Skip to main content
Log in

Brouwer’s Notion of ‘Egoicity’

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Axiomathes Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

According to Brouwer’s ‘theory of the exodus of consciousness’, our experience includes ‘egoicity’, a distinct kind of feeling. In this paper, we (i) describe his phenomenology in order to (ii) explore and elaborate on the notion of egoic sensations. In the world of perception formed from sensations, some of them are, Brouwer claims, not completely separated or ‘estranged’ from the subject, which is to say they have a certain degree of egoicity. We claim this phenomenon can be explained in terms of the primordial state of consciousness from where the ‘exodus’ starts. Having undertaken the analysis and interpretation of Brouwer’s descriptions and examples of egoic sensations, we (iii) provide a formal account of egoicity based on Brouwer’s definition of its relation to estrangement, desire and fear. We show that the four terms can be modeled by a classical and a graded logical hexagon, giving the corresponding axiomatizations.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. An account which can be traced to an essay he wrote at the age of 17 (Brouwer 1990a).

  2. The exodus of consciousness can be compared to Kant’s (1998) role of the productive imagination (B152), if we understand Brouwer’s ‘categories’ to be the new ways of arranging sensations acquired in every phase: object, causality, things, cooperation. Productive imagination pertains to the synthetic unity of apperception, where manifold is given in a single intuition. It also includes spontaneity, where the synthesis happens “in accordance with the categories” (B152) and is in that case “an effect of the understanding on sensibility and its first application [...] to objects of the intuition that is possible for us” (B152).

    Moreover, concerning the important separation between the subject and the object marking the exodus, Brouwer’s account is similar to Kant’s in as much as the latter regards the synthetic unity of apperception as the condition that the united representations can be said to belong to one and the same subject—“only because I can comprehend their manifold in a consciousness do I call them all together my representations” (B134). The concept of an object is also generated by the synthetic unity, since this unity is “something under which every intuition must stand in order to become an object for me” (B138). We thank an anonymous reviewer for pointing to Kant’s productive imagination.

  3. To our knowledge, Brouwer does not distinguish between ‘intellect’ and ‘mind’. The latter we find in (the translations of) his later works.

  4. van Dalen (1998) offers an interpretation of egoicity in a mathematical context, applying the notion to intuitionistic choice sequences. We do not find, however, any textual support for the assumption that Brouwer used the term ‘egoic’ in describing mathematical constructions.

  5. The reader should take into account that the section about immanent truth from Life, Art, and Mysticism contains some highly questionable remarks about women. Brouwer seems to have believed that experiencing immanent and transcendent truth, as well as turning-into-oneself, is an exclusively male privilege and possibility, where woman is a “Siren luring him away from his path” (1905/1996, p. 407). He provides a number of (supposed) examples from art and literature. We strongly disagree with Brouwer on this.

  6. In this paper, we use the term ‘model’ for the structures of opposition in a wider sense, to mean a (diagrammatic) representation of semantic relations. It includes and presupposes an interpretation (and a relational structure) one finds in a ‘model’ meant in the technical, narrow, sense.

  7. See Dufatanye (2012, pp. 54–56) for its English translation and analysis.

  8. The axiom is the same, expressing the implication between the A and the I corner (as we will show shortly in Fig. 2). Since we use a language of propositional logic augmented with four operators (which allows for internal negation), we need only three definitions, while Kalinowski uses four. In such language, two of Kalinowski’s definitions become derivable in our sytem, but we need to add Df1\(^c\), the counterpart of which is not present (or expressible) in Kalinowski’s account.

  9. Possibility theory was introduced by Zadeh (1978). It utilizes his fuzzy logic (Zadeh 1975) based on his fuzzy sets (Zadeh 1965), a logic which uses Łukasiewicz’ continuum-valued interpretation of logical connectives. So, the graded logical hexagon could also be called ‘fuzzy’.

References

  • Barendregt H (2008) Buddhist models of the mind and the common core thesis on mysticism. In: van Atten M et al (eds) One hundred years of intuitionism (1907–2007): the Cerisy conference. Birkhäuser, Basel

    Google Scholar 

  • Blanché R (1953) Sur l’opposition des concepts. Theoria 19:89–130

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blanché R (1966) Structures intellectuelles: essai sur l’organisation systématique des concepts. Vrin, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer LEJ (1975a) Consciousness, philosophy, and mathematics. In: (Heyting 1975), pp 480–494 (originally published in 1949)

  • Brouwer LEJ (1975b) Points and spaces. In: (Heyting 1975), pp 522–538 (originally published in 1954)

  • Brouwer LEJ (1990a) Profession of faith by L.E.J. Brouwer. In: van Stigt WP (ed) Brouwer’s intuitionism. North-Holland Publishing Company, Amsterdam (originally written in Dutch in 1898)

    Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer LEJ (1990b) The rejected parts of Brouwer’s dissertation. In: van Stigt WP (ed) Brouwer’s intuitionism. North-Holland Publishing Company, Amsterdam, pp 405–415

    Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer LEJ (1990c) Will, knowledge and speech. In: van Stigt WP (ed) Brouwer’s intuitionism. North-Holland Publishing Company, Amsterdam (originally published in Dutch in 1933)

    Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer LEJ (1996) Life, art, and mysticism. Notre Dame J Form L 37(3):389–429 (originally published in Dutch in 1905)

    Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer LEJ (1998) Mathematics, science, and language. In: Mancosu P (ed) From Brouwer to Hilbert: the debate on the foundations of mathematics in the 1920s. Oxford University Press, New York (originally published in German in 1929)

    Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer LEJ (2017) The unreliability of the logical principles. In: Atten M van, Sundholm G: L.E.J. Brouwer’s 'Unreliability of the logical principles': a new translation, with an introduction. Hist Philos Logic 38(1):24–47 (originally published in Dutch in 1908)

  • Dubois D, Prade H (2012) From Blanché’s hexagonal organization of concepts to formal concept analysis and possibility theory. Log Univ 6(1–2):149–169

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dubois D, Prade H (2015) Gradual structures of oppositions. In: Magdalena L et al (eds) Enric Trillas: a passion for fuzzy sets. Springer, Cham

    Google Scholar 

  • Dufatanye A-A (2012) From the logical square to Blanché’s hexagon: formalization, applicability and the idea of normative structure of thought. Log Univ 6(1–2):45–67

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franchella M (2015) Brouwer and Nietzsche: views about life, views about logic. Hist Philos Logic 36(4):367–391

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heyting A (ed) (1975) L.E.J. Brouwer collected works, vol 1. North-Holland Publishing Company, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacoby P (1950) A triangle of opposites for types of propositions in Aristotelian logic. New Scholast 24(1):32–56

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kalinowski G (1967) Axiomatisation et formalisation de la théorie hexagonale de l’opposition de M. R. Blanché (système B). Les études Philos 22(2):203–209

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (1998) Critique of pure reason (translated and edited by P Guyer and A W Wood). Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Łukasiewicz J (1970) Investigations into the sentential calculus. In: Borkowski L (ed) Jan Łukasiewicz selected works. North-Holland Publishing Company, Amsterdam (originally published in German in 1930)

    Google Scholar 

  • Placek T (1999) Mathematical intuitionism and intersubjectivity. Springer, Dordrecht

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sesmat A (1951) Logique II: les raisonnements, la logistique. Hermann, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • van Atten M (2002) The irreflexivity of Brouwer’s philosophy. Axiomathes 13:65–77

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Atten M, Tragesser R (2015) Mysticism and mathematics: Brouwer, Gödel, and the common core thesis. In: van Atten M (ed) Essays on Gödel’s reception of Leibniz, Husserl, and Brouwer. Springer, Cham

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • van Dalen D (1998) From a Brouwerian point of view. Philos Math 6(2):209–226

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Stigt WP (1996) Introduction to Life, art, and mysticism. Notre Dame J Form L 37(3):381–387

    Google Scholar 

  • Zadeh LA (1965) Fuzzy sets. Inform. Control 8(3):338–353

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zadeh LA (1975) Fuzzy logic and approximate reasoning. Synthese 30(3–4):407–428

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zadeh LA (1978) Fuzzy sets as a basis for a theory of possibility. Fuzzy Set Syst 100:3–28

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We thank an anonymous reviewer and professor Srećko Kovač for their helpful comments and suggestions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ivan Restović.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Restović, I. Brouwer’s Notion of ‘Egoicity’. Axiomathes 32, 83–100 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-020-09509-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-020-09509-4

Keywords

Navigation