Skip to main content
Log in

Committing Crimes with BCIs: How Brain-Computer Interface Users can Satisfy Actus Reus and be Criminally Responsible

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Neuroethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Brain-computer interfaces allow agents to control computers without moving their bodies. The agents imagine certain things and the brain-computer interfaces read the concomitant neural activity and operate the computer accordingly. But the use of brain-computer interfaces is problematic for criminal law, which requires that someone can only be found criminally responsible if they have satisfied the actus reus requirement: that the agent has performed some (suitably specified) conduct. Agents who affect the world using brain-computer interfaces do not obviously perform any conduct, so when they commit crimes using brain-computer interfaces it is unclear how they have satisfied actus reus. Drawing on a forthcoming paper by Allan McCay, I suggest three potential accounts of the conduct that satisfies actus reus: the agent’s neural firings, his mental states, and the electronic activity in his brain-computer interface. I then present two accounts which determine how actus reus may be satisfied – one a counterfactual and the other a minimal sufficiency account. These accounts are lent plausibility because they are analogous to the but-for and NESS (Necessary Element in a Sufficient Set) tests for causation which are generally accepted tests for causation in legal theory. I argue that due to the determinations of these accounts and considerations regarding the relationship between the mind and brain, actus reus is satisfied by either the agent’s neural activity or brain-computer interface electrical activity. Which of these satisfies actus reus is determined by how well the brain-computer interface is functionally integrated with the agent.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Although for a cautionary note about speculating too far ahead see [15].

  2. There may be an analogous problem in civil law criminal systems, but I will not engage directly with these systems here. For a discussion of the similarities of criminal law in common law and civil law jurisdictions see [17].

  3. “Intentionally” may be substitutable for “purposely”, although the former term is laden with theoretical baggage, so I discuss only purposeful action.

  4. For more on mental actions see [32].

  5. It is at least not one of the agent’s direct actions, which seem to be the ones relevant for actus reus. For discussion of direct and indirect actions see [33].

  6. For some recent examinations of BCIs and agency, albeit in a different form of BCIs, see [34,35,36,37]. For an assessment of actions performed through the use of BCIs see Steinert et al. [2].

  7. Strictly this may be a state of affairs, not an event, but these sorts of conditions must plausibly be included within minimally sufficient sets.

  8. For various problems for the NESS test see [41].

  9. Although given these stipulations, this event may not be a crime because White would lack mens rea.

  10. This may be considered analogous to the search for a proximal cause when determining causation in legal theory. See [41].

  11. For a study which supports Libet’s finding see [49] Although for one criticism (of many) of Libet’s experiments see [50].

References

  1. Gerven, M.v., et al. 2009. The brain–computer interface cycle. Journal of Neural Engineering. 6: 1–10.

  2. Steinert, S., et al. 2018. Doing things with thoughts: Brain-computer interfaces and disembodied agency. Philosophy & Technology.: 1–26.

  3. Abbott, M.N., and S.L. Peck. 2017. Emerging ethical issues related to the use of brain-computer interfaces for patients with Total locked-in syndrome. Neuroethics. 10 (2): 235–242.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Phillips, L.H. 2006. Communicating with the “locked-in” patient: Because you can do it, should you? Neurology. 67 (3): 380–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Clausen, J. 2009. Man, machine and in between. Nature. 457: 1080–1081.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Clausen, J. 2013. Bonding brains to machines: Ethical implications of Electroceuticals for the human brain. Neuroethics. 6 (3): 429–434.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Hochberg, L.R., and K.D. Anderson. 2012. In BCI users and their needs, in Brain-Computer Interfaces: Principles and Practice, ed. J. Wolpaw and E.W. Wolpaw. Oxford University Press.

  8. Clausen, J. 2008. Moving minds: Ethical aspects of neural motor prostheses. Biotechnology Journal 3 (12): 1493–1501.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Clausen, J. 2011. Conceptual and ethical issues with brain–hardware interfaces. Current Opinion in Psychiatry 24 (6): 495–501.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Clausen, J., E. Fetz, J. Donoghue, J. Ushiba, U. Spörhase, J. Chandler, N. Birbaumer, and S.R. Soekadar. 2017. Help, hope, and hype: Ethical dimensions of neuroprosthetics. Science. 356 (6345): 1338–1339.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Jebari, K. 2013. Brain machine Interface and human enhancement – An ethical review. Neuroethics. 6 (3): 617–625.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Vlek, R.J., D. Steines, D. Szibbo, A. Kübler, M.J. Schneider, P. Haselager, and F. Nijboer. 2012. Ethical issues in brain–computer Interface research, development, and dissemination. Journal of Neurologic Physical Therapy. 36 (2): 94–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Schermer, M. 2009. The mind and the machine. On the conceptual and moral implications of brain-machine interaction. NanoEthics. 3 (3): 217–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Gurney, D. 2018. Killer robot arms: A case-study in brain–computer interfaces and intentional acts. Minds and Machines. 28 (4): 775–785.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Gilbert, F., and E. Goddard. 2014. Thinking ahead too much: Speculative ethics and implantable brain devices. AJOB Neuroscience. 5 (1): 49–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. McCay, A. 2019. Neurobionic revenge porn and the criminal law: Brain-computer interfaces and intimate image abuse. In Neuro-interventions and the law: Regulating human mental capacity, eds. N. Vincent, T. Nadelhoffer, and A. McCay. New York: Oxford University Press.

  17. Hermida, J. 2006. Convergence of civil law and common law in the criminal theory realm. University of Miami International and Comparative Law Review. 13 (1): 163–232.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Holm, S., and T.C. Voo. 2010. Brain-machine interfaces and personal responsibility for action – Maybe not as complicated after all. Studies in Ethics, Law, and Technology. 4: 3): 1–3): 6.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Grübler, G. 2011. Beyond the responsibility gap. Discussion note on responsibility and liability in the use of brain-computer interfaces. AI & Society. 26: 377–382.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Matthias, A. 2004. The responsibility gap: Ascribing responsibility for the actions of learning automata. Ethics and Information Technology. 6 (3): 175–183.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. O'Brolchain, F. and B. Gordijn. 2014. Brain–computer interfaces and user responsibility, in Brain-computer-interfaces in their ethical, social and cultural contexts, G. Grübler and E. Hildt, Editors. Springer.

  22. Tamburrini, G. 2009. Brain to computer communication: Ethical perspectives on interaction models. Neuroethics. 2 (3): 137–149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Warwick, K. 2010. Future issues with robots and cyborgs. Studies in Ethics, Law, and Technology. 4: 3): 1–3):18.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Wolkenstein, A., R.J. Jox, and O. Friedrich. 2018. Brain–computer interfaces: Lessons to be learned from the ethics of algorithms. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics. 27(Special Issue 4: 635–646.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. The Crimes Amendment (Intimate Images) Act 2017 (NSW): S91N, S91Q.

  26. Wasserstrom, R.A. 1960. Strict liability in the criminal law. Stanford Law Review. 12 (4): 731–745.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Cornell Law School. Mens Rea. Available from: https://www.law.cornell.edu/wex/mens_rea. Accessed 15 Dec 2018.

  28. American Law Institute. 1962. Model Penal Code. Philadelphia.

  29. Glannon, W. 2016. Ethical issues in neuroprosthetics. Journal of Neural Engineering. 13 (2): 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Cornell Law School. Actus Reus. Available from: https://www.law.cornell.edu/wex/actus_reus. Accessed 20 May 2018.

  31. Crimes Act 1900 (NSW): S310J.

  32. Levy, Y. 2016. Action Unified. The Philosophical Quarterly 66 (262): 65–83.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Davidson, D., Essays on actions and events. 1980: Oxford University Press.

  34. Gilbert, F. 2015. A threat to autonomy? The intrusion of predictive brain implants. AJOB Neuroscience. 6 (4): 4–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. Gilbert, F., and M. Cook. 2015. Are predictive brain implants an indispensable feature of autonomy? Bioethica Forum. 8 (4): 121–127.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Gilbert, F., et al. 2017. Embodiment and estrangement: Results from a first-in-human “intelligent BCI” trial. Science and Engineering Ethics.: 1–14.

  37. Haselager, P. 2013. Did I do that? Brain–computer interfacing and the sense of agency. Minds and Machines. 23 (3): 405–418.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. Lewis, D. 1973. Causation. The Journal of Philosophy 70 (17): 556–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  39. Lewis, D., Counterfactuals. 1973, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

  40. Calabresi, G. 1975. Concerning cause and the law of torts: An essay for Harry Kalven, Jr. The University of Chicago Law Review 43 (1): 69–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  41. Moore, M.S., Causation and responsibility: An essay in law, morals, and metaphysics. 2009: Oxford University Press.

  42. Wright, R.W. 1985. Causation in tort law. California Law Review. 73 (6): 1735–1828.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  43. Hart, H.L.A., and T. Honoré. 1985. Causation in the law. 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  44. Paul, L.A., and N. Hall. 2013. Causation: A User's guide. Oxford University Press.

  45. Wright, R.W. 2011. The NESS account of natural causation: A response to criticisms, in Perspectives on Causation, R. Goldberg, editor. Bloomsbury Publishing.

  46. Searle, J.R. 1983. Intentionality: An essay in the philosopy of mind. Cambridge University Press.

  47. Libet, B., et al. 1983. Time of conscious intention to act in relation to onset of cerebral activity (readiness-potential): The unconscious initiation of a freely voluntary act. Brain. 106 (3): 623–642.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  48. Libet, B. 1985. Unconscious cerebral initiative and the role of conscious will in voluntary action. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 8 (4): 529–539.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  49. Haggard, P., and M. Eimer. 1999. On the relation between brain potentials and the awareness of voluntary movements. Experimental Brain Research. 126 (1): 128–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  50. Roskies, A.L. 2011. Why Libet's studies Don't pose a threat to free will, in Conscious will and responsibility, W. Sinnott-Armstrong and L. Nadel, Editors. Oxford University Press. 11–22.

  51. Todd, G., J.L. Taylor, J.E. Butler, P.G. Martin, R.B. Gorman, and S.C. Gandevia. 2007. Use of motor cortex stimulation to measure simultaneously the changes in dynamic muscle properties and voluntary activation in human muscles. Journal of Applied Physiology 102 (5): 1756–1766.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Frederic Gilbert, Marianne McAllister, Allan McCay, Neil Levy, Lewis Phaceas, Oliver Rawle, Amanda Thompson, and Nicole Vincent.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kramer Thompson.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest

I have received assistance on this work from two individuals associated with Neuroethics: Neil Levy and Nicole Vincent. This work was produced without financial assistance.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Thompson, K. Committing Crimes with BCIs: How Brain-Computer Interface Users can Satisfy Actus Reus and be Criminally Responsible. Neuroethics 14 (Suppl 3), 311–322 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-019-09416-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-019-09416-5

Keywords

Navigation