Skip to main content
Log in

Slippery Slope Arguments in Legal Contexts: Towards Argumentative Patterns

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Argumentation Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Addressing the slippery slope argument (SSA) in legal contexts from the perspective of pragma-dialectics, this paper elaborates the conditions under which an SSA-scheme instance is used reasonably (rather than fallaciously). We review SSA-instances in past legal decisions and analyze the basic legal SSA-scheme. By illustrating the institutional preconditions influencing the reasoning by which an SSA moves forward, we identify three sub-schemes (causal SSA, analogical SSA, and Sorites SSA). For each sub-scheme we propose critical questions, as well as four rules that clarify when the SSA scheme is used reasonably. The institutional preconditions make the analogical SSA expectable in common law contexts; the Sorites SSA is expectable in civil law contexts; whereas the causal SSA is common to both contexts. This result should inform future work on the identification of typical argumentative patterns for the SSA in legal contexts.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Saliger (2007, p. 342) states that SSAs “[…] belong to the class of practical consequence arguments.” Yet Walton (2015, p. 275) rightly observes that, although an SSA shares obvious characteristics with consequentialist argumentation, this does not explain the reasoning-mechanism leading from the “starting point” to the “end point” (i.e., how the initial state-of-affairs leads to an unacceptable final outcome). Walton (1996, p. 203) also mentions a connection between an SSA and the argumentum ad absurdum, a type of argument he considers to be based on the argument from consequences. Besides a negative form of the argumentum ad absurdum, the SSA also has a positive form if the outcome is desirable rather than catastrophic (Walton et al. 2008, p. 332).

  2. According to pragma-dialectical notation, ‘1’ marks the standpoint (or conclusion), while ‘1.1’, respectively ‘1.1.1’, mark the premises. The letters ‘a’ and ‘b’ identify a coordinative argument, whose premises are both necessary and, when taken together, can be sufficient for the standpoint; while in multiple arguments (e.g., 1.1, 1.2), the premises can be independently sufficient for the standpoint (Van Eemeren et al. 2002, pp. 69–70).

  3. As Rescher puts it: “([e]ven in reasoning) a chain is no stronger than its weakest link. Non fortiter catena quam anulus debilissimus. This too is true in the rational as in the physical realm. The idea was operative in the principle of Theophrastus in relation to modal syllogisms: Peiorem sequitur semper conclusio partem. The conclusion always follows the weaker part, not only the weaker in point of modality, but also the weaker in quality and quantity” (Rescher 2010, p. 133; capitalization removed).

  4. The available empirical data from the Netherlands only show that both assisted suicide and voluntary euthanasia are relatively uncommon, but there is no support from this data for a direct and inevitable causal relation between both praxes. According to studies from 1990, 1995, and 2001 on medical praxes that shorten life, assisted suicide is “relatively uncommon” in the Netherlands in these years, occurring in between 0.1% and 0.4% of all deaths, whereas voluntary euthanasia occurred in between 1.7 and 2.6% of all deaths (Weyers 2001).

  5. Texas v. Johnson, 1989, WL 65,231.U.S., 57 U.S.L.W.4770.

  6. 398 U.S., at 60, 90 S.Ct., at 1557, quoting 10 US.C.772(f).

  7. In Obergefell v. Hodges, 576 U.S. (2015), liberal proponents held that the right view on marriage can keep pace with the times, because “it has not stood in isolation from developments in law and society.” They viewed “the combination of love and responsibility” as the moral nature of marriage, and not the union of a heterosexual couple. Conservatives who endorse the gender restriction, by contrast, emphasize the social responsibilities of having and supporting children.

  8. In United States’ Griswold v. Connecticut (381 U.S.479, 1965) doctors had provided medical advice and prescriptions for contraception to married women, some of whom were charged, and convicted, because Connecticut state law prohibits using contraceptives. The relevant statute, however, did ascribe to a fertilized egg cell a legal personality, thus semantically conflating contraception and infanticide. The Federal Supreme Court overturned these verdicts and established the right to privacy in marriage.

  9. Under the literal rule, a judge must consider what a statute says, rather than what it might mean. The judge will thus assign to the statute a literal meaning (i.e., the ordinary everyday meaning), even if this interpretation results in what might be considered an otherwise unjust or undesirable outcome. The golden rule modifies the literal rule such that, if the literal rule results in an absurd interpretation, then the court should look for an alternative interpretation that avoids the absurdity. The mischief rule allows a judge to exercise yet further discretion, beyond what the literal or the golden rule allows. It requires of the court to consider what the law said before the focal statute was passed, to thus discover the gap, or mischief, that the statute was meant to cover. The court must then interpret the statute in a way that covers this gap. On the purposive approach, finally, the court does not only consider the gap in the old law, but bases the decision also on what the court interprets as the law-giving parliament’s intention (Slapper and Kelly 2011, p. 38).

References

  • Arras, John D. 1982. The right to die on the slippery slope. Social Theory and Practice 8 (3): 285–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barry, Vincent. 1976. Practical logic. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burton, Steven J. 1995. An Introduction to Law and Legal Reasoning, 2nd ed. New York: Aspen Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bowell, Tracy, and Gary Kemp. 2005. Critical thinking: A concise guide, 2nd ed. London and New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Corner, Adam, Ulrike Hahn, and Mike Oaksford. 2011. The psychological mechanism of the slippery slope argument. Journal of Memory and Language 64 (2): 133–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chemerinsky, Erwin. 2019. Constitutional law: Principles and policies, 6th ed. New York: Wolters Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dorfman, Grant. 2008. The founders’ legal case: No taxation without representation versus taxation no tyranny. Houston Law Review 44: 1377–1412.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eng, Svein. 2000. Fusion of descriptive and normative propositions: The concepts of descriptive proposition as concepts of degree. Ratio Juris 13: 236–260.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Endicott, Timothy. 2000. Vagueness in law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Feteris, Eveline T. 2002. A Pragma-dialectical approach of the analysis and evaluation of pragmatic argumentation in a legal context. Argumentation 16: 349–367.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feteris, Eveline T. 2017. Fundamentals of legal argumentation: A survey of theories on the justification of judicial decisions. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Groarke, Leo A., Christopher W. Tindale, and Linda Fisher. 2004. Good reasoning matters: A constructive approach to critical thinking, 3rd ed. Toronto and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Govier, Trudy. 2010. A practical study of argument, 7th ed. Belmont, CA: Cengage Learning.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, Patrick. 1982. A concise introduction to logic. Belmont: Wadsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holtug, Nils. 1993. Human gene therapy: Down the slippery slope? Bioethics 7 (5): 402–419.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hart, Herbert L. A. 2012. The concept of law, 3rd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Koppelman, Andrew. 1998. Same-sex marriage, choice of law, and public policy. Texas Law Review 76 (5): 921–1002.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lode, Eric. 1999. Slippery slope arguments and legal reasoning. California Law Review 87 (6): 1469–1543.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Launis, Veikko. 2002. Human gene therapy and the slippery slope argument. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 5 (2): 169–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, Penney. 2007. The empirical slippery slope from voluntary to non-voluntary euthanasia. Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 35 (1): 197–210.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mayo, David J. 1990. The role of slippery slope arguments in public policy debates. Philosophic Exchange 21 (1): 81–97.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, John. 2003. On liberty (Edited by David Bromwich and George Kateb). New Haven and London: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Resnik, David. 1994. Debunking the slippery slope argument against human germ-line gene therapy. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 19 (1): 23–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rizzo, Mario, and Douglas Whitman. 2003. The camel’s nose is in the tent: rules, theories, and slippery slopes. UCLA Law Review 51 (2): 540–591.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, Nicholas. 2010. On rules and principles: A philosophical study of their nature and function. Amsterdam: De Gruyter.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schauer, Frederick. 1985. Slippery slopes. Harvard Law Review 99 (2): 361–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schauer, Frederick. 2009. Thinking like a lawyer: A new introduction to legal reasoning. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, Stephen W. 2005. Evidence for the practical slippery slope in the debate on physician-assisted suicide and euthanasia. Medical Law Review 13: 17–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saliger, Frank. 2007. The dam burst and slippery slope argument in medical law and medical ethics. Zeitschrift fur Internationale Strafrechtsdogmatik 9: 341–352.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slapper, Gary, and David Kelly. 2011. Law: The basics. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Eemeren, Frans, and Rob Grootendorst. 1992. Argumentation, communication and fallacies: A pragma-dialectical perspective. New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Eemeren, Frans, Rob Grootendorst, and A. Francisca Snoeck. Henkemans. 2002. Argumentation, analysis, evaluation, presentation. New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Van Eemeren, Frans, and Rob Grootendorst. 2004. A systematic theory of argumentation: A pragma-dialectical approach. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Eemeren, Frans. 2017. Prototypical argumentative patterns: Exploring the relationship between argumentative discourse and institutional context. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Company.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Van Eemeren, Frans. 2018. Argumentation theory: A pragmatic-dialectical perspective. Cham: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Van der Burg, Wibren. 1991. The slippery slope argument. Ethics 102 (1): 42–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Volokh, Eugene. 2005. Same-sex marriage and slippery slopes. Hofstra Law Review 33 (4): 1155–1202.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woods, John. 2000. Slippery slope and collapsing taboos. Argumentation 14: 107–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weyers, Heleen. 2001. Euthanasia: The process of legal change in the Netherlands. In Regulating physician-negotiated death, ed. Albert Klijn, et al. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, Douglas. 1992. Slippery slope arguments. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, Douglas. 1996. Argument schemes for presumptive reasoning. Mahwah NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, Douglas, Chris Reed, and Fabrizio Macagno. 2008. Argument schemes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Walton, Douglas. 2015. The basic slippery slope argument. Informal Logic 35 (3): 273–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walton, Douglas. 2017. The slippery slope argument in the ethical debate on genetic engineering of humans. Science Engineering Ethics 23 (6): 1507–1528.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We thank two anonymous reviewers for this journal for very constructive comments that helped improve an earlier version of this manuscript. B.W. acknowledges funding from the Humanities and Social Sciences Youth Foundation of the Ministry of Education of China (No. 20YJC820044). F.Z. acknowledges the support of EU COST Action 17132 (APPLY, European Network for Argumentation and Public Policy Analysis).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Frank Zenker.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Wang, B., Zenker, F. Slippery Slope Arguments in Legal Contexts: Towards Argumentative Patterns. Argumentation 35, 581–601 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-020-09545-9

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-020-09545-9

Keywords

Navigation