Skip to main content
Log in

Respect, Punishment and Mandatory Neurointerventions

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Neuroethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The view that acting morally is ultimately a question of treating others with respect has had a profound influence on moral and legal philosophy. Not surprisingly, then, some scholars forcefully argue that the modes of punishment that the states mete out to offenders should not be disrespectful, and, furthermore, it has been argued that obliging offenders to receive neurological treatment is incompatible with showing them their due respect. In this paper, I examine three contemporary accounts of what showing respect for offenders in our sentencing practices would amount to: that it involves not interfering with offenders’ capacities for rationality and autonomy, that it should not undermine offenders’ prospect of reform, and that it amounts to treating offenders as if opaque. I then critically discuss whether any of these accounts plausibly imply that mandating neurointerventions to some offenders is necessarily morally wrong. I argue that they do not.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I understand mandatory neurointerventions as interventions mandated by the state as, or as part of, a criminal sanction that exerts their effect(s) directly on the recipient’s brain.

  2. As might be clear, I am going to assume that respect-constraints on punishment should be understood to also apply to non-punitive measures, such as rehabilitative measures, that a state may pursue in the name of criminal justice. This seems to me a plausible assumption. At least, I cannot think of a nonarbitrary reason as to why this should not be the case. But if the reader disagrees, she could simply take what follows to be a conditional discussion. That is, a discussion of what would follow in regard to the permissibility of mandating neurointerventions if non-punitive measures should be constrained by the same consideration of respect as punitive measures.

  3. Recognition respect is contrasted by Darwall [21] with appraisal respect. This latter form of respect is an attitude we might have towards some persons, but not others, based on whether they show great skill as, for instance, a musician or have a strong character, and which, as such, does not ground general constraints on how members of a certain group should be treated. Furthermore, this kind of respect can be granted to a greater or lesser extent to an individual, as well as be lost or retracted if the individual fails to live up to some respect-giving standard of action or behaviour [20].

  4. For similar interpretations of Kleinig as defending capacity-based respect constraint on punishments, see e.g. ([24] p. 186–187) and ([25], p. 117).

  5. For the present purposes, we need not scrutinise further whether this is indeed a plausible approach to identifying disrespectful and thus morally wrong kinds of punishment, but for some persuasive arguments that it is not, see, for example, [25].

  6. Jesper Ryberg [27, chapter 3] has provided a similar argument in regard to the concern that neurointerventions would necessarily have an effect on offenders’ capacity for mental control.

  7. For this view see, for example, [34].

  8. At least this seem to be true if: (1) there is no afterlife, and (2) the offender has not already been reformed prior to him being killed by the state.

  9. It is worth noting that strictly speaking arguing in either of these manners seems to imply that the central issue regarding violations of the opacity constraint is whether a given offender consents to information about his mental capacities being employed by the courts and not whether the neurointervention is mandated by a court. To put it differently, it is conceivable that some offenders will consent to courts using and acting on their psychological information while others will not. And so, in the former cases no violation of the opacity constraint will have taken place if the state obliges an offender to receive a neurointervention, while a violation of the constraint would take place if the same was to happen to the latter group of offenders. What this shows is that the opacity constraint might in fact not rule out the use of mandatory neurointerventions per se, but rather the imposition of involuntary neurointerventions. I will, however, not pursue this issue further here.

  10. An interesting objection that I will not discuss at length here as it would take us too far astray, is that because the offender has refused to let the state act on information about his psychological history to avoid harming him, he is himself (at least partly) responsible for the harm that befalls him when he, for instance, develops PTSD or relapses into depression. Thus, the state would do no wrong if a punishment was harmful in the relevant sense.

  11. One interesting way one could do so may, for example, be to explore further whether respect requires that modes of punishment do not pose a symbolic threat to offenders’ agency, and whether such a constraint is violated by mandatory neurointerventions (see e.g. [41]).

References

  1. del Busto, Elena, and Michael C. Harlow. 2011. American sexual offender castration treatment and legislation. In International perspectives on the assessment and treatment of sexual offenders: Theory, practice, and research, ed. Douglas P. Boer, Reinhard Eher, Leam A. Craig, Michael H. Miner, and Friedemann Pfäfflin, 543–571. UK: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  2. Hough, Mike, Anna Clancy, Tim McSweeney, and Paul J. Turnbull. 2003. The impact of drug treatment and testing orders on offending: Two-year reconviction results. London: The Home Office, Research, Development and Statistics Directorate.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Chew, Christopher, Thomas Douglas, and Nadira S. Faber. 2018. Biological interventions for crime prevention. In Treatment for crime: Philosophical essays on neurointerventions in criminal justice, ed. David Birks and Thomas Douglas. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Berman, Mitchell E., Michael S. McCloskey, Jennifer R. Fanning, Julie A. Schumacher, and Emil F. Coccaro. 2009. Serotonin augmentation reduces response to attack in aggressive individuals. Psychological Science 20: 714–720.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Duke, Aaron A., Laurent Bègue, Rob Bell, and Tory Eisenlohr-Moul. 2013. Revisiting the serotonin-agression relation in humans: a meta-analysis. Psychological Bulletin 139: 1148–1172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Young, L., J.A. Camprodon, M. Hauser, A. Pascual-Leone, and R. Saxe. 2010. Disruption of the right temporoparietal junction with transcranial magnetic stimulation reduces the role of beliefs in moral judgments. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 107: 6753–6758. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.0914826107.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Tassy, Sébastien, Olivier Oullier, Yann Duclos, Olivier Coulon, Julien Mancini, Christine Deruelle, Sharam Attarian, Olivier Felician, and Bruno Wicker. 2012. Disrupting the right prefrontal cortex alters moral judgement. Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience 7: 282–288. https://doi.org/10.1093/scan/nsr008.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Dambacher, Franziska, Teresa Schuhmann, Jill Lobbestael, Arnoud Arntz, Suzanne Brugman, and Alexander T. Sack. 2015. Reducing proactive aggression through non-invasive brain stimulation. Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience 10: 1303–1309. https://doi.org/10.1093/scan/nsv018.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Molero-Chamizo, Andrés, Raquel Martín Riquel, Juan Antonio Moriana, Michael A. Nitsche, and Guadalupe N. Rivera-Urbina. 2019. Bilateral prefrontal cortex anodal tDCS effects on self-reported aggressiveness in imprisoned violent offenders. Neuroscience 397: 31–40. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neuroscience.2018.11.018.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Lu, Lin, Xi Wang, and Thomas R. Kosten. 2009. Stereotactic neurosurgical treatment of drug addiction. The American Journal of Drug and Alcohol Abuse 35: 391–393. https://doi.org/10.3109/00952990903312478.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Newton, Alexander, Xennor May, Steven Eames, and Maryam Ahmad. 2019. Economic and social costs of reoffending. Ministry of Justice.

  12. Douglas, Thomas. 2014. Criminal rehabilitation through medical intervention: moral liability and the right to bodily integrity. The Journal of Ethics 18: 101–122. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10892-014-9161-6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Shaw, Elizabeth. 2019. The Right to Bodily Integrity and the Rehabilitation of Offenders Through Medical Interventions: A Reply to Thomas Douglas. Neuroethics 12: 97–106. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-016-9277-4.

  14. Douglas, Thomas. 2019. Nonconsensual Neurocorrectives and bodily integrity: a reply to Shaw and Barn. Neuroethics 12: 107–118. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-016-9275-6.

  15. Bublitz, Jan Christoph, and Reinhard Merkel. 2014. Crimes against minds: on mental manipulations, harms and a human right to mental self-determination. Criminal Law and Philosophy 8: 51–77. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-012-9172-y.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Craig, Jared N. 2016. Incarceration, direct brain intervention, and the right to mental integrity – a reply to Thomas Douglas. Neuroethics 9: 107–118. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-016-9255-x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Petersen, Thomas Søbirk, and Kristian Kragh. 2017. Should violent offenders be forced to undergo neurotechnological treatment? A critical discussion of the “freedom of thought” objection. Journal of Medical Ethics 43: 1–5. https://doi.org/10.1136/medethics-2016-103492.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Dillon, Robin S. 2018. Respect. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9973.00225, 33, 210, 228.

  19. Kant, Immanuel. 2019. Groundwork of the metaphysics of morals. Compass Circle.

  20. Woodruff, Paul Bestor. 2019. Respect. In International Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. Hugh LaFollette. John Wiley & Sons, Ltd.

  21. Darwall, L., and Stephen. 1977. Two kinds of respect. Ethics 88: 36–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Hill, E., and Thomas. 2000. Respect, pluralism, and justice - Kantian perspectives. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  23. Kleinig, John. 1998. The hardness of hard treatment. In Fundamentals of Sentencing Theory, ed. Andrew Ashworth and Martin Wasik. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Ryberg, Jesper. 2018. Neuroscientific treatment of criminals and penal theory. In Treatment for crime: Philosophical essays on neurointerventions in criminal justice, ed. David Birks and Thomas Douglas. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  25. Petersen, Thomas S. 2010. Punishment and dignity. In Punishment and ethics: New perspectives, ed. Jesper Ryberg and J. Angelo Corlett. Palgrave Macmillan.

  26. Lippke, Richard L. 1998. Arguing against inhumane and degrading punishment. Criminal Justice Ethics 17: 29–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Ryberg, Jesper. 2019. Neurointerventions, crime, and punishment: Ethical considerations. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  28. Schaefer, G. Owen, Guy Kahane, and Julian Savulescu. 2014. Autonomy and enhancement. Neuroethics 7: 123–136. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-013-9189-5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  29. Douglas, Thomas, Pieter Bonte, Farah Focquaert, Katrien Devolder, and Sigrid Sterckx. 2013. Coercion, incarceration, and chemical castration: an argument from autonomy. Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 10: 393–405. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11673-013-9465-4.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Ryberg, Jesper. 2012. Punishment, pharmacological treatment, and early release. International Journal of Applied Philosophy 26: 231–244. https://doi.org/10.5840/ijap201226217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Hoskins, Zachary. 2013. Punishment, contempt, and the prospect of moral reform. Criminal Justice Ethics 32: 1–18. https://doi.org/10.1080/0731129X.2013.777250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. Hampton, J. 1984. The moral education theory of punishment. Philosophy & Public Affairs 13: 208–238.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Kant, Immanuel. 1991. The metaphysics of morals. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  34. Duff, R.A. 2001. Punishment, communication and community. Oxford: Oxford University Press

  35. APA. 2013. Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders. Fifth edit. Arlington: American Psychiatric Association.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Young, S., D. Moss, O. Sedgwick, M. Fridman, and P. Hodgkins. 2015. A meta-analysis of the prevalence of attention deficit hyperactivity disorder in incarcerated populations. Psychological Medicine 45: 247–258. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0033291714000762.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  37. Ilieva, Irena P., and Martha J. Farah. 2013. Enhancement stimulants: perceived motivational and cognitive advantages. Frontiers in Neuroscience 7: 1–6. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnins.2013.00198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. Vrecko, Scott. 2013. Just how cognitive is “cognitive enhancement”? On the significance of emotions in university students’ experiences with study drugs. AJOB Neuroscience 4: 4–12. https://doi.org/10.1080/21507740.2012.740141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  39. Carter, Ian. 2011. Respect and the basis of equality. Ethics 121: 538–571.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  40. Bennett, Christopher. 2018. Intrusive intervention and opacity respect. In Treatment for crime: Philosophical essays on Neurointerventions in criminal justice, ed. David Birks and Thomas Douglas, 255–273. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Shaw, Elizabeth. 2018. Against the mandatory use of neurointerventions. In Treatment for crime: Philosophical essays on neurointerventions in criminal justice, ed. David Birks and Thomas Douglas. Oxford, United Kingdom: Open University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The author thanks Jesper Ryberg, Ditte Marie Munch-Jurisic, Thomas Søbirk Petersen, Frej Klem Thomsen, Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen, Sigri Gaïni, Elizabeth Ashford, Cecilia Vollmer, two anonymous reviewers and the editors of Neuroethics for their valuable comments on an earlier draft of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sebastian Jon Holmen.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Holmen, S.J. Respect, Punishment and Mandatory Neurointerventions. Neuroethics 14, 167–176 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-020-09434-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-020-09434-8

Keywords

Navigation