Skip to main content
Log in

How we Think About Human Nature: Cognitive Errors and Concrete Remedies

  • Published:
Foundations of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Us and them is perhaps the simplest explanation of human nature. —Wayne Bennett (2014).

Abstract

Appeals to human nature are ubiquitous, yet historically many have proven ill-founded. Why? How might frequent errors be remedied towards building a more robust and reliable scientific study of human nature? Our aim is neither to advance specific scientific or philosophical claims about human nature, nor to proscribe or eliminate such claims. Rather, we articulate through examples the types of errors that frequently arise in this field, towards improving the rigor of the scientific and social studies. We seek to analyze such claims rhetorically, cognitively, and epistemically. Namely, how do we think about human nature? Claims about human nature, we show, are susceptible to widely exhibited deficits in cognitive tendencies such as framing, confirmation bias, satisficing, and teleological perspectives, as well as motivated reasoning. Such missteps foster methodological, empirical, and psychological mistakes and biases. Specifically, they promote the naturalizing error, whereby cultural ideology and values are projected onto an apparently objective description of nature. Concrete remedies are offered to aid scientists in conducting and reporting their research goals and findings more responsibly and effectively (relevant also to educators and other communicators who convey these findings publicly). Recommendations include acknowledging that human nature claims are often context-dependent, seeking multiple critical perspectives, and explicitly labeling uncertainties.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Allchin, D. (2001). Error types. Perspectives on Science, 9, 38–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allchin, D. (2008). Naturalizing as an error-type in biology. Filosofia e História da Biologia, 3, 95–117.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allchin, D. (2015). Correcting the “self-correcting” mythos of science. Filosofia e História da Biologia, 10, 19–35.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allchin, D. (2017). Sacred bovines: The ironies of misplaced assumptions in biology. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Allchin, D. (2018). The politics of biodiversity-speak. American Biology Teacher, 80, 397–400.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allchin, D., & Werth, A. J. (2017). The naturalizing error. Journal for the General Philosophy of Science, 48(1), 3–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allchin, D., & Werth, A. J. (2020). How we think about human nature: The naturalizing error. Philosophy of Science, 87(3), 499–517.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allen, G. (2011). Eugenics and modern biology: Critiques of eugenics, 1910–1945. Annals of Human Genetics, 75(3), 314–325.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Amundson, R. (2000). Against normal function. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Biology and Biomedical Sciences, 31, 33–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ardrey, R. (1966). The territorial imperative: A personal inquiry into the animal origins of property and nations. New York: Athenaeum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ariely, D. (2008). Predictably irrational: The hidden forces that shape our decisions. New York: Harper Collins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ariely, D., & Kreisler, J. (2017). Dollars and sense: How we misthink money and how to spend smarter. New York: Harper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Austriaco, N. P. G. (2015). Human nature as normative concept: Relevance for health care. In T. Schramme & S. Edwards (Eds.), Handbook of the Philosophy of Medicine (pp. 273–285). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bailey, J. M. (2019). How to ruin sex research. Archives of sexual behavior, 48(4), 1007–1011.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bain, P. G., Kashima, Y., & Haslam, N. (2006). Conceptual beliefs about human values and their implications: Human nature beliefs predict value importance, value trade-offs, and responses to value-laden rhetoric. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 91(2), 351–367.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bain, P., Park, J., Kwok, C., & Haslam, N. (2009). Attributing human uniqueness and human nature to cultural groups: Distinct forms of subtle dehumanization. Group Processes and Intergroup Relations, 12(6), 789–805.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, H. C. (2015). The shape of thought: How mental adaptations evolve. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, W. (2014). What babies and college football tell us about human nature. TeamWorx Team Building Programs website. Retrieved February 25 2014 from http://teamworxteambuilding.com/what-babies-and-college-football-tell-us-about-human-nature/.

  • Boulter, S. J. (2012). Can evolutionary biology do without Aristotelian essentialism? Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 70, 83–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, D. E. (1991). Human universals. New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, D. E. (2004). Human universals, human nature & human culture. Daedalus, 133(4), 47–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buller, D. J. (2005). Adapting minds: Evolutionary psychology and the persistent quest for human nature. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buss, D. M., & von Hippel, W. (2018). Psychological barriers to evolutionary psychology: Ideological bias and coalitional adaptations. Archives of Scientific Psychology, 6(1), 148–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carlson, A. C. (2015). The natural family where it belongs: New agrarian essays. Piscataway, NJ: Transaction Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cherry, M. J. (Ed.). (2015). The normativity of the natural: Human goods, human virtues, and human flourishing. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Curry, O. (2006). Who’s afraid of the naturalistic fallacy? Evolutionary Psychology, 4, 234–247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Curtis, G. N. (2018). Appeal to nature. The Fallacy Files website. Retrieved June 10 2018 from http://www.fallacyfiles.org/adnature.html.

  • de Waal, F. (1996). Good natured: The origins of right and wrong in humans and other animals. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • de Waal, F. (2000). Survival of the rapist: Two scientists argue that plain old evolution explains why men rape. New York Times April 2, 2000, http://www.nytimes.com/books/00/04/02/reviews/000402.002waalt.html

  • de Waal, F. (2001). The ape and the sushi master: Reflections of a primatologist. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (2008). Resurrecting biological essentialism. Philosophy of Science, 75, 344–382.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dobelli, R. (2013). The art of thinking clearly. London: Sceptre.

    Google Scholar 

  • Downes, S. M., & Machery, E. (2013). Arguing about human nature: Contemporary debates. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J. (2003). On human nature. Human Affairs, 13, 109–122.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J. (2018). Human nature: A process perspective. In B. Hannon & T. Lewens (Eds.), Why we disagree about human nature (pp. 92–107). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eiser, J. R., & van der Pligt, J. (1988). Attitudes and decisions. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newsweek (1992). Is this child gay? Born or bred: The origins of homosexuality. 24 February 1992. Retrieved April 17, 2014 from http://newsweek.com/homosexuality-born-or-bred-20036.

  • Foot, P. (2001). Natural goodness. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ford, Z. (2016). Pittsburgh-area school to transgender students: It’s ‘irrefutable’ that you’re unnatural. Think Progress Retrieved December 19 2017 from https://thinkprogress.org/pine-richland-transgender-students-dcf967f62f4f/.

  • Freeman, D. (1983). Margaret mead and samoa: The making and unmaking of an anthropological myth. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuentes, A. (2017). The “Google Manifesto”: Bad biology, ignorance of evolutionary processes, and privilege. PLOS SciComm. https://blogs.plos.org/scicomm/2017/08/14/the-google-manifesto-bad-biology-ignorance-of-evolutionary-processes-and-privilege.

  • Fyfe, S., Williams, C., Mason, O. J., & Pickup, G. J. (2008). Apophenia, theory of mind and schizotypy: Perceiving meaning and intentionality in randomness. Cortex, 44(10), 1316–1325.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gaspar, P. (2004). Is biology destiny? International Socialist Review, 38, https://isreview.org/issues/38/genes.shtml.

  • Gazzaniga, M. (2008). Human: The science behind what makes your brain unique. New York: Harper Collins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gelman, S. A., & Rhodes, M. (2012). Two-thousand years of stasis: How psychological essentialism impedes evolutionary understanding. In K. S. Rosengren, S. Brem, E. M. Evans, & G. Sinatra (Eds.), Evolution challenges: Integrating research and practice in teaching and learning about evolution (pp. 3–21). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gergely, G., & Csibra, G. (2003). Teleological reasoning in infancy: The naïve theory of rational action. Trends in cognitive sciences, 7(7), 287–292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilovich, T. (1993). How we know what isn’t so: The fallibility of human reason in everyday life. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilovich, T., Griffin, D., & Kahneman, D. (2002). Heuristics and biases: the psychology of intuitive judgment. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gonzalez Galli, L. M., & Meinardi, E. N. (2010). The role of teleological thinking in learning the Darwinian model of evolution. Evolution: Education and Outreach, 4(1), 145–152.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J. (1996). The mismeasure of man (2nd ed.). New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, W. A., & Heine, S. J. (2012). Implicit essentialism: Genetic concepts are implicitly associated with fate concepts. PLoS One, 7(6), e38176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P. E. (2002). What is innateness? Monist, 85, 70–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P. E., Machery, E., & Linquist, S. (2009). The vernacular concept of innateness. Mind and Language, 24, 605–630.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guggenmos, C. J. (2012). Teleological reasoning in adults: Believing in the purpose of events. Master’s thesis, Western Kentucky University, Bowling Green, KY.

  • Guilhem, M. (2013). New princesses rescue girls from a distressed damselhood. National Public Radio 15 December 2013. Available at http://www.npr.org/2013/12/15/251157298/once-upon-a-time-the-princess-saved-the-environment.

  • Hannon, E., & Lewens, T. (Eds.). (2018). Why we disagree about huma nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haraway, D. (1989). Primate visions. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harding, S. (1991). Whose science? Whose knowledge? Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haslam, N., Bain, P., Douge, L., Lee, M., & Bastian, B. (2005). More human than you: Attributing humanness to self and others. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 89(6), 937–950.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haslam, N., & Loughnan, S. (2014). Dehumanization and infrahumanization. Annual Review of Psychology, 65, 399–423.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haslam, N., Loughnan, S., Kashima, Y., & Bain, P. (2008). Attributing and denying humanness to others. European Review of Social Psychology, 19(1), 55–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heick, T. (2019). The cognitive bias codex: a visual of 180+ cognitive biases. Teachthought.com website. Retrieved August 24 2020 from https://www.teachthought.com/critical-thinking/the-cognitive-bias-codex-a-visual-of-180-cognitive-biases/.

  • Heine, S. J., Dar-Nimrod, I., Cheung, B. Y., & Proulx, T. (2017). Essentially biased: Why people are fatalistic about genes. Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 55, pp. 137–192). New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heinrich, N., & Heinrich, J. (2007). Why humans cooperate. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobbes, T. (1651). Leviathan or the matter, forme and power of a common wealth ecclesiasticall and civil (facsimile edition). Cambridge, MA: Hackett.

  • Hull, D. L. (1978). A matter of individuality. Philosophy of Science, 45, 335–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. L. (1986). On human nature. In PSA Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, Vol. 2. (pp. 3-13). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Huxley, T. H. (1894). Evolution and ethics (facsimile). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, S., & Rees, A. (2007). The appalling appeal of nature: The popular influence of evolutionary psychology as a problem for sociology. Sociology, 41(5), 917–930.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahan, D. (2013). Ideology, motivated reasoning, and cognitive reflection: An experimental study. Judgment and Decision Making, 8, 407–424.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, fast and slow. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., Slovic, P., & Tversky, A. (1982). Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Katz, L. D. (Ed.). (2002). Evolutionary origins of morality: Cross-disciplinary perspectives. Thorverton, UK: Imprint Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keim, B. (2013). Human nature might not be so warlike after all. Wired https://www.wired.com/2013/07/to-war-is-human-perhaps-not/.

  • Kelemen, D. (1999). Functions, goals and intentions: Children’s teleological reasoning about objects. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 12, 461–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelemen, D., & Rosset, E. (2009). The human function compunction: Teleological explanation in adults. Cognition, 11, 138–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelemen, D., Rottman, J., & Seston, R. (2013). Professional physical scientists display tenacious teleological tendencies: Purpose-based reasoning as a cognitive default. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 142(4), 1074–1083.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kronfeldner, M. (2018). What’s left of human nature? A post-essentialist, pluralist, and interactive account of a contested concept. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kronfeldner, M. (2018). Divide and conquer: The authority of nature and why we disagree about human nature. In B. Hannon & T. Lewens (Eds.), Why we disagree about human nature (pp. 186–206). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kronfeldner, M., Roughley, N., & Toepfer, G. (2014). Recent work on human nature: Beyond traditional essences. Philosophy Compass, 9, 642–652.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krueger, J. L., & Funder, D. C. (2004). Towards a balanced social psychology: Causes, consequences, and cures for the problem-seeking approach to social behavior and cognition. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 27, 313–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krupenye, C., Kano, F., Hirata, S., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2016). Great apes anticipate that other individuals will act according to false beliefs. Science, 354(6308), 110–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kunda, Z. (1990). The case for motivated reasoning. Psychological Bulletin, 108, 480–498.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levinowitz, A. (2020). Natural: How faith in nature’s goodness leads to harmful fads, unjust laws and flawed science. Boston: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levins, R. (1966). The strategy of model building in population biology. American Scientist, 54, 421-31. Reprinted in Sober, E. (Ed.), Conceptual issues in evolutionary biology (pp. 18-27). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Lewens, T. (2012). Human nature: The very idea. Philosophy & Technology, 25(4), 459–474.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewens, T. (2015). The biological foundations of bioethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lewens, T. (2018). Introduction: The faces of human nature. In B. Hannon & T. Lewens (Eds.), Why we disagree about human nature (pp. 1–17). Oxford: Oxford University Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin, R. C. (1993). Biology as ideology: The doctrine of DNA. New York: Harper Collins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lieberman, D. (2013). The story of the human body: Evolution, health, and disease. New York: Pantheon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Linquist, S., Machery, E., Griffiths, P. E., & Stotz, K. (2011). Exploring the folkbiological conception of human nature. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 366, 444–453.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. (1990). Science as social knowledge. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. (2001). The fate of knowledge. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyle, H. F., & Smith, E. A. (2012). How conservative are evolutionary anthropologists? Human Nature, 23(3), 306–322.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E. (2008). A plea for human nature. Philosophical Psychology, 21(3), 321–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E. (2018). Doubling down on the nomological notion of human nature. In B. Hannon & T. Lewens (Eds.), Why we disagree about human nature (pp. 18–39). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGrew, W. C. (2015). The Cultured Chimpanzee: Nonsense or Breakthrough? Human Ethology Bulletin, 30(1), 41–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mead, M. (1928). Coming of age in Samoa: A psychological study of primitive youth for western civilization. New York: Morrow.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mercier, H., & Sperber, D. (2017). The enigma of reason. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, T. H. (1925). Evolution and genetics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nickerson, R. S. (1998). Confirmation bias: A ubiquitous phenomenon in many guises. Review of General Psychology, 2, 175–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nisbett, R., & Ross, L. (1980). Human inference: Strategies and shortcomings of human judgement. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oreskes, N. (2019). Why trust science? Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Piatelli-Palmarini, M. (1994). Inevitable illusions: How mistakes of reason rule our minds. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, S. (2002). The blank slate: The modern denial of human nature. New York: Viking.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, S. (2011). The better angels of our nature: Why violence has declined. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Potts, R., & Sloan, C. (2010). What does it mean to be human? Washington, DC: National Geographic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Potts, R., & Sloan, C. (2010b). Hall of human origins (curators). Smithsonian Museum of Natural History, Washington, DC, http://humanorigins.si.edu.

  • Ramsey, G. (2013). Human nature in a post-essentialist world. Philosophy of Science, 80(5), 983–993.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reiss, J. (2011). Not by design: Retiring Darwin’s watchmaker. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rettner, R. (2013). Government shutdown science: why human nature is to blame. Yahoo News 2 October 2013, Retrieved April 17 2014 from http://news.yahoo.com/govt-shutdown-science-why-human-nature-blame-134218785.html.

  • Richardson, R. C. (2007). Evolutionary psychology as maladapted psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Richerson, P. J. (2018). The use and non-use of the human nature concept by evolutionary biologists. In B. Hannon & T. Lewens (Eds.), Why we disagree about human nature (pp. 145–169). Oxford: Oxford University Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ridley, M. (1996). The origins of virtue: Human instincts and the evolution of cooperation. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ridley, M. (2010). The rational optimist: How prosperity evolves. New York: Harper.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, W. J. (1910). The appeal to nature in morals and politics. International Journal of Ethics, 20, 295–313.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rottman, J., Zhu, L., Wang, W., Schillaci, R. S., Clark, K. J., & Kelemen, D. (2017). Cultural influences on the teleological stance: Evidence from China. Religion, Brain and Behavior, 7, 17–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roughley, N. (2000). Being humans: Anthropological universality and particularity in transdisciplinary perspectives. Berlin: de Gruyter.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Saad, G. (2011). The consuming instinct: What juicy burgers, Ferraris, pornography, and gift giving reveal about human nature. Amherst, NY: Prometheus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sacks, O. (2008). Musicophilia: Tales of music and the brain. New York: Vintage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sadedin, S. (2017). Science says the biological claims in the Google Anti-Diversity Manifesto are dead wrong. Quora, https://www.inc.com/quora/science-says-the-biological-claims-in-the-google-a.html.

  • Sahlins, M. D. (2008). The western illusion of human nature. Chicago: Prickly Paradigm Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Samuels, R. (2012). Science and human nature. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 70, 1–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sapolsky, R. (2017). Behave: The biology of humans at our best and worst. London: Vintage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schiebinger, L. (1993). Why mammals are called mammals: Gender politics in eighteenth-century natural history. The American Historical Review, 98(2), 382–411.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmitt, D. P., & Pilcher, J. J. (2004). Evaluating evidence of psychological adaptation: How do we know one when we see one? Psychological Science, 15, 643–649.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shankman, P. (2009). The trashing of Margaret Mead: Anatomy of an anthropological controversy. Madison, WI: University of Wisconsin Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shankman, P. (2013). The “fateful hoaxing” of Margaret mead: A cautionary tale. Current Anthropology, 54(1), 51–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shermer, M. (2012). Shock and awe: Replicating Milgram’s shock experiments reveals not blind obedience but deep moral conflict. Scientific American, 307(5), 86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shubin, N. (2008). Your inner fish: a journey into the 3.5-billion-year history of the human body. New York: Knopf Doubleday.

  • Simon, H. (1956). Rational choice and the structure of the environment. Psychological Review, 63, 129–139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Solinas, M. (2015). From aristotle’s teleology to darwin’s genealogy: The stamp of inutility. London: Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, M. (2001). Social empiricism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stanford, P. K. (2006). Exceeding our grasp: Science, history, and the problem of unconceived alternatives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stotz, K., & Griffiths, P. (2018). A developmental systems account of human nature. In B. Hannon & T. Lewens (Eds.), Why we disagree about human nature (pp. 58–75). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunderland, S. (1992). Irrationality: Why we don’t think straight. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sutherland, S. (2013). Irrationality: The enemy within. London: Pinter and Martin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tattersall, I. (1998). Becoming human: Evolution and human uniqueness. San Diego: Harcourt Brace.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tattersall, I., & DeSalle, R. (2007). What makes us human? (curators) Hall of Human Origins. Am Mus Nat Hist, New York, www.amnh.org/exhibitions/permanent/humanorigins/human/.

  • Taylor, H. (2013). Connecting interdisciplinary dots: Songbirds, ‘white rats’ and human exceptionalism. Social Science Information, 52(2), 287–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • TFP Student Action (2014). Ten reasons why homosexual “marriage” is harmful and must be opposed. Retrieved April 17 2014 from www.tfpstudentaction.org/politically-incorrect/homosexuality/10-reasons-why-homosexual-marriage-is-harmful-and-must-be-opposed.html.

  • Thornhill, R., & Palmer, C. T. (2000). A natural history of rape: Biological bases of sexual coercion. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tybur, J. M., Miller, G. F., & Gangestad, S. G. (2007). Testing the controversy: An empirical examination of adaptationists’ political attitudes. Human Nature, 18, 313–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varella, M. A. C. (2016). Using randomness and history Darwin breaks Aristotle’s conceptual pillars about natural world. Human Ethology Bulletin, 31(2), 56–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varella, M. A. C. (2018). The biology and evolution of three psychological tendencies to anthropomorphize biology and evolution. Frontiers in Psychology, 9, 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varella, M. A. C., Santos, I. B. C., Ferreira, J. H. B. P., & Bussab, V. S. R. (2013). Misunderstandings in applying evolution to human mind and behavior and its causes: A systematic review. EvoS Journal: The Journal of the Evolutionary Studies Consortium, 5(1), 81–107.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walker, A. T. (2017). Transgenderism and the abolition of man. National Review online, http://www.nationalreview.com/article/445335/transgenderism-battles-human-nature-biology-will-lose.

  • Walter, C. (2006). Thumbs, toes, and tears: And other things that make us human. New York: Walker.

    Google Scholar 

  • Werth, A. J. (2012). Avoiding the pitfall of progress and associated perils of evolutionary education. Evolution: Education and Outreach, 5(2), 249–265.

    Google Scholar 

  • Werth, A. J., & Allchin, D. (2020). Teleology’s long shadow. Evolution: Education and Outreach, 13(4), 1–11.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W. C. (2007). Re-engineering philosophy for limited beings. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wrangham, R. (2019). The goodness paradox: The strange relation between virtue and violence in human history. New York: Pantheon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ziman, J. (1968). Public knowledge: An essay concerning the social dimension of science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zimring, J. C. (2019). What science is and how it really works. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zuk, M. (2013). Paleofantasy: Why evolution really tells us about sex, diet and how we live. New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Funding

The authors state that they have no funding sources to report.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

Both AJW and DA wrote, edited, and approved the final manuscript.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alexander J. Werth.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The authors that they have no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Werth, A.J., Allchin, D. How we Think About Human Nature: Cognitive Errors and Concrete Remedies. Found Sci 26, 825–846 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-020-09726-5

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-020-09726-5

Keywords

Navigation