Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-dfsvx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-25T09:46:06.381Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Scientific Realism in the Wild: An Empirical Study of Seven Sciences and History and Philosophy of Science

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

We report the results of a study that investigated the views of researchers working in seven scientific disciplines and in history and philosophy of science in regard to four hypothesized dimensions of scientific realism. Among other things, we found (i) that natural scientists tended to express more strongly realist views than social scientists, (ii) that history and philosophy of science scholars tended to express more antirealist views than natural scientists, (iii) that van Fraassen’s characterization of scientific realism failed to cluster with more standard characterizations, and (iv) that those who endorsed the pessimistic induction were no more or less likely to endorse antirealism.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

We would like to thank audience members at the 2018 Buffalo Annual Experimental Philosophy Conference and the 2018 meeting of the Central States Philosophical Association, Huginn Thorsteinsson, and three anonymous reviewers from Philosophy of Science for helpful feedback on this project. All data and materials from this project are available at https://osf.io/cevsr.

References

Alspector-Kelly, Marc. 2001. “Should the Empiricist Be a Constructive Empiricist?Philosophy of Science 68:413–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bird, Alexander. 2007. “What Is Scientific Progress?Noûs 41:6489.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bueno, Otavio. 1999. “Empiricism, Conservativeness, and Quasi-Truth.” Philosophy of Science 66:S474S485.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cartwright, Nancy. 1983. How the Laws of Physics Lie. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cartwright, Nancy. 2007. “Why Be Hanged for Even a Lamb?” In Images of Empiricism: Essays on Science and Stances, ed. Monton, Bradley, 3245. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cattell, Raymond B. 1966. “The Scree Test for the Number of Factors.” Multivariate Behavioral Research 1:245–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chakravartty, Anjan. 2007. A Metaphysics for Scientific Realism: Knowing the Unobservable. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, Paul M. 1985. “The Ontological Status of Observables: In Praise of the Superempirical Virtues.” In Images of Science: Essays on Realism and Empiricism with a Reply from Bas C. van Fraassen, ed. Churchland, Paul M. and Hooker, Clifford A., 3547. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Dellsén, Finnur. 2016. “Scientific Progress: Knowledge versus Understanding.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 56:7283.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dellsén, Finnur. 2017. “Reconstructed Empiricism.” Acta Analytica 32:95113.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dicken, Paul. 2010. Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dicken, Paul, and Lipton, Peter. 2006. “What Can Bas Believe? Musgrave and van Fraassen on Observability.” Analysis 66:226–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Egg, Matthias. 2016. “Expanding Our Grasp: Causal Knowledge and the Problem of Unconceived Alternatives.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 67:115–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elliot-Graves, Alkistis, and Weisberg, Michael. 2014. “Idealization.” Philosophy Compass 9:176–85.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Forrest, Peter. 1994. “Why Most of Us Should Be Scientific Realists: A Reply to Van Fraassen.” Monist 77:4770.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frost-Arnold, Greg. 2014. “Can the Pessimistic Induction Be Saved from Semantic Anti-realism about Scientific Theory?British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 65:521–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hacking, Ian. 1983. Representing and Intervening: Introductory Topics in the Philosophy of Natural Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hawking, Stephen, and Mlodinow, Leonard. 2010. The Grand Design. New York: Bantam.Google Scholar
Hesse, Mary. 1976. “Truth and the Growth of Scientific Knowledge.” In PSA 1976: Proceedings of the 1976 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, Vol. 2, ed. Suppes, Patrick and Asquith, Peter D., 261–80. East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association.Google Scholar
Horwich, Paul. 1991. “On the Nature and Norms of Theoretical Commitment.” Philosophy of Science 58:114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hutcheson, Graeme, and Sofroniou, Nick. 1999. The Multivariate Social Scientist. London: Sage.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Iemhoff, Rosalie. 2013. “Intuitionism in the Philosophy of Mathematics.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Zalta, Edward N. Stanford, CA: Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/intuitionism/.Google Scholar
Jones, Ward. 2003. “Is Scientific Theory-Commitment Doxastic or Practical?Synthese 137:325–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kaiser, Henry F. 1960. “The Application of Electronic Computers to Factor Analysis.” Educational and Psychological Measurement 20:141–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. 1970. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Ladyman, James. 2000. “What’s Really Wrong with Constructive Empiricism? Van Fraassen and the Metaphysics of Modality.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 51:837–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laudan, Larry. 1977. Progress and Its Problems: Toward a Theory of Scientific Growth. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Laudan, Larry. 1981a. “A Confutation of Convergent Realism.” Philosophy of Science 48:1949.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laudan, Larry. 1981b. “A Problem-Solving Approach to Scientific Progress.” In Scientific Revolutions, ed. Hacking, Ian, 144–55. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lyons, Timothy D. 2005. “Toward a Purely Axiological Scientific Realism.” Erkenntnis 63:167204.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Muller, F. A. 2004. “Can a Constructive Empiricist Adopt the Concept of Observability?Philosophy of Science 71:8097.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Musgrave, Alan. 1985. “Realism versus Constructive Empiricism.” In Images of Science: Essays on Realism and Empiricism with a Reply from Bas C. van Fraassen, ed. Churchland, Paul M. and Hooker, Clifford A., 197221. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Musgrave, Alan. 1988. “The Ultimate Argument for Scientific Realism.” In Relativism and Realism in Science, ed. Nola, Robert, 229–52. Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
Niiniluoto, Ilkka. 2014. “Scientific Progress as Increasing Verisimilitude.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 46:7377.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Niiniluoto, Ilkka. 2017. “Optimistic Realism about Scientific Progress.” Synthese 194:3291–309.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O’Connor, Brian P. 2000. “SPSS and SAS Programs for Determining the Number of Components Using Parallel Analysis and Velicer’s MAP Test.” Behavior Research Methods, Instrumentation, and Computers 32:396402.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pearson, Karl. 1911. The Grammar of Science. 3rd ed. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Poincaré, Henri 1905/1952. Science and Hypothesis. Repr. New York: Dover.Google Scholar
Psillos, Stathis. 1996. “On van Fraassen’s Critique of Abductive Reasoning.” Philosophical Quarterly 46:3147.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Psillos, Stathis. 1999. Scientific Realism: How Science Tracks Truth. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Putnam, Hilary. 1975. “What Is Mathematical Truth?” In Mathematics, Matter and Method: Philosophical Papers, 1:6078. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Robinson, Brian, Gonnerman, Chad, and O’Rourke, Michael. 2019. “Experimental Philosophy of Science and Philosophical Differences across the Sciences.” Philosophy of Science 86 (3): 551–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosen, Gideon. 1994. “What Is Constructive Empiricism?Philosophical Studies 74:143–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roush, Sherrilyn. 2010. “Optimism about the Pessimistic Induction.” In New Waves in Philosophy of Science, ed. Magnus, P. D. and Busch, Jacob, 2958. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rowbottom, Darrell P. 2011. “The Instrumentalist’s New Clothes.” Philosophy of Science 78:12001211.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rowbottom, Darrell P. 2019. The Instrument of Science. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schlick, Moritz. 1936. “Meaning and Verification.” Philosophical Review 45:339–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smart, J. J. C. 1963. Philosophy and Scientific Realism. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Stanford, P. Kyle. 2006. Exceeding Our Grasp: Science, History, and the Problem of Unconceived Alternatives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Teller, Paul. 2001. “Whither Constructive Empiricism?Philosophical Studies 106:123–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Fraassen, Bas C. 1980. The Scientific Image. Oxford: Clarendon.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Fraassen, Bas C. 1985. “Empiricism in the Philosophy of Science.” In Images of Science: Essays on Realism and Empiricism with a Reply from Bas C. van Fraassen, ed. Churchland, Paul M. and Hooker, Clifford A., 245308. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, Bas C. 1994. “Gideon Rosen on Constructive Empiricism.” Philosophical Studies 74:179–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Fraassen, Bas C. 2001. “Constructive Empiricism Now.” Philosophical Studies 106:151–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Fraassen, Bas C. 2007. “From a View of Science to a New Empiricism.” In Images of Empiricism: Essays on Science and Stances, with a Reply from Bas C. van Fraassen, ed. Monton, Bradley, 337–84. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, Bas C. 2017. “Misdirection and Misconception in the Scientific Realism Debates.” In Varieties of Scientific Realism, ed. Agazzi, Evandro, 95108. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Worrall, John. 1989. “Structural Realism: The Best of Both Worlds.” Dialectica 43:99124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Worrall, John. 1994. “How to Remain (Reasonably) Optimistic: Scientific Realism and the ‘Luminiferous Ether.’” In PSA 1994: Proceedings of the 1994 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, Vol. 1, ed. Burian, Richard M., Hull, David, and Forbes, Mickey, 334–42. East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association.Google Scholar
Wray, K. Brad. 2007. “A Selectionist Explanation for the Success and Failures of Science.” Erkenntnis 67:8189.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wray, K. Brad. 2008. “The Argument from Underconsideration as Grounds for Anti-realism: A Defense.” International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 22:317–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wray, K. Brad. 2010. “Selection and Predictive Success.” Erkenntnis 72:365–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar