I have dealt with in the preceding sections epitomize but the discontents of a late modernity that, apparently, have not arrived “past the last post.” In other, namely Kantian, words, our belief in the “civilizing process” has not managed to transcend the “inevitable antagonism” ruling humankind and to navigate through a natural history of destruction in order to arrive at a general “condition of calm and security.” That is, to leave “the lawless state of savagery” behind.Footnote 61 As I have argued, the unprecedented developments of “a derailed modernity” rather point into a significantly different direction today. They not only give us to understand that violence is woven into “the political forms of modernity” (Lefort) in an irreducible fashion. Even worse, they call upon us to finally approach the truly uncomfortable insight that humankind indeed is deeply parasitic upon, namely the ready-made otherness of such “violence,” however infamous and abject its cultural representations may appear to us, however disconcerting the dismay of images may be. More generally put, I hypothesize that the very ostracizing of a kind of extraordinary and excessive violence but complements the (more or less) smooth functioning of our societies in order to eclipse and disavow their own, order-preserving violences.Footnote 62 The structural rule of various systemic forms of violence, the resulting indifference towards the suffering of others and the “deadly consent”Footnote 63 that it entails: all of this is suppressed by way of presenting violence as our “accursed share” (Bataille). That is, something that we ought to get rid of—something that the trope of “religious violence” so dearly epitomizes. This parasitism, however, is not to be misperceived in terms of a contingent outcome of some deliberately misconstrued politics, political ideology, alienating exclusion, or “social pathology.” Rather, I argue that we need to understand it as a necessary byproduct of modernity as such, or, in Derrida’s words, its “originary supplement.” In this regard it is of paramount importance to note the related eclipse of violence as a both basic and irreducible problem in social philosophy and political theory. As a matter of fact, this “problem” was played out in the genealogy of the modern state and the legitimation of a “monopoly on violence” that has been afforded. As Das and Poole clearly explain: “In this vision of political life, the state is conceived of as an always incomplete project that must constantly be spoken of—and imagined—through an invocation of the wilderness, lawlessness, and savagery that not only lies outside its borders but also threatens it from within.”Footnote 64

If we take this observation seriously, we need to accept a hard truth: that the constitution of the political with regard to such a warlike “state of nature” (Hobbes), which has been presented as the matrix of political theory for centuries, does firstly require the construction of a counterfactual bugaboo of such a “state of war”—whether by presenting it as the “censored chapter” of the modern self or by projecting it onto others, allegedly threatening others. Secondly it requires, as the procedure results in marginalizing and disavowing the violences of its own rule by fabricating the said imaginations of disorder and by representing others as this kind of violence incarnate, the ordering of (religious) violence, as Goldstone has shown convincingly. It thus apparently requires eclipsing the (religious) violence of ordering:

Remaining mindful of and, indeed, vigilant against this specter of the worst has played a constitutive role in the structuring of modern subjectivities, authorizing new political arrangements and the array of preventative and punitive measures – from profiling and surveillance to intimidation and torture – intended to keep the danger of religious passions at bay.[…] Equally significant, though, are the ways in which visions of what might be thought of as religion’s best possibilities – from helping to maintain civic virtues and morally buttressing ideas such as democracy and human rights to, at the very least, mandating that one’s beliefs be held in a sufficiently modest and noncompulsory manner – have served to underwrite the brand of religiosity that a liberal culture normativizes and seeks to bring about or failing that, to marginalize and render obsolete. Which is only to say that it can no longer be assumed that secularism naturally resists all theologico-political formations, for it is precisely a distinctive – and often no less terrifying – political theology that it wishes to inaugurate.Footnote 65

While this is not the place to discuss this truly disconcerting hypothesis in detail and to assess how it potentially corrupts some amongst our most dear patterns of political thought, it offers an important clue to understand what kind of phenomenological enterprise we deem fit to confront these realities. As I have argued, the “crisis of secularism” and its contemporary discontents are related in a most tricky way to the ways of perception of the “return of religion” in general. In particular, the “black box” of “religious violence.” As our observations have shown, we thence cannot but underwrite Heidegger’s most basic hermeneutic insight. That is, any phenomenological inquiry into the varieties of religious experience and (mal)practice has to start “from out of our own historical situation and facticity.”Footnote 66 This insight requires that the phenomenological method applied has to proceed in a diacritical way. In other words, it has to focus in a most meticulous fashion on the “as-structure” that designates, mostly in a pre-reflective and unthematic fashion how those realities are perceived by us in an already interpreted way. It has to ask how some kind of social action is perceived as “violence,” how it is interpreted in “religious” terms, and what the marker “religious” is taken to designate in the respective contexts. As suggested, the social imagination and symbolic institution of “religious violence” in terms of “opacity,” “irrationality” and “violence incarnate”—frequently epitomized as senselessness—plays an indeed crucial role in the integration of our contemporary social imaginaries. In ambiguously lingering between threat and fascination, it epitomizes the “mysterium tremendum et fascinans”Footnote 67 of our late modern “political theologies” in an age of waning statehood and sovereignty. It figures as a paradigmatic imagination of disorder against which our social worlds are pitted and our concepts of freedom, autonomy, and sovereignty are taken in order to be shaped. In other words, our social, cultural, and political ideals of freedom and sovereignty are posited over and against the threats of vulnerability and disintegration that these imaginations of “senseless violence” are taken to embody in an exemplary way.

In the last decade, phenomenology has contributed a lot to describing and deconstructing this so-called “myth of senseless violence.”Footnote 68 Various contributions have explored how violence is not only destructive sense but is also built into the very fabrics of social life, cultural practice, and the genealogy of “the political.”Footnote 69 Interestingly enough, however, this variety of phenomenological investigations into the many faces of violence—be they physical, psychological, linguistic, structural, epistemic, or collective—has thus far not led to any attempt at confronting the disconcerting realities of “religious violence.” Bearing this in mind, it was the declared task of the papers collected for this special issue to mark a first, hopefully pioneering step into this direction, however selective and contestable it may be to force the vast variety of phenomena into an eidetic outlook. As the introduction has argued, the very attempt at isolating the Sache selbst indeed is haunted by serious objections. These objections pertain not only to the discursive construction of its very object but also to its transgressive dynamics. As I have attempted to demonstrate, it is a constitutive trait of this dynamics that it transpierces the borders of our beloved modern conceptual distinctions: whether we nominate them in terms of the secular and the sacred, moral religion and fallible parerga, communicative reason and social pathology, or order and disorder—the parasitic character of any order deemed pure or neutral but betrays the violence of its effects. As this order necessarily revolves around the blind spots of its normative institution, we end up ostracized from any safe haven, whether we may search for it in the arcanum of subjectivity, an apriori of discourse, or the all too smooth functioning of our social technologies. In other words, there is no direct way to phenomenologically confront the trope of “religious violence.” It requires, as I have put it, a diacritical phenomenology, one that proves capable to confront what Husserl called UnwesenFootnote 70—an idiomatic German expression that can neither be translated in terms of non-essence nor of disarray.

4 An outlook on the contributions

In light of these remarks and observations, let me finally offer some words on the contributions that are assembled in the special issue at hand. All of them deal with a variety of divergent facets. Without a doubt, a special issue is definitely not the right place to proceed in a monograph-like fashion and to systematically unravel any eidetic structures of the phenomenon at stake. Interestingly enough, however, some topics are recurrent and some conclusions, in the last analysis, seem to converge in certain ways. Albeit that I am strongly aware of the fact that this brief summary is hardly able to even compile more than just a brief selection of some cardinal motives and relevant figures of thought, I hope it will suffice to flesh out at least in nuce how the contributions not only revolve around similar problems but also contribute—given their diacritical stance toward the trope of “secular modernity”—to a more in-depth reflection concerning the general discontents that I have carved out in this introduction.

Most clearly related to this general outlook that I have sketched, stands Mensch’s inaugural contribution, which sets the stage for all of the following ones. It head on confronts the question that appears to be essential for understanding the predicament of the “post-secular constellation” and its vexed relationship to the ambiguous trope of “religious violence.” While not relating his reflections to Habermas’ basic question concerning “what is missing” from secular life, Mensch directly focuses—by applying René Girard’s theory of sacrifice and the “sacrificial crisis” of modern societies—the disastrous “forgetting of the ‘founding violence’”Footnote 71 the implications of which we are about to confront in our contemporary “tales of transcendence.”Footnote 72 Accordingly, Mensch demonstrates in a most convincing fashion how such a forgetting leads to an eclipse, or, as he formulates with a little help from Kierkegaard, “suspense of the ethical.” As he argues, this is displayed most sharply in our contemporary “societies of the spectacle” and how their ambiguous relationship with violence in general feeds into both our unavowed political theologies of domination as well as their theocratic regimes.

Starting from the same insight into the constitutive overlapping of “the secular” and “the religious” as Mensch, Ó Murchadha sets out to discuss the inherently liminal character of violence in general, and religious violence in particular. As the author explains, the experience of violence borders on the senseless. This general unspeakability and horror is intensified, as he further hypothesizes, in the case of “religious violence.” In order to convey any social sense, violence needs to rely on its justification, notwithstanding the senselessness it also entails. “Religious violence” appears different in this regard inasmuch as it claims for a higher, that is, theodical justification that transcends the meaningful webs of our social worlds. In tearing apart the correlation of means and ends, “religious violence” accordingly forecloses the temporal structures of meaning and “revels in its own spectacle.” This “eschatological longing for the closing of the gap between God and World” consequently results in the annihilation of every worldly order as well as a relativizing of all evil. Thus, epitomizing the tremendum mysterium (Otto), “religious violence” mimics the splendor of the holy which it affectively attempts to set in scene. As Ó Murchadha argues further on, this—often indeed fascinating—strategy still results in a perversion of hope through an “eschatological” forcing of time.Footnote 73 In attempting to negate the contingency of its worldly situation, the “desire to become God” (Sartre) transforms into a “desire to haste the coming eschatological perfection,”Footnote 74 a horizonal move that appears condemned to sink into despair. In sacrificing the intelligibility of its con-temporal destiny and human direction, this gesture necessarily goes awry: it does not open itself for the kind of mystical awe that unfolds nowhere but in the vertical givenness of ordinary everydayness as such. Finally, however, the question remains whether this mystical “antidote” that the author locates in our capacity to live our temporality otherwise, will prove efficient. As he argues, the impregnation of our temporality with a mystical form may help us avoid our destructive impulses to force the end—or “seize the source”Footnote 75—but instead listen to the “mystery in the everyday.”Footnote 76 How the habit of an “anticipatory resoluteness” of the “fanatic mindset” (literally das Vorlaufen in den Tod) can be bent back upon such unifying awe while being exposed to an all-consuming spectacle of violence, is a question that exceeds the framework of this contribution.

In some sense, Rogozinski’s phenomenological analysis of ISIS takes up the question above.Footnote 77 This analysis takes off in the same general context, i.e., with regard to the excessively violent forms that the expressly modern Jihadist “return” to some “true religion” revolves around. In its concrete focus, the paper offers a yet rare attempt at concretely applying the phenomenological framework to a contemporary case of a collectively organized form of “religious violence.” By demonstrating how a transformed brand of phenomenologyFootnote 78 can be used to describe the very schemas that interlink human affectivity and the socio-political functioning of ISIS’ “theology of violence,” the author paves a rich pathway for an eidetic-phenomenological analysis of “religious violence” in general. In particular, Rogozinski analyzes two meaning generative schemas or matrices of social action that make this world of violence tick, i.e., in projectively transforming the subject’s primordial alterity into some exterior threat. The two guiding threads are the symbolically charged figures of the Anti-Messiah and the aforementioned trope of Messianic hope. In a first step, he accordingly demonstrates how a non-foundational phenomenology of embodied co-existence can be applied productively to explore the pre-predicative, inter-affective functioning of these schemas. In a second move, the author offers a convincing account of how this “logic of hatred” turns parasitic upon always escalating projections of enmity and proliferating ideologies of conspiration: in order to sustain an inherently negative vision of communal being, this parasitism appears as constitutive as the crisis of a derailed modernity and liberal imaginary, which has foreclosed the communal horizons of hope and true liberation.

Greisch’s review essay demonstrates how Rogozinski’s earlier book on the Witch-huntFootnote 79 can be understood as another attempt at analyzing the historic expressions of this “logic of hatred.” It shows, in a both clear and disconcerting manner, how Rogozinski indeed gives us to understand that the foundering ideals of community that can be found in various historic eras, lead to a distortion of human trust on its most basic scale: what appears to be left of our most basic, functioning trust in the other in all these contexts is but an always proliferating hate in which the people alone still seem to be able to trust.Footnote 80 This entails, as Greisch argues, a most serious challenge to our contemporary social imaginaries in general, and to our procedural ideal of democracy in particular. Thus, it aptly summarizes the truly disconcerting consequence of Rogozinski’s reflections.

In his reflections on “transcendental pride” and “Luciferism,” Hart develops and in fact transcendentally verifies some basic insights of Rogozinski’s article in a more eidetic fashion. In a nutshell, the author employs classical transcendental phenomenology yet wields resources from scholastic thought as well as theology in order to analyze the fundamental, basic extremes of being-human. Following Sartre’s ideas from his Notebook for an Ethics, Hart finds these “incongruent counterparts” of human nature epitomized in the God-like qualities of mankind taking over the presumedly liberating role of the “anti-creator” (Sartre). The “I am become death, destroyer of worlds” (Oppenheimer) mindset, which he finds at play here, testifies to the yawning, sometimes widening abyss that mirrors the basic “affective fragility of man.”Footnote 81 Here the “myth of Lucifer” (taken as an integral part of the Abrahamic traditions) serves as a guiding thread for an eidetic analysis and existential interpretation of these twofold impulses. Exploring the implications of this myth, Hart discusses the malleability of the human condition and its explosive existential grounding. Accordingly, he distinguishes at the very heart of our desiring condition not only a spiritual striving toward divinization, which bears the potential for creative self-renunciation, but also a “transcendental pride” that leads to idolatrous self-inflation. The paper, thus viewed, is most important because it demonstrates that the potential of a Luciferian conversion of agency as is but the flip side of the moral substance attributed to religious systems of knowledge and practice. This insight, however, calls upon us to thoroughly revisit the relationship between “religion” and “violence,” and especially to rethink the modern myth that has attempted to univocally affirm their relation—a myth that has resulted in the predicament of our post-secular constellation and its infusion with excessive images of violence incarnated.

As Welten convincingly shows, Levinas’ thought is animated exactly by taking issue with the proclaimed neutrality of modernity and its widely-celebrated capacity to contain violence in a totalizing rational order, be it conceived in discursive, procedural, or transcendental terms. The idolatrous pride that Hart has exposed to be rooted in the self-contained relationship of modern selfhood, is targeted directly in Levinas’ attack on the primacy of intentionality and the normativist ethics deduced therefrom. As Welten argues in contradistinction to a whole tradition of interpretation, we must not dissociate Levinas’ philosophical ethics from his Talmudic thinking. Quite the contrary, it is in the Talmudic readings that Welten finds a clue to confront the presumed contradiction between an “ethical violence” that traumatically summons and singularizes the subject and the empiric “violence that needs to be overcome.” As Welten goes on to argue, it is the “difficult freedom” of the religious subject. That is, a subject which is initially constituted by the (self)revelatory violence of the Other within, which can only accept its conditioned freedom “against its own will,” and “after the fact.” Thus viewed, Levinas’ concept of such an Exodic freedom that commits the dispossessed subject to an always overburdening Messianic responsibility for the other, introduces a different kind of phenomenology: instead of further propagating the imperialism of intentionality and its lingering seizure of power (I-can), Levinas proposes to overcome the modern tyranny of individualism by way of restoring the violence as to how it was “in the beginning.” This original violence, as Welten contends, is not be confused with the Hobbesian-like “war of all against all,”Footnote 82 which (like in Clausevitz’ reference to the Chameleon-like character of war) easily comes to parade as a purported peace-making. The original violence that Welten’s Levinas has in (his Lacanian) mind, rather, is a truly primordial one: it is one that confronts the subject not only with his diachronic religious exposition to the Other but at once emphasizes that this exposition is dependent upon an irreducible alterity experienced within. Such alterity, however, irreducibly ties religion to its other, revelation to contamination, God to the history of “He war,”Footnote 83 to quote Derrida’s most cryptic but revelatory syntagma. Thus viewed, Welten’s reading of Levinas attests to the same basic ambiguity that has been exposed by Rogozinski and Hart alike—thus pointing at the necessity to recover an original alteration of the absolute within us that calls on us to avoid any unanimous attempt at “seizing the source” of some divine essence.

In contradistinction to Welten’s reading of the Levinasian account, which deals with the relationship between religion and violence in a seemingly most general way only, Gschwandtner brings the analysis back to more life-worldly issues. The author engages in a convincing reading of Paul Ricœur’s theory of “narrative identity” and demonstrates how it may fruitfully be brought to bear on understanding the role of religion as a shaper of the (all too) human “struggle for concordance in discordance.” Gschwandtner, in a fashion similar to the transcendental investigation proffered by Hart, is most sensitive in exploring the ambiguous potential of religious narratives that is effectuated when being turned “from text to action.” How, she asks, can religious communities be driven either to apply exclusionary forms of violence or foster ways of life that promote liberation, compassion, and peace? In bridging Ricœur’s widely unrelated discussions concerning “embodied existence,” “narrative identity” and the operative impact of “social imaginaries,” Gschwandtner provides a comprehensive outlook on the intersecting dynamics that she finds at work in the shaping of religious selfhood and collective identity. As she argues, such an account is needed in order to trace the concrete interplay somehow entertained by faith communities between both their theoretical potentials for hermeneutically overcoming their own violent potentials (epitomized in the phronetic potentials of the wisdom traditions) and their practical need for materially embodying religious narratives in topologies of the sacred and the profane—topologies that are, by definition, exclusionary and hence potentially violent. As Gschwandtner rightly concludes, this ambiguity has to be endured and hermeneutically cultivated; at any rate, it must not seduce us to (necessarily violently) “seize the source” (or “force the end”) of what transcends a given community of faith. She is thus underwriting the same insights as yielded by Hart and others.

Marion’s paper, finally, addresses a very different, yet no less essential question. It confronts the conflictual topology of our post-secular “social imaginaries” with the resurgent question of transcendence and its malleable role in social relations. Harkening back to the discussion concerning Girard’s challenge that had been taken up by Mensch’s inaugural reflections on the modern trope of the “return of religion,” Marion investigates the potentiality of asymmetric forgiveness. Following Levinas, but firmly located within the contours of his “phenomenology of givenness,” he proposes to understand this most basic “political virtue” (Arendt) as a “gift” to overcome our reciprocal sacrificial modern imaginaries. Its most relevant capacity consists in its power to institute a dispossessive relationship with the other instead. That is, one that is not dependent upon imaginations of procedural coherence, the effectivity of social technologies, or a reciprocal struggle for recognition—but thrives upon a surplus which it indeed poietically institutes.Footnote 84 Here the wager of the gift, to put it in other words, is presented as a self-effacing means to trump the stakes of totality by a “weak force,” (Derrida) which ascends but in its aimless redundancy.

Marion, without a doubt, succeeds in presenting Levinas’ primordial ethics as a necessary, albeit “incongruent counterpart” that is required to come to terms with Girard’s challenge. The question nonetheless remains whether or not the violence that presides in the beginning—as it has been exposed by Welten’s reading—is not also prone to anticipatorily “consecrate war and its virile virtues in good conscience.”Footnote 85 As the other articles have demonstrated, this disconcerting insight but calls on us to further expose this cardinal ambiguity (and describe its symbolic institutions and practical implementation). We indeed need to do so in order to avoid falling into a habit of indifference that self-righteously condones one’s own necessary “counter-violence” by way of projecting—and sometimes even creating—the “original supplement” of some other violence onto our others, and thus underwrites the myth of some original violence. In this general gesture seems to reside the specific capacity of a genuinely phenomenological account of “religious violence” and the surplus it may offer over and against the findings of historians, sociologists of religion, and political theorists–since all of them find themselves all too often locked in a “hunt for causation.”Footnote 86 This posture, however, easily overlooks not just the expressive and indeed poietic potentials of violence. All the more problematic is the fact that it is also prone to (re)create its very object—be it by intention or not. It is in the same vein that the articles here assembled hope to start a discussion that is much needed nowadays, indeed.