Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-dnltx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-20T00:44:49.438Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Kantian Self-Conceit and the Two Guises of Authority

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  24 October 2019

Francey Russell*
Affiliation:
Barnard College and Columbia University, New York, NY, USA

Abstract

There is a debate in the literature as to whether Kantian self-conceit is intrapsychic or interpersonal. I argue that self-conceit is both. I argue that, for Kant, self-conceit is fundamentally an illusion about authority, one’s own and any authority one stands in relation to. Self-conceit refuses to recognize the authority of the law. But the law “shows up” for us in two guises: one’s own reason and other persons. Thus, self-conceit refuses to recognize both guises of the law. Hence self-conceit is essentially double-sided, at once intrapsychic and interpersonal.

Type
Article
Copyright
© The Author(s) 2019. Published by Canadian Journal of Philosophy

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Allison, Henry E. 1995. Kant’s Theory of Freedom. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Baxley, Anne Margaret. 2007. “Kantian Virtue.” Philosophy Compass 2 (3): 396410.Google Scholar
Darwall, Stephen. 1977. “Two Kinds of Respect.” Ethics 88 (1): 3649.Google Scholar
Darwall, Stephen. 2006. The Second-Person Standpoint: Morality, Respect and Accountability. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Darwall, Stephen. 2008. “Kant on Respect, Dignity, and the Duty of Respect.” In Kant’s Ethics of Virtue, edited by Betzler, Monika. Berlin: De Gruyter.Google Scholar
Engstrom, Stephen. 2009. The Form of Practical Knowledge. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Engstrom, Stephen. 2010. “The Triebfeder of Pure Practical Reason.” In Kant’s Critique of Practical Reason: A Critical Guide, edited by Reath, Andrews and Timmerman, Jens. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Grenberg, Jeanine. 2005. Kant and the Ethics of Humility. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Grenberg, Jeanine. 2013. Kant’s Defense of Common Moral Experience. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Herman, Barbara. 2005. “Transforming Incentives: Feelings and the Making of the Kantian Moral Agent.” In Philosophical Aspects of the Emotions, edited by Carlson, Åsa. Stockholm: Thales.Google Scholar
Herman, Barbara. 2007. Moral Literacy. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. (1781/1787) 1999. Critique of Pure Reason. Translated and edited by Guyer, Paul and Wood, Allen. UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. (1784) 1997. “Moral Philosophy: Collins’s Lecture Notes.” In Lectures on Ethics. Edited by Heath, Peter and Schneewind, J. B., translated by P. Heath. UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. (1784) 1999. “An Answer to the Question: What Is Enlightenment?” In Practical Philosophy, translated and edited by Gregor, Mary. UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. (1784) 2007. “Idea for a Universal History with a Cosmopolitan Aim,” In Anthropology, History, and Education. Edited by Loudon, Robert and Zöller, Günter. Translated by Allen Wood. UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. (1785) 1999. “Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals,” In Practical Philosophy, translated and edited by Gregor, Mary. UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. (1788) 1999. “The Critique of Practical Reason.” In Practical Philosophy. Translated and edited by Gregor, Mary. UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. (1788) 2001. Critique of the Power of Judgment. Translated and edited by Guyer, Paul and Matthews, Eric. UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. (1788) 2002. Critique of Practical Reason. Translated by Pluhar, Werner S.. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. (1793) 1998. Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason. Translated and edited by Wood, Allen and di Giovanni, George. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. (1797) 1999. “The Metaphysics of Morals.” In Practical Philosophy, translated and edited by Gregor, Mary. UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. (1798) 2007. “Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View.” In Anthropology, History, and Education, translated and edited by Louden, Robert B.. UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. 2001. “Moral Philosophy: Collins Lecture Notes.” In Lectures on Ethics, translated and edited by Heath, Peter. UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Merritt, Melissa. 2017. “Practical Reason and Respect for Persons.” Kantian Review 22 (1): 5379.Google Scholar
Moran, Kate. 2014. “Delusions of Virtue: Kant on Self-Conceit.” Kantian Review 19 (3): 419–47.Google Scholar
O’Neill, Onora. (1986). “Reason and Politics in the Kantian Enterprise.” In Constructions of Reason: Explorations of Kant’s Practical Philosophy. UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Reath, Andrews, ed. 2006. “Kant’s Theory of Moral Sensibility: Respect for the Moral Law and the Influence of Inclination.” In Agency and Autonomy in Kant’s Moral Theory: Selected Essays. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ware, Owen. 2014a. “Kant on Moral Sensibility and Moral Motivation.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 52 (4): 727–46.Google Scholar
Ware, Owen. 2014b. “Rethinking Kant’s Fact of Reason.” Philosopher’s Imprint 14 (32).Google Scholar
Ware, Owen. 2015. “Accessing the Moral Law through Feeling.” Kantian Review, 20 (2): 301–11.Google Scholar
Wood, Allen. 1999. Kant’s Ethical Thought. UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Wood, Allen. 2008. Kantian Ethics. UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar