Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-c47g7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-23T18:40:05.444Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Is knowledge of causes sufficient for understanding?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Xingming Hu*
Affiliation:
Philosophy Department, Nanjing University, Jiangsu, China

Abstract

According to a traditional account, understanding why X occurred is equivalent to knowing that X was caused by Y. This paper defends the account against a major objection, viz., knowing-that is not sufficient for understanding-why, for understanding-why requires a kind of grasp while knowledge-that does not. I discuss two accounts of grasp in recent literature and argue that if either is true, then knowing that X was caused by Y entails at least a rudimentary understanding of why X occurred. If my defense is successful, it would cast doubt on an influential account of the epistemic value of understanding.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors 2018

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Achinstein, P., 1983. The Nature of Explanation. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ahlstrom-Vij, K., and Grimm, S. R.. 2013. “Getting It Right.” Philosophical Studies, 166 (2): 329347.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boyd, K., 2017. “Testifying Understanding.” Episteme, 14 (1): 103127. doi:10.1017/epi.2015.53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, S., 2002. “Basic Knowledge and the Problem of Easy Knowledge.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 65 (2): 309329. doi:10.1111/phpr.2002.65.issue-2.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elgin, C., 2004. “True Enough.” Philosophical Issues, 14 (1): 113131. doi:10.1111/phis.2004.14.issue-1.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elgin, C., 2009. “Is Understanding Factive?” In Epistemic Value, edited by Haddock, A., Millar, A., and Pritchard, D.. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Grimm, S., 2010. “Understanding.” In The Routledge Companion to Epistemology, edited by Berneker, S. and Pritchard, D.. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Grimm, S., 2014. “Understanding as Knowledge of Causes.” In Virtue Epistemology Naturalized, edited by Fairweather, A., 329345. Cham: Springer International Publishing.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grimm, S. R., 2006. “Is Understanding a Species of Knowledge?The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 57 (3): 515535. doi:10.1093/bjps/axl015.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hills, A., 2009. “Moral Testimony and Moral Epistemology’.” Ethics, 120 (1): 94127. doi:10.1086/648610.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hills, A., 2015. “Understanding Why.” Noûs, 49 (2): 128.Google Scholar
Hopkins, R., 2007. “What Is Wrong with Moral Testimony?Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 74 (3): 611634. doi:10.1111/phpr.2007.74.issue-3.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kelp, C., 2014. “Knowledge, Understanding and Virtue.” In Virtue Epistemology Naturalized, edited by Fairweather, A., 347360. Cham: Springer International Publishing.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, J., 1974. “Causes and Counterfactuals.” The Journal of Philosophy, 70 (17): 570572. doi:10.2307/2025312.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, P., 1985. “Salmon on Explanation and Causality: Two Approaches to Explanation.” The Journal of Philosophy, 82: 632639. doi:10.2307/2026419.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kvanvig, J., 2003. The Value of Knowledge and the Pursuit of Understanding. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D., 2000. “Causation as Influence.” The Journal of Philosophy, 97 (4): 182197. doi:10.2307/2678389.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lipton, P., 2004. Inference to the Best Explanation. 2nd ed. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Lipton, P., 2009. “Understanding without Explanation.” In Scientific Understanding: Philosophical Perspectives, edited by De Regt, H. W., Leonelli, S., and Eigner, K., 4363. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mackie, J. L., 1965. “Causes and Conditions.” American Philosophical Quarterly, 2 (4): 245264.Google Scholar
Merricks, T., 2001. Objects and Persons. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Paul, L. A., 2009. “Counterfactual Theories.” In The Oxford Handbook of Causation, edited by Beebee, H., Menzies, P., and Hitchcock, C.. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pritchard, D., 2010. “Knowledge and Understanding.” In The Nature and Value of Knowledge: Three Investigations, edited by Pritchard, D., Millar, A., and Haddock, A.. Oxford: OUP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pritchard, D., 2014. “Knowledge and Understanding.” In Virtue Epistemology Naturalized, edited by Fairweather, A. 315327. Cham: Springer International Publishing.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salmon, W., 1984. Scientific Explanation and the Causal Structure of the World. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Sliwa, P., 2015. “Understanding and Knowing.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 115 (1): 5774. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9264.2015.00384.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sosa, E., 2009. Reflective Knowledge: Apt Belief and Reflective Knowledge. Vol. II. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strevens, M., 2013. “No Understanding without Explanation.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 44 (3): 510515.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sullivan, E., 2018. “Understanding: Not Know-How.” Philosophical Studies, 175 (1): 221240. doi:10.1007/s11098-017-0863-z.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woodward, J., 2003. Making Things Happen: A Theory of Causal Explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Zagzebski, L., 2001. “Recovering Understanding.” In Knowledge, Truth, and Duty: Essays on Epistemic Justification, Responsibility, and Virtue, edited by Steup, M.. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar