Skip to main content
Log in

Similarities in axiomatizations: equal surplus division value and first-price auctions

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Review of Economic Design Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We compare axiomatizations between a value for cooperative games with transferable utilities (TU games), and a rule for auctions. The equal surplus division value on the set of zero-monotonic TU games is characterized by the following: individual rationality, Pareto efficiency, and equal effect of players’ nullification on others. Meanwhile, first-price auctions, on the general preference domain, are characterized by individual rationality, envy-freeness, and weak equal effect of buyers’ nullification on others. Here, envy-freeness implies Pareto efficiency in the model of auctions. Given the agents’ general preferences in the auction model, the characteristic of a weak equal effect of buyers’ nullification on others weakens the requirement of equal effect of players’ nullification on others. Although the two models are different, the corresponding axioms in both models require conditions corresponding to each other. In particular, individual rationality requires voluntary participation of agents, Pareto efficiency (or its stronger axiom of envy-freeness in the model of auctions) requires outcomes with no waste, and (weak) equal effect of players’ (buyers’) nullification on others requires equal treatment of agents when an agent is nullified. Therefore, in terms of axiomatizations, we can similarly interpret the equal surplus division value and first-price auctions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Buyers who do not obtain the item in an auction may still end up paying. A typical example is the payment of participation fee for auctions.

  2. See also Graham and Marshall (1987) for incentive aspects in their model.

  3. van den Brink (2007) also studies the same situation and characterizes the convex combination between the equal surplus division and equal division values. Further, Branzei et al. (2009) studies the relationships between the complete information auction games and peer group games.

  4. Yokote and Funaki (2017) consider only a case with greater than or equal to six players.

  5. An excellent survey on this property is given by Thomson (2016).

  6. The first-price auctions and the second-price auctions have been recently compared from a different viewpoint from axiomatizations (see Shimoji 2017).

  7. Peleg and Sudhölter (2003) call this condition weak superadditivity.

  8. Ferrières (2017) introduces an equivalent axiom to \(\hbox {EENO}_G\) in TU games.

  9. This weaker variation of \(\hbox {EENO}_G\) is introduced by Kongo (2019) to axiomatize the set of weighted surplus division values. Following Casajus (2017), who weaken the balanced contributions property of Myerson (1980) in this way, corresponding generalizations of existing axioms in TU games are well-investigated. For example, Casajus and Yokote (2017) weakens differential marginality in Casajus (2011), and Casajus (2018a) engages in symmetry. Furthermore, further generalizations of such axioms are discussed in Casajus (2018b) and Casajus (2019).

  10. From (P1), there exists \(WP(\succsim _i) \in {\mathbb {R}}\) such that \((0,0) \sim _i (1,WP(\succsim _i))\). Suppose that \(WP(\succsim _i)<0\). From (P2), there exists \(m_i \in (WP(\succsim _i), 0)\) such that \((1,WP(\succsim _i)) \succ _i (1, m_i) \). From (P3), \((1,0) \succsim _i (0,0)\). Therefore, we obtain \((1,0) \succ _i (1,m_i)\). But, this contradicts (P2) because \(0>m_i\).

  11. One possible way to apply this axiom to TU games is that \(\varphi _i(v)=\varphi _j(v)\) for any \(i,j \in N\) and any \(v \in V(N)\), which has a condition representing strict egalitarianism. This condition does not imply \(\hbox {PE}_G\) and, together with \(\hbox {PE}_G\), this condition clearly implies the equal division value \(\varphi ^e\).

  12. This rule is the same as that in Adachi and Kongo (2013).

  13. In Sakai (2008), this property is formalized as an axiom called non-imposition. Clearly, non-imposition is a weaker requirement than \(\hbox {IR}_A\).

  14. This lemma is the same as Lemma 1 in Adachi and Kongo (2013).

  15. The other case of \(a_i(\succsim '_j,\succsim _{-j})=0\) and \(a_j(\succsim '_j,\succsim _{-j})=1\) can be shown by replacing i and j.

References

  • Adachi T (2014) Equity and the Vickrey allocation rule on general preference domain. Soc Choice Welf 42:508–518

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Adachi T, Kongo T (2013) First-price auctions on general preference domains: axiomatic characterizations. Econ Theory Bull 1:93–103

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ashlagi I, Serizawa S (2012) Characterizing Vickrey allocation rule by anonymity. Soc Choice Welf 38:531–542

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Béal S, Rémila E, Solal P (2015) Preserving or removing special players: What keeps your payoff unchanged in TU-games? Math Soc Sci 73:23–31

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Branzei R, Fragnelli V, Meca A, Tijs S (2009) On cooperative games related to market situations and auctions. Int Game Theory Rev 11:459–470

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Casajus A (2011) Differential marginality, van den Brink fairness, and the Shapley value. Theory Decis 71:163–174

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Casajus A (2017) Weakly balanced contributions and solutions for cooperative games. Oper Res Lett 45:616–619

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Casajus A (2018a) Sign symmetry vs symmetry: Young’s characterization of the Shapley value revisited. Econ Lett 169:59–62

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Casajus A (2018b) Symmetry, mutual dependence, and the weighted Shapley values. J Econ Theory 178:105–123

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Casajus A (2019) Relaxations of symmetry and the weighted Shapley values. Econ Lett 176:75–78

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Casajus A, Huettner F (2014) Null, nullifying, or dummifying players: the difference between the Shapley value, the equal division value, and the equal surplus division value. Econ Lett 122:167–169

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Casajus A, Yokote K (2017) Weak differential marginality and the Shapley value. J Econ Theory 167:274–284

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chew SH, Serizawa S (2007) Characterizing the Vickrey combinatorial auction by induction. Econ Theory 33:393–406

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chun Y, Park B (2012) Population solidarity, population fair-ranking, and the egalitarian value. Int J Game Theory 41:255–270

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clarke E (1971) Multi-part pricing of public goods. Public Choice 11:17–33

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Driessen T, Funaki Y (1991) Coincidence of and collinearity between game theoretic solutions. OR Spektrum 13:15–30

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferrières S (2017) Nullified equal loss property and equal division values. Theory Decis 83:385–406

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foley D (1967) Resource allocation and the public sector. Yale Econ Essays 7:45–98

    Google Scholar 

  • Graham D, Marshall R (1987) Collusive behavior at single-object second-price and English auctions. J Pol Econ 95:1217–1239

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Graham DA, Marshall RC, Richard JF (1990) Differential payments within a bidder coalition and the Shapley value. Am Econ Rev 80:493–510

    Google Scholar 

  • Groves T (1973) Incentives in teams. Econometrica 45:617–631

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holmstrom B (1979) Grove’s scheme on restricted domains. Econometrica 47:1137–1144

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hu XF (2019) Coalitional surplus desirability and the equal surplus division value. Econ Lett 179:1–4

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ju Y, Wettstein D (2009) Implementing cooperative solution concepts: A generalized bidding approach. Econ Theory 39:307–330

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kongo T (2018) Effects of players’ nullification and equal (surplus) division values. Int Game Theory Rev 20(01):1750029

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kongo T (2019) Players’ nullification and the weighted (surplus) division values. Econ Lett 183:108539

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Myerson RB (1980) Conference structures and fair allocation rules. Int J Game Theory 9:169–182

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peleg B, Sudhölter P (2003) Introduction to the Theory of Cooperative Games. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Saitoh H, Serizawa S (2008) Vickrey allocation rule with income effect. Econ Theory 35:391–401

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sakai T (2008) Second price auctions on general preference domains: two characterizations. Econ Theory 37:347–356

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sakai T (2013) An equity characterization of second price auctions when preferences may not be quasilinear. Rev Econ Des 17:17–26

    Google Scholar 

  • Satterthwaite MA, Sonnenschein H (1981) Strategy-proof allocation mechanisms at differentiable points. Rev Econ Stud 48:587–597

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapley LS (1953) A value for \(n\)-person games. In: Kuhn H, Tucker A (eds) Contributions to the theory of games II. Princeton University Press, Princeton, pp 307–317

    Google Scholar 

  • Shimoji M (2017) Revenue comparison of discrete private-value auctions via weak dominance. Rev Econ Des 21:231–252

  • Sjostrom T (1991) A new characterization of the Groves-Clarke mechanism. Econ Lett 36:263–267

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Svensson LG (1983) Large indivisibles: an analysis with respect to price equilibrium and fairness. Econometrica 51:939–954

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomson W (2016) Non-bossiness. Soc Choice Welf 47:665–696

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van den Brink R (2007) Null or nullifying players: the difference between the Shapley value and equal division solutions. J Econ Theory 136:767–775

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van den Brink R, Funaki Y (2009) Axiomatization of a class of equal surplus sharing solutions for TU-games. Theory Decis 67:303–340

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vickrey W (1961) Counterspeculation, auctions, and competitive sealed tenders. J Finance 16:8–37

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yokote K, Funaki Y (2017) Monotonicity implies linearity: characterizations of convex combinations of solutions to cooperative games. Soc Choice Welf 49:171–203

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The author is grateful to the editor and an anonymous referee for their comments that assisted in improving this manuscript. This study was funded by JSPS KAKENHI (grant number 19K01569).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Takumi Kongo.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kongo, T. Similarities in axiomatizations: equal surplus division value and first-price auctions. Rev Econ Design 24, 199–213 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10058-020-00233-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10058-020-00233-4

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation